23 on preventing another century of misunderstanding: toward a psychoethology of human experience...

Upload: maximiliano-portillo

Post on 27-Feb-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    1/17

    This article was downloaded by: [Gazi University]On: 19 August 2014, At: 08:08Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: MortimerHouse, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journalfor Psychoanalysis and the NeurosciencesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20

    On Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding:Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience anda Psychoneurology of Affect: Commentary by JaakPanksepp (Bowling Green, Ohio)Jaak Panksepp

    a

    aDepartment of Psychology, Bowling Green State University, Bowling Green, OH 43403,

    e-mail:

    Published online: 09 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article:Jaak Panksepp (2000) On Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethologyof Human Experience and a Psychoneurology of Affect: Commentary by Jaak Panksepp (Bowling Green, Ohio),

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journal for Psychoanalysis and the Neurosciences, 2:2, 240-255, DOI:

    10.1080/15294145.2000.10773315

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773315

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose ofthe Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be reliedupon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shallnot be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and otherliabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic

    reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773315http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773315http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773315http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20
  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    2/17

    240

    Most

    of

    our group were just tourists, peering at

    one culture from the capsule

    of

    another. Only Bob

    was prepared to live on the border. But he was full

    of

    ambivalence. Like the Zairean medical students, he

    did not much like Chinese society; for him it lacked

    warmth. At the same time he was deeply attracted to

    the tradition

    of

    Chinese medicine.

    So, although it is perhaps a scandal that the two

    aspects

    of

    psychology are distrustful of each other.

    Whittle is right, these are not jus t aspects, but self

    sufficient cultures. In Canada, for all our talk

    of

    multi

    culturalism, we have not yet managed to become com-

    Jaak Panksepp

    fortable with the fault-line that runs between the

    Anglos and the French, let alone with our many other

    cultural splits. Within psychology, we are not comfort

    able with our split, but perhaps by recognizing it as a

    cultural one, we psychologists can know that the move

    to make is toward multiculturalism.

    Keith Oatley

    Dept. of Human Development

    Applied Psychology

    OISE University

    of

    Toronto

    252 Bloor Street West

    Toronto Canada M5S

    V

    On Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience

    and

    a Psychoneurology

    of

    Affect

    Commentary by

    Jaak

    Panksepp (Bowling Green, Ohio)

    Whittle s gentle complaint provides fertile ground for

    sharing some of my own thoughts on this contentious

    topic the chasm between analytic-dissective and

    synthetic-integrative approaches to understanding the

    mind. I will take this opportunity to share what has

    been on my mind for the last 30 years rather frankly

    concerning our continuing failure to have a unified

    and coherent mind-brain-behavior science.

    The one thing all might agree on is that the exper

    imental psychology that emerged during the past cen

    tury has yet to give us a lasting and coherent science

    of

    the human or animal condition. In my estimation,

    this is largely due to the fact that it never really came

    to terms with the evolutionary dynamics and epige

    netic complexities

    of

    ancient regions of the mamma

    lian brain. All too often it skirted the most profound

    and central issues

    of

    our

    lives the

    clarification

    of

    the

    many internal impulses and feelings that guide the

    intentional actions and choices we routinely make

    each day. For quite a while, neuroscience has also

    followed that same pattern, pretending that the dy

    namic, evolutionarily provided integrative statesof the

    nervous system are of little importance for under

    standing what the brain does. In fact, the probability

    high that the brain generates a great deal of its

    magic not simply through information transmis-

    Jaak Panksepp is Distinguished Research Professor

    of

    Psychobiology,

    Emeritus, Department

    of

    Psychology, Bowling Green State University,

    Ohio.

    sion, but through massive, coordinated operationsof

    enormous ensembles of neurons that create global and

    organic neurodynamics (states of being) that constitute

    the forms

    of

    affective consciousness, not capable of

    being reproduced, so far as we know,

    on

    digital com

    puters. Those global, evolutionary dynamics are the

    fundamental fabric of mind, which comes to be richly

    embellished and besmirched by the vast complexities

    of individual experiences information that is more

    readily reproducible computationally.

    Psychoanalysis addressed many

    of

    these issues

    but all too rarely in ways that helped create a rigorous

    culture of consensual

    truth

    that is the hallmark of

    modern scientific thought (Macmillan, 1997). Experi

    mental psychology became a fledgling memberof the

    scientific community early in the twentieth century,

    not because of any coherent sc ientific insight and syn

    thesis it generated concerning the nature of mind or

    the natural behaviors organisms exhibit, but rather be

    cause of its willingness to implement generally ac

    cepted experimental and statistical methodologies in

    its search for lasting knowledge. Indeed, its analytic

    success during the twentieth century was largely based

    on

    barring

    the door to the darker affective corners of

    the mind and keeping its attention focused obsessively

    on those peppercorns of behavioral and cognitive evi

    dence that strict-minded experimentalists could agree

    upon. Both behaviorism and cognitivism agreed, at

    times all too explicitly, that emotions and other af

    fective processes were issues too murky or difficult to

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    3/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    understand. Psychoanalysis never chose those paths of

    psychic trivialization to create empirical consensus.

    Its reputation suffered accordingly.

    Considering the seemingly antithetical premises

    of experimental psychological and psychoanalytic ap

    proaches, as well as the more-apparent-than-real dual

    ities

    of

    the human brain-mind, the polarity between

    the two disciplines was inevitable but it need not be

    irreversible. However, a great deal of conceptual

    stitching, often through some remarkably tough intel

    lectual hides e.g., see Uttal, 2000), will be needed

    in order to mend the widening rift that has emerged

    Panksepp, 1999). This may be achieved more rapidly

    if

    we better recognize the degree to which our mind

    sciences are molded by personalities that are attracted

    to the stark positivistic aesthetics of various intellec

    tual--experimental schools, commonly well insulated

    from each other, that today continue to rule the aca

    demic landscape in cognitive science and neurosci

    ence. What may eventually coax investigators

    of

    vastly different persuasions to return to a shared intel

    lectual table is the increasingly evident fact that a com

    prehensive understanding

    of

    psychological and

    behavioral subtleties cannot be achieved simply by

    viewing them from a single vantage point, whether by

    positivistic behaviorism, cognitivism, functionalism,

    computationalism, eliminativism, naturalism, men

    talism, or mysterianism. Multiple and synergistic non

    dualistic points of view are essential, including

    behavioral, psychological, and neurological ones,

    taken all

    together

    bitter medicine that most have

    not been ready to swallow. However, the times they

    may be changing. The idea that the way we c an best

    understand the brain-mind is by simply emulating the

    physical sciences is gradually losing force. The recog

    nition that the mind is not only used by but also

    re lized various brain activities, with unique types

    of self-organizing complexity not capable of being

    replicated by silicone-based digital computers, is tak

    ing hold Searle, 1992; Clark 1997).

    Slowly Toward a Coherent

    Mind-Brain-Behavior Science

    The failure of too many in the various psychological,

    psychoanalytic, and neuroscience communities to con

    currently embrace the full hierarchical complexity

    of

    the human brain-mind with a full devotion to concep

    tual flexibility and scientific rigor, has saddened many

    generations of students who wanted a deep and realis

    tic understanding of the human condition. After a cen-

    24

    tury

    of

    remarkable research effort in experimental

    psychology, almost five decades

    of

    cognitivism, and

    three decades

    of

    modern neuroscience, we still have

    no unified community

    of

    scholars that tries to bring all

    the relevant issues openly into consideration-perhaps

    the recently emerging consciousness studies programs

    come closest. In any event, since we are close to solv

    ing some substantive psychological issues scientifi

    cally e.g., the nature of attention, memory, and

    perhaps even emotions), we should no longer ignore

    the many remaining issues that have long been ne

    glected from the fundamentally affective dimensions

    of mind to subtle feelings of volition and free-will. In

    experimental psychology, the most poignant orphan

    of our intellectual practices has been primary process

    or core consciousness----our deeply animalian--emo

    tional

    n ture n

    issue that psychoanalysis accepted

    see Solms and Nersessian, 1999) but which, at least

    during the past century, it did not nurture toward a

    vigorous scientific maturity. However, because

    of

    the

    recent revolutions in neuroscience and molecular biol

    ogy, along with emerging psychobehavioral and dy

    namic perspectives, we may finally be in a position to

    deal credibly with some

    of

    those long-neglected issues

    using rather standard, albeit somewhat more theoreti

    cally flexible, scientific approaches. The only thing

    that should matter in this scientific game is the capac

    ity to make predictions that can be empirically verified

    or falsified, whether they be traditional third-person

    measures or various indirect measures

    of

    first-person

    experience.

    A broad neuropsychobehavioral probing

    of

    the

    nature of the basic emotional and motivational sys

    tems of the mammalian brain, and the layers of con

    sciousness they regulate, has considerable potential to

    help heal the rifts between these troubled fields

    of

    ours.

    think the evidence, read correctly, is over

    whelming that our most immediate psychobehavioral

    concerns, from our fundamental instinctual actions to

    our more subtle life choices, are based upon funda

    mental biological values that our brains express as

    feelings MacLean, 1990; Panksepp, 1998a; Damasio,

    1999). We will only make meager progress on a vari

    ety of higher mental issues e.g., see Uttal, 2000) until

    those foundational values are better clarified.

    Unfortunately, the powerful cultural, intellectual,

    and emotional forces that would seek to counter such

    efforts remain alive and well. Indeed, those forces

    probably arise naturally from the deep polarities and

    animosities of human nature. The reactionaries who

    brought Galileo to his knees four centuries ago, con

    tinue to thrive within our own scientific communities,

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    4/17

    242

    although they no longer command the old tools of

    torture. But all too often they do control the purse

    strings for furthering empirical inquiries. Obviously,

    the scientific community is not immune to everyday

    power politics and the skewering influence of bull

    headed, alpha-type personalities who have commonly

    had too little hands-on experience with relevant as

    pects of life or laboratory to make the best scientific

    choices. Indeed, all long-standing scholarly traditions

    seem to be conservative in nature, with a class of ill

    prepared priests who recite traditional catechisms

    to protect the status quo.

    To try to shed some light, admittedly dim, on

    such issues, I will aspire to characterize (and shall, no

    doubt, caricature) the personalities that may be imped

    ing progress at the present time. My aim is not pejora

    tive, but I would highlight the intellectual stagnation

    that can result when too many scientific practitioners

    take excessive pride in the rigor of their logic and the

    precision of

    their methods rather than their willingness

    to confront nature as she truly presents herself in ani

    mate life. I will here call them, perhaps rather too

    gratuitously, left-hemisphere types, and contrast their

    approaches with the growing minority who aspire to

    grapple with the whole brain, with all of its diverse

    and often irrational riches.

    The Sociobiology of the Psychological Sciences

    As Whittle emphasizes, there are many subtle reasons

    for the schisms that characterize the various scholarly

    traditions that aspire to understand the psyche, the

    mind, and behavior. Although I largely agree with

    Whittle s analysis, I will toy further with the possibil

    ity that rather straightforward human cultural and per

    sonality issues may lie at the heart

    of

    the various

    intellectual disharmonies and discontents he described

    so poignantly. I also believe many

    of

    our troubles arise

    from ancient group dynamics that any competitive

    group of highly intelligent anthropoid apes is bound

    to exhibit when they are competing for limited re

    sources and their minds are split between fundamen

    tally different, culturally shaped worldviews, such as

    the willingness to consider objective versus subjective

    forms of data, experimental versus insightful-intuitive

    approaches to human nature, and the resulting disputes

    concerning the scientific credibility of third versus first

    person points of view. I do believe that the mentalistic

    position to which most intelligent people subscribe has

    been so widely rejected by mind-brain specialists to

    some extent for primitive group solidarity rea-

    Jaak Panksepp

    sons partly because their limited but rigorous spe

    cialist positions set them apart as uniquely qualified

    experts who supposedly have privileged perspectives

    to adjudicate on the nature of psychological reality.

    At some point, most investigators, probably be

    cause of their cognitive and emotional strengths but

    also because of the reward structures in which they

    must pursue their activities, select which approach

    they most admire either for deep intellectual and, not

    uncommonly, for straightforward opportunistic rea

    sons. During the past half-century of advancing mate

    rialism, there have been clear and differential rewards

    for selecting positivistic analytic paths over deeper in

    tegrative-synthetic ones. As a result, the middle way,

    which accepts the importance of both approaches, of

    both deductive reason and inductive insight, for any

    coherent understanding, has become the road least

    traveled. I remain puzzled

    at

    how little commerce cur

    rently exists on that byway, especially in my own field

    of

    behavioral neuroscience, a powerful animal brain

    research discipline that has so much rigorous evidence

    and evolutionary hypotheses to offer for the creation

    of a lasting psychobiological understanding of the hu

    man mind (Panksepp and Panksepp, 2000).

    It seems that to some yet unmeasured extent, pre

    vailing intellectual positions reflect desires to establish

    group and individual identities. Every human has a

    need to feel that he or she is best at something. f one is

    a farmer

    or

    builder, the evidence is often immediately

    evident to the eye. Hence, grantsmanship all too often

    becomes a skilled exercise in deceptive practices. f

    one is an academic or a therapist, then it is only evi

    dent in the praise and attention that others are willing

    to grant. Thus, in intellectual matters, the strengths

    of

    our alliances may be as important as the coherence of

    our ideas. Without social coalitions, we put ourselves

    at

    risk

    of

    being marginalized in the competition for

    the necessary resources to continue scientific work.

    And it is much easier to agree on the factual pepper

    corns than the big-ticket integrative items. Accord

    ingly, most scientists are committed to views held by

    long-established scientific groups, most

    of

    which in

    order to survive as traditions are bound to be intellec

    tually conservative. Unless a field is in the midst of

    technological-eonceptual breakthroughs (such as mo

    lecular biology during the past few decades), most in

    vestigators are bound to remain constrained by the

    leaden weight of the status quo even if they have won

    derful and productive ideas they would personally like

    to pursue. The federal granting establishment in the

    United States has become a remarkable exemplar of

    a system that encourages conceptual conservatism and

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    5/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    rewards run-of-the-mill empIrICIsm at least at the

    funding application stage, since what one does scien

    tifically with the provided support is rarely subject to

    accountability .

    One reason there has been remarkably little prog

    ress in understanding someof the key issues of human

    nature is because the study of emotions and motiva

    tions has long been devalued in the biological, psycho

    logical, and brain sciences. For current cultural

    reasons, emotions and psychoanalytic approaches are

    deemed

    of

    much less importance than cognitions and

    information processing approaches to understanding

    the human mind. Although the reasons for that are

    many perhaps the most important being the ascen

    dancy of the digital computer model of mind , the one

    dimension that has rarely been discussed is the poten

    tial skewing influences of the typical personalities that

    are attracted to scientific endeavors. I will now weave

    a blunt hypothesis that there has been a massive left

    hemisphere bias operating in the scientific arena and

    a right-hemisphere bias in the psychoanalytic one. Al

    though this hypothesis remains to be empirically eval

    uated, the mere fact that it has been so difficult to

    get substantive programs of emotion research off the

    ground in mainstream psychology and neuroscience

    will be taken as prima facia evidence that some rather

    unusual personality and cultural forces have shaped

    the ways in which the mind has been studied over the

    past five decades.

    Can

    Left-Brain Sciences Understand Whole

    rain

    Minds?

    As Whittle implies, the causes of the intellectual dis

    sensions that have been evident in the twentieth-cen

    tury mind sciences probably go deeper into human

    nature than we are typically wont to admit. Tempera

    mental style surely has an enormous influence on

    guiding the scholarly and professional choices of the

    participants. The scientific structures built by those

    who enjoy the chaotic right-hemispheric play

    of

    diver

    gent ideas and the resulting intuitive flashes, and those

    who admire more rigorously straight-furrowed left

    hemispheric forms of convergent thinking and the re

    sulting logical inferences are bound to differ. Could

    one of the major dilemmas in the brain-mind sciences

    be that most practitioners, becauseof student selection

    pressures, are remarkably proficient in left-hemi

    sphere linear thinking skills while being rather impov

    erished in right-hemisphere pattern-recognition

    abilities? Might it be largely the reverse in psychoana-

    4

    lytic circles, where open listening surely a right-hemi

    sphere attitude must be cultivated? Might such biases,

    if they could be demonstrated to exist, lead inexorably

    to remarkably skewed conceptionsof the brain-mind?

    For didactic purposes, I will here utilize a vastly

    oversimplified conception

    of

    right- and left-hemi

    sphere functions to make some general points about

    scientific personalities that may need to be made in

    rather glaring terms. Although there is abundant evi

    dence that the right hemisphere is more capable of

    extracting nondominant patterns and meanings from

    available information stores Fiore and Schooler,

    1998 , the attitudinal dichotomy I will pursue surely

    runs deeper in the brain-mind thanjust right-left hemi

    spheric biases. Still, recent attempts to put everything

    of obvious cognitive value into the left hemisphere

    Gazzaniga, 1998 , without fully recognizing the psy

    chologically more subtle and emotionally deep contri

    butions of the right Beeman and Chiarello, 1998 ,

    encourage me to proceed with my oversimplified

    tongue-in-cheek analysis.

    A great deal of the controversy concerning

    whether we can empirically study mental states is

    based

    on

    our philosophical position concerning the

    empirical accessibility of such states. Some claim that

    such states, although they surely exist within the brain,

    are simply not open to substantive empirical analysis

    at the present time Uttal, 2000 . I suspect that such

    philosophic positions are created as much by the af

    fective inclinations, or lack thereof,

    of

    their purveyors

    as the intellectual rigor of their arguments. In any

    event, if we consider that the generation and apprecia

    tion of inductive inferences is promoted more by the

    synthetic flow of right-hemisphere associations

    my-

    thos

    while the power of deductive logic is promoted

    more by left-hemispheric analytic skills

    logos ,

    we

    may come to understand why linear, left-hemisphere

    mental styles have prevailed so overwhelmingly in the

    sciences, including those that have sought to under

    stand behavior and mental life. The rules

    of

    scientific

    agreement are much more certain and clear-cut for

    deductively logical left-hemispheric thought than for

    the creative inferential leaps that emerge more from

    the right.

    Indeed, the traditional linear analytic thinking of

    the natural sciences has paid enormous dividends in

    generating systematic understanding of our world and

    in harnessing its material resources. However, those

    modes of left-hemispheric thought that have worked

    so well at unraveling the dynamics of the physical

    world, have not succeeded as dramatically in the

    brain-mind sciences. Perhaps this is because the brain-

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    6/17

    244

    mind is not simply the unfeeling type of linear infor

    mation processing computational device that many

    left-hemisphere types would like to believe, but rather,

    at its foundation it is a fundamentally organic and

    globally holistic integrator and blender

    of

    past evolu

    tionary solutions and present environmental chal

    lenges. Perhaps for any comprehensive understanding,

    the two views need to be judiciously combined, so that

    the capacity of a mode of thought to generate coherent

    predictions rather than logically airtight arguments be

    comes the main arbiter of how we allow a fundamen

    tally organic mind science to evolve.

    We should also recall that left and right hemi

    spheres have rather different affective styles and social

    priorities. Most of us tend to present ourselves to the

    world with our left-hemisphere linguistic skills, to the

    point where we commonly speak out of one side of our

    mouth----often remarkably logically in a propositional

    left-hemisphere way, but quite unreasonably from a

    more integrative right-hemisphere perspective. The

    left hemisphere, in its appointed role of projecting an

    image of positive social desirability into the world, is

    not only an interpreter Gazzaniga, 1998), but also

    a skilled confabulator , especially when it comes to

    trying to deal with emotional experiences, which are

    felt more intensely by its more passive and silent part

    ner. Clearly, it is the right hemisphere that provides the

    greater depth to our emotional narratives and affective

    experiences Ross, Homan, and Buck, 1994; Ornstein,

    1997; Beeman and Chiarello, 1998), and perhaps the

    left hemisphere is a specialist in emotional repression.

    f so, there is reason to believe that the left hemi

    sphere, divorced from the fundamental anchoring of

    the full spectrum of human emotional experiences

    elaborated subcortically and within the other side of

    the brain, could easily become adept at helping con

    struct simple-minded

    dreams

    of reason that create

    monsters

    y

    least favorite examples being the

    radical behaviorism that denied mind and brain any

    place in the behavioral sciences and all eugenics

    movements past and present. Also, the mere fact that

    women are better than men in coordinating the activi

    ties of the two hemispheres Shaywitz, Shaywitz,

    Pugh, and Constable, 1995), may go a long way to

    ward explaining why females are underrepresented in

    the natural sciences, as well as why holistic and fluid

    right-hemispheric modes of psychoanalytic thought

    have prevailed in feminist theory and the arts.

    There is much to be discovered about the person

    alities that are attracted to an uncompromisingly left

    hemisphere logic-reason) view

    of

    the world as well

    as those who selectively view life through the prism

    Jaak

    Panksepp

    of the right intuition-insight). I would wager that,

    could it be empirically evaluated, the majority

    of

    tradi

    tional scientists would tend to fall in the former cate

    gory, helping explain why twentieth-century

    psychology offered us so many linear and logically

    simplified, and ultimately incomplete views of human

    nature. Indeed, might the stark Machiavellian egotism

    that all too commonly prevails in high-powered left

    hemisphere science see Pert [1997] for a recent de

    scription of the take-as-you-can types that pervade so

    much of present-day science), reflect a functional dis

    connection syndrome when the left-hemisphere abili

    ties are excessively divorced from right-hemisphere

    values?

    To put the hypothesis bluntly: A larger than nor

    mal proportion of the most successful scientists, in

    cluding experimental psychologists, may be

    remarkably self-centered, highly competitive, and all

    too often, not very agreeable types. As a population,

    they may have less than normal levels of emotional

    sensitivity, with a predilection for exhibiting notewor

    thy symptoms of academic autism. They are satis

    fied to know more and more about less and less, with

    little heed for social and emotional sensitivities that

    concern most other people. Whether the incidence of

    such personality styles is actually higher than that

    found in the humanities or other professions would be

    a most interesting issue to evaluate empirically, and

    if

    the data support the hypothesis, to discuss psychoana

    lytically. To my knowledge, no substantive empirical

    analysis

    of

    differential personality styles in different

    academic disciplines has been conducted, but I suspect

    the topic may be a rich mine for some eager psycholo

    gist, sociologist, or cultural anthropologist. In any

    event, I offer this psychoanalytic hypothesis to explain

    the chaotic state of our mind sciences only half in jest.

    In any event, the Janus-faced nature

    of

    our cognitive

    and affective proclivities has surely exerted yet un

    measured effects on the forms of our various

    mind-brain science.

    Future Speculations about the Personality

    Styles of Scientists and the Sciences They

    Create

    f

    there is some type

    of

    selective funneling

    of

    different

    personalities into different disciplines, it is bound to

    have remarkable consequences for the way whole

    fields of

    thought and inquiry are framed, most espe

    cially in the psychological sciences. For instance,

    might the massive intolerance for talk about inner psy-

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    7/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    chological causes among behavioral psychologists be

    based not only on the methodological difficulties

    posed by the study of the subjective life, but also on

    their lopsided emotional skills? From my own 40 years

    of

    experiences in the field, that does not seems a far

    fetched possibility. Despite recent advances in deci

    phering how emotional learning transpires in certain

    areas

    of

    the brain such as the amygdala (e.g., LeDoux,

    1996), one is still hard put to find a behavioral scientist

    who seems constitutionally able to openly discuss the

    potential role

    of

    affective feelings in the instigation

    and guidance

    of

    behavioral responses and regulation

    of behavioral choices. The majority, at least in my

    experience, tend to believe that type of talk borders

    on the absurd. Only begrudgingly will most entertain

    the idea that other animals actually experience pain

    and

    fear-preferring

    to phrase their ideas in terms of

    nociceptive stimuli and anxietylike behaviors.

    The radical behaviorism

    of

    the middle part

    of

    the

    twentieth-century-the mode

    of

    thought that aspired

    to kill

    psychoanalysis-was

    an exemplar

    of

    that kind

    of

    thought. It was deeply logical in its limited domain,

    but in my estimation, it yielded a fundamentally mis

    guided view

    of

    animate nature. Despite the behaviorist

    desire to aspire to nothing but visually observable ob

    jectivity, there is still every reason to believe that ani

    mals lives revolve around many comparatively

    invisible inner causes, evolutionarily constructed, that

    cannot be unambiguously observed in the behavioral

    acts

    of

    organisms but must be neurotheoretically in

    ferred. I did my part to coax Skinner to change his

    radically antagonistic and limited ways

    of

    thinking

    (i.e., Panksepp, 1990), but, in the final accounting, he

    was not coaxed into reconsidering the possibility that

    emotional and motivational feelings are not simply

    excellent examples of the fictional causes to which

    we commonly attribute behavior (Skinner, 1953, p

    160).

    To this day, his ultrapositivistic way

    of

    viewing

    the animate life prevails in behavioral neuroscience,

    even though the more skilled thinkers will now tend to

    espouse terminal agnosticism (typically

    of

    the

    closed

    door

    variety) on the topic

    of

    emotional and motiva

    tional affective experiences in animals. In the face

    of

    the massive amount

    of

    data indicating that various

    subcortical areas

    of

    the mammalian brain mediate va

    lenced affective states, arising from essentially the

    same circuits in all species that have been studied

    (Panksepp, 1998a), I find closed door agnosticism

    to be either opportunistic or remarkably half-minded.

    If

    physicists had taken such positions to the internal

    structure of atoms, we would still be ignorant of the

    5

    physical nature

    of

    matter. We will remain as ignorant

    of

    the true organizational principles

    of

    the mammalian

    brain if we continue to ignore the central role

    of

    af

    fective states in the governance of animal behavior

    and human mind. Considering the deep neuroanatomi

    cal homologies in the organization of subcortical re

    gions of the brain, it is likely that our capacity to

    decipher the circuitry that generates emotional pro

    cesses in animals (e.g., as indexed by approach and

    avoidance, and conditioned place preferences and

    aversions) can provide an essential platform for un

    derstanding which types

    of

    brain systems govern af

    fective states, and perhaps the foundations of

    consciousness, in humans. At least, it will yield coher

    ent theoretical propositions that can be empirically

    evaluated in humans using various biological (e.g.,

    pharmacological) maneuvers. Thus, the type

    of

    agnos

    ticism we should aspire to should be

    of

    the open

    door variety.

    In any event, affective processes are still widely

    considered insubstantial by most neuroscientists,

    while considerably more dubious procedur l concepts

    such as reinforcement are commonly discussed as

    if

    they are substantive biological realities simply be

    cause animal behavior in prisonlike environments can

    be molded remarkably effectively by systematically

    applied whips and

    carrots,

    all too commonly

    wielded by experimenters who relish the concept

    of

    linear control

    s

    opposed to chaotic neurodynamics.

    Need it be pointed out that to this day no one has yet

    demonstrated a reinforcement

    process

    to be oper

    ate in molding the real-world behaviors

    of

    animals?

    If

    one really looked at

    ll

    the evidence, one would be

    forced to conclude that concepts such as reinforce

    ment are more likely to be the phlogiston

    of psychol

    ogy than are the basic emotional value systems of

    ancient regions

    of

    the mammalian brain.

    The notion

    of

    reinforcement may simply be an

    inevitable hangover

    of

    the assumption that we could

    obtain clear conceptions of the major causes of animal

    actions simply by studying stimulus-control

    of

    behav

    ior in semistarved animals tested under conditions

    where there were no effective behavioral alternatives

    other than those provided by the experimenter. This

    is a classic methodological

    flaw-an

    experimenter-im

    posed

    dem nd ch r cteristic th t

    introductory psy

    chology students are trained to recognize and avoid in

    designing their own fledgling experiments. Although

    it is understandable why many would deem it to be

    an exquisitely desirable form

    of

    experimental con

    trol, we should not accept the delusion that such

    methodologies provide general insights into how the

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    8/17

    6

    spont n ous

    behavior

    of

    animals is regulated.

    Throughout the behaviorist era, the instruments of

    measurement were essential for creating the system

    atic response patterns that were observed. The natural

    spontaneous behaviors of animals were neglected, and

    when those urges did rear their wondrous heads, they

    were deemed to reflect the misbehavior

    of

    organ

    isms. Today, a similar type

    of

    control-oriented mind

    set is leading to a massive overdiagnosis of Attention

    Deficit-Hyperactivity Disorders in our American

    society (Panksepp, 1998c).

    Obviously, when animals have no reasonable be

    havioral options, they are likely to take the single one

    offered to them by the experimenter. The remarkably

    robust and consistent patterns of behavior in starved

    animals within Skinner Boxes did provide a clear im

    age

    of

    how most organisms will behave under strin

    gent economic constraints, but we should be under no

    illusion that those methodologies provided powerful

    and deeply meaningful general laws of behavior.

    Paradoxically, the realistic alternative that evolu

    tionarily provided instinctive feelings typically guide

    behavioral choices in the real world remains as rare

    in the prevailing forms of dustbowl cognitivism

    s

    in

    the preceding behavioristic varieties. Although af

    fective explanations would require us to specify rather

    precisely what we mean by internally valenced feel

    ings, that is now an option that can be realistically

    envisioned (Panksepp, 1998b; Berridge, 2000). Feel

    ings are not simply vague concepts that emerge from

    our linguistic abilities (Rolls, 1999) nor from our vast

    abilities to remember events transpiring in our brains

    (LeDoux, 1996) or to perceive events in our bodies

    (Damasio, 1994). They appear to be fundamental birth

    rights of ancient centromedial regions of the human

    brain (Damasio, 1999) that we share with all the other

    mammals (Panksepp, 1998a).

    I do believe that brain evolution represented the

    animal s point of view much more than most behav

    ioral neuroscientists and cognitive psychologists were

    ever willing to consider. To the best of our knowledge,

    all other mammals have basic emotional feelings and

    neurosymbolic selves based on neural foundations

    that are homologous to our own (Panksepp, 1998a,b).

    Affective or core consciousness is a very old brain

    function (Damasio, 1999; Panksepp, 1998a, 2000).

    Once we begin to provisionally entertain and to exper

    imentally evaluate the existence

    of

    such brain pro

    cesses, a coherent psychological science may emerge

    that

    s

    more accurate and more conceptually satisfying

    than the ones we now have (Watt, 1999). Such ap

    proaches to mental life may also provide an intellec-

    Jaak Panksepp

    tual structure that can be more easily respected by

    many other disciplines, and it can be incorporated

    readily into revitalized forms of psychoanalytic

    thought.

    Continuing Intellectual Polarities

    From a psychoanalytic point of view, the stark, skele

    tonlike structure of behavioristic thought often resem

    bled a monstrosity that had not come to terms with

    many essential aspects of either human or animal life.

    As Whittle poignantly highlighted, the minds of stu

    dents were all too often numbed at sacrificial altars

    of

    intellectual traditions that disenfranchised themselves

    from vast swaths of human experience and animal

    existence. The absence

    of

    any substantive or even

    handed discussion

    of

    animate emotions in the behav

    iorist literature was only the most evident case in

    point, and such attitudes remain alive and well today

    in both cognitively and neuroscientifically oriented

    disciplines. Indeed, our most recent attempt-to-publish

    experience has revealed to us once more how vital the

    antiemotional forces are within the scientific commu

    nity our

    discovery

    of

    what appears to be animal

    laughter has been most difficult to publish in tradi

    tional scientific outlets (Panksepp and Burgdorf,

    1999), as were our studies

    of

    animal play 20 years

    earlier, and

    of

    separation-induced crying before

    that (Panksepp, 1998a, chapters 14 and 15). The ac

    ceptance

    of

    coherent primordial forces in the animal

    brain is apparently not welcome news in those disci

    plines, for many practitioners would still like to con

    ceptualize animals as mindless, nonconscious reflex

    machines rather than the spontaneously active agents

    that they are.

    The fact that basic emotions and motivations

    were so thoroughly devalued in twentieth-century ex

    perimental psychology (including current cognitive

    varieties) remains the most tangible symbolic token,

    perhaps even a fundamental cause, of

    our

    century

    of

    misunderstanding. At present, there are a remarkable

    number

    of

    investigators who still scoff at the idea that

    a variety of affective feelings may be intrinsic func

    tions of the mammalian brain. Since the study sections

    of granting agencies are abundantly populated by such

    skeptics, work on many

    of

    the most important basic

    emotional systems

    of

    the mammalian brain, such as

    those that mediate anger, grief, and joy, continue to

    receive essentially no support, and thereby are receiv

    ing remarkably little experimental attention. Likewise,

    pharmaceutical firms, whose research departments re-

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    9/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    main well populated by unreasonably radical behav

    iorists (who brought them many slick behavioral

    technologies, but few productive ideas), are not devot

    ing sufficient resources to trying to discover medica

    tions for regulating specific emotions. Meanwhile

    exhorbitant amounts

    of

    money are being squandered,

    to put it bluntly but symbolically, on severely stressing

    animals to determine how nociceptive responses in

    their tails are modified by local spinal mechanisms.

    During the twentieth century, experimental psy

    chology became a discipline that expected productive

    minds to subsist at the meager table

    of facts with

    which all reasonably alexithymic left-hemisphere

    types can agree. At the same time, psychoanalytic

    thought insisted that we must seek to deal with the

    full complexity of the human condition, but sadly, it

    did not encourage investigators to invest in compelling

    new empirical paradigms to clarify the ideas and con

    cepts it wished to disseminate. Through that failure,

    it disenfranchised itself from the available sources of

    scientific support and respect. All too often, psychoan

    alytic thought wished to capture the full circus carni

    val life, and thereby found its most welcome home

    among literary theorists who felt no need to have their

    thought tempered by the purifying fire of experimental

    analysis. After all, humans do love a great story,

    and as often as not, the facts be damned.

    All too many proponents of psychoanalytic views

    have insisted that the diversity of individual lives can

    not (and often, should not) be subjected to the dehu

    manizing tools and perspectives of available

    experimental disciplines; for the subtleness of mind

    might not emerge unscathed from that. Indeed, there

    is much to be said against human sciences that wish

    to force the vast diversity of human mind and behavior

    into statistically constructed pigeonholes such as few

    factor theories of personality and massive evolution

    arily dictated modularities that all too often do not

    respect the remarkable plasticities and potentialities

    of the human brain. However, to the extent that psy

    choanalytic thought is to be taken seriously in scien

    tific circles, it will need to be linked to empirical

    observations. As many behaviorists might claim from

    their starkly ascetic perspectives it is better to have

    an honest kernel of replicable knowledge rather than

    a banquet of verbally generated understanding laid

    out on quicksand. Fortunately, what was quicksand

    only a few decades ago, has become firm ground for

    theory building because of the neuroscience and mo

    lecular biology revolutions. The fact that many emo

    tions and motivations have specific circuits and

    molecular codes is the single most important finding

    7

    that allows us clear access into the neuronal nature

    of a growing number of primitive mental processes

    (Panksepp, 1986, 1993).

    In any event, what is needed now is for us to

    leave those old intellectual battles for dominance be

    hind, and to seek new ways

    of

    thinking that allow

    multiple viewpoints a voice around a widening intel

    lectual table. As Freud suspected, fundamental mental

    tendencies are

    re lize within

    neuronal systems. As

    we come to absorb the lessons from neuroscience, we

    should also come to respect the need for accurate em

    pirical descriptions of the human mind. We should

    not allow established dogma to be the arbiter of what

    constitutes generally accepted understanding we

    should be guided by prediction generated by our ideas.

    Perspectives that yield no predictions must continue

    to be deemed sterile or premature.

    Toward Reconciliations

    Thus, we now stand at an intellectual juncture where

    there is enormous room for fruitful compromise, pro

    ductive synthesis, and the development of robust new

    hybrid research strategies. Psychoanalytic thought

    without a new level of empiricism and experimental

    psychology without a fuller confrontation with the an

    cient foundational value substrates of the mind, will

    only sustain needless polarities. As long as our intel

    lectual systems sustain and nurture those polarities

    (e.g., in the structures of academic subdisciplines

    where one area need not pay attention to the relevant

    work of other areas), we will continue to discourage

    and alienate the best students who come to us still

    adept at using both of their cerebral hemispheres at

    times miraculously so, considering the current domi

    nance of left-brain oriented educational systems

    within our society. Thus, any future curriculum in psy

    choanalysis should absorb the best psychobiology,

    neuroscience, and evolutionary psychology of the last

    few decades. Indeed, all the social sciences must come

    to terms with the evolved, epigenetically refined abili

    ties of the brain.

    In therapy also, we must better recognize that

    there are two distinct personalities in each individual,

    of both right and left hemispheric varieties (Ross et

    aI., 1994; Schore, 1994), as well as deeper, subcortical

    affective ones. One aim of therapeutic enterprises, as

    well as our educational ones, should be to introduce

    them to each other (Schiffer, 1998).

    Obviously, the styles of both hemispheres need

    to be acknowledged not only in therapy but also in

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    10/17

    8

    our educational systems, s we reverse the sustained

    misunderstandings that characterized the twentieth

    century. Perhaps that can be achieved by all sides in

    vesting in new empirically based perspectives with

    which all can agree. As argued eloquently by Uttal

    (2000), a newly refined form

    of

    behaviorism must be

    a player, but not the only player, in any future synthe

    sis. I sometimes think that an emerging functional neu

    roscience, based on evolutionary principles, can

    become a sufficiently robust and lasting foundation

    where all modes of thought can consiliate within the

    dynamics

    of

    the enchanted loom. The emerging evi

    dence has now demonstrated that all brains contain a

    set of emotional and motivational value-creating sys

    tems around which a great deal of behavior, both ratio

    nal and irrational, revolves. The evolutionary

    divergences and progressions within these core pro

    cesses among mammalian lines have probably been so

    modest that remarkable homologies still exist in brain

    systems that help regulate basic human and animal ac

    tions.

    The continuous historical thread of DNA that still

    ties

    us

    to all other forms of life, is providing a richness

    of underlying controls, shared with all other animals,

    that should be satisfying to both hemispheres for many

    millennia (Raff, 1996), especially when it is viewed

    from the perspective of

    the environmental contexts in

    which it must unfurl its magic in remarkably plastic

    ways (Oyama, 1985). At the same time, the interactive

    mind-brain processes allow us to envision, all too eas

    ily, evolved cerebral modules (e.g., Tooby and Cos

    mides, 2000) where only general cerebral abilities may

    exist (Samuels, 1998; Panksepp and Panksepp, 2000).

    Thus, the major danger of theoretical approaches,

    s

    behaviorism always claimed (as a result of the multi

    plication of instincts at the turn of the century), is

    the ease with which after-the-fact

    just so

    stories

    can be generated. Without strong corroborative evi

    dence

    of

    conclusions, they just constitute plausible ex

    amples of a vast number of theoretical possibilities,

    and it should be the responsibility of each investigator

    to cast potential explanations in ways that can be em

    pirically falsified. Neuroscientific thought can anchor

    our theorizing realistically better than any other con

    straint at the present time.

    For the foreseeable future, a most important so

    cial and educational question will be: How shall we

    build modes of thought and educational systems that

    respect and convey the fullness of

    the shared seeds

    that evolution has provided not only for us but all our

    brethren creatures, without in any way demeaning the

    sustaining environments, both natural and cultural,

    Jaak Panksepp

    that allow those seeds to grow fruitfully? Parentheti

    cally, we must now consider, with renewed energy,

    how we might discourage those who would flirt with

    disasters-for

    instance, the new eugenicists who

    would meddle with our germ lines, no doubt

    r the

    betterment

    the human spirit.

    Could we really geneti

    cally engineer humans who feel the hedonic caress of

    bliss more than the sting of loss (e.g.,.

    wireheading.

    com

    without doing irreparable harm to the social fab

    ric? Surely sociocultural problems require sociocultu

    ral solutions (e.g., Panksepp, 1998c), even though

    there should also be many biological aids for individu

    als whose emotional processes are deficient or trouble

    some. But we are only at the verge of realistically

    discussing such possibilities. The levels of genetic and

    epigenetic complexity that we must deal with are stag

    gering (Oyama, 1985; Raff, 1996), and many of us

    find it troublesome that the analytically adept left

    hemisphere types, with their dreams of reason, are

    once again contemplating playing carelessly with our

    most precious heritage.

    New and refined versions of neuropsychoanalytic

    thought could be one of the most powerful antidotes

    to blindly meddling with the human spirit. But to be

    effective, that may require a new and rigorous attitude

    to take hold--one where the full array of analytic tools

    from the experimental disciplines are fully imple

    mented to demonstrate the general foundational out

    lines and the individual details of human minds. That

    is exactly where experimental psychology has failed

    quite miserably during our past century of misunder

    standing. It has given us rather little knowledge about

    our ultimate concerns-the nature of the pericons

    cious affective processes that surround and support

    our more acute forms of awareness.

    e

    must come to

    terms with the many deep and insistent feelings that

    guide the life choices we must make. We need to cre

    ate cultural supports for encouraging a full scientific

    confrontation with those deep neuropsychological

    issues.

    We are now in a position to take some major

    steps along the path that Freud sketched in sparse out

    line, and all too often in very preliminary and, at least

    from our present vantage, rather perplexing ways. I

    believe that we could have a major healing

    process-a

    synthesis that takes full advantage of the scientific

    analytic traditions of the twentieth

    century-if

    we

    build a new and robust psychoanalytic science. I

    would like to share two views, one philosophical, and

    one practical, that may help us construct a unified sci

    ence of

    human mind, based partly on animal brain

    research, where neuropsychological and psychoana-

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    11/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    lytic thought, not to mention scientific and humanistic

    thought in general, can subsist and support each oth

    er s endeavors.

    Philosophical Issues

    I am fond of the possibility that

    we

    may be able to

    make progress

    if we

    only have a solid foundation

    of

    knowledge about biological values with which most

    reasonable thinkers could agree. I think that the neuro

    psychic world, at least in the long run, is constructed

    largely

    as

    it appears to us

    subjectively-we

    make an

    enormous number

    of

    life choices based upon the way

    those choices make us feel.

    We

    avoid cold, hunger,

    thirst, fear, and loneliness. We all aspire to engage

    creatively with the world, seeking material and social

    resources and interactions that produce pleasures and

    satisfactions, to avoid all kinds

    of

    harm. Our adult

    social behavior is often

    so

    confusing only because we

    commonly do not follow the immediate dictates

    of

    our

    feelings, but rather the paths that seem instrumentally/

    cognitively most propitious for our long-term goals.

    This leads to all varieties of conflicts and thwarting,

    which establish layers

    of

    emotional complexity upon

    our more basic urges. Accordingly, it has been a di

    lemma to conceptualize adequately what those more

    ancient species

    of

    psychic activity, the basic feelings,

    consist of. However, now we have some credible

    hypotheses-they

    reflect the actions

    of

    ancient neural

    systems that were constructed, during long-spans

    of

    evolutionary time to generate various intentions in

    action (Searle, 1983 -which are ultimately experi

    enced as dynamic value codes (i.e., feelings with a

    psychodynamic shape to guide our behavioral ac

    tions (for summary, see Panksepp, 1998a). With addi

    tional layers of cognitive evolution,

    as

    our ancestors

    came to compete more and more for the same limited

    resources, the options for effective behavioral action

    became ever more complex, yielding the possibility

    that we could have real intentions to act in voluntary

    ways (Spence and Frith, 1999). And now we hu

    mans-the top

    predators-have

    hierarchically ar

    ranged neural systems unparalleled in brain evolution,

    creating a subtlety

    of

    mind accompanied by a sense of

    power and dominion over the world that is unrivaled.

    This does not mean that the manner in which the

    brain achieves psychological capacities is transparent,

    and it

    is

    all too easy to acknowledge defeat, in princi

    ple, and regress to behaviorist solutions that were re

    markably successful for helping

    us

    address certain

    limited problems in rigorous empirical ways. It is all

    9

    too easy to have the type of psychobiological despair

    recently expressed by William Uttal (2000):

    However, behaviorists generally argue that all re

    sponses (or behaviors) are measures

    of

    the totality of

    the experience or awareness

    of

    the behaving organism

    and are the resultant of a combination of many differ

    ent stimulus, organism, and response variables as well

    as the past experiences and (to an unknown, but usu

    ally lesser, degree) the genetic heritage of the individ

    ual. The combination is irretrievably tangled,

    according to behaviorists, and little if anything can

    be done to disentangle the combination. According to

    this viewpoint, behavior cannot tell us anything about

    the component processes or mechanisms that underlie

    the mental events. Indeed, because many possible

    mechanisms could lead to the same psychological

    event and there are many obscuring and transforming

    factors between behavior and mental processes, the

    barrier between the two domains is impenetrable as a

    matter

    of both deep principles and practical consider

    ations p 5].

    Well, true enough, as long as we choose to leave

    the evolved circuitry of subcortical regions of the brain

    out of our overall analysis. Clearly, it is our newfound

    knowledge

    of

    the brain that can now save us from the

    endless quandary of the behaviorist nightmare de

    scribed so poignantly above. We do have one robust

    path out

    of

    that bog

    of

    despair, and it is paved by

    neuroscientific knowledge that recognizes that basic

    psychological processes can be both used and

    re lized in complex brain systems (Searle, 1983 -a

    path that has been resisted, until recently, by both psy

    chology and psychoanalysis.

    However, a true understanding of affective pro

    cesses in the mammalian brain allows us a conceptual

    path of remarkable clarity. The reality of both human

    and animal minds is based upon the dynamics of our

    ancient, and hence often shared, value systems. Those

    behavioral actions that make us feel good internally,

    in the many ways that have so rarely been discussed

    in modern neuroscience and experimental psychology,

    will be advanced. Those actions that make us feel

    worse internally, in the many ways that have hardly

    been discussed in modern experimental psychology or

    neuroscience, will be diminished. It may be

    as

    sim

    p e as that.

    Behaviorism may have had it backwards all

    along--environments mold behavior only to the extent

    that they can recruit the self-organizing affective func

    tions

    of

    organisms. The only reason reinforcement

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    12/17

    5

    procedures work so well, especially in highly con

    strained prisonlike circumstances, is because they tap

    into the dynamics

    of

    various underlying emotional sys

    tems. There really is no unified brain function such

    as

    reinforcement, only environmentally induced

    changes in our perception

    of

    world events, and our

    endeavors to maximize positive feelings and to mini

    mize distress within those perceptual fields. However,

    as

    psychoanalytic thought has always recognized, to

    feel better, sometimes we must make psychological

    detours of enormous proportions, with many subtle

    interactive and often conflictual layers of being. The

    mind is like an onion. As we peel off the outside cog

    nitive layers (many

    of

    which are less conscious and

    less intentional than most believe) we get closer and

    closer to the ancient animalian centers of gravity, the

    basic emotional and motivational barometers, that

    guided the evolution and epigenetic emergence

    of

    the

    surrounding complexities. As we peel away the thick

    cortical layers

    of

    cognitive potentials (the tool

    boxes of consciousness), the evolved animal mind

    (

    id structures full

    of

    a nonpropositional form

    of

    affective consciousness) reveals itself within the hu

    man brain.

    If this

    is

    a realistic picture, it will,

    of

    course,

    be

    of

    foremost importance to come to terms with the

    fundamental nature

    of

    feelings. That is a project that

    has barely begun, and prominent investigators are still

    trying to conceptualize feelings

    as

    epiphenomenal spe

    cies within the higher memorial and linguistic reaches

    of the brain (LeDoux, 1996; Rolls, 1999) where our

    highest levels

    of

    intentionality are elaborated (Spence

    and Frith, 1999), rather than in the evolutionary an

    cient emotional processes

    of

    the brainstem where the

    core of mammalian consciousness emerged. I believe

    those forms of neodualism, that are yielding such won

    derful peppercorns of fact, are fundamentally mis

    guided. They do not adequately recognize the natural

    psychological kinds that arise from intrinsic, evolu

    tionarily provided brain activities, and they continue

    to

    be lumbered by a form

    of

    dualism that could be

    resolved straightfowardly

    if

    they recognized how men

    tal processes are not only

    used

    but also

    re lized

    in

    certain operations

    of

    the brain (Searle, 1983, chap

    ter 10). But there is now a robust alternative view,

    coherent with the general philosophic path laid out by

    Searle-that our values are fundamentally created by

    the ancient instinctual operating systems

    of

    the brain

    that

    we

    share with other animals (Panksepp, 1998a;

    Damasio, 1999).

    I believe the evidence has become overwhelm

    ing-our basic feelings are fundamentally the reflec-

    Jaak Panksepp

    tions

    of

    certain brainstem neural systems in action.

    The experience

    of

    thirst arises from plasma volume

    and osmotic receptors in specific areas

    of

    the hypothal

    amus, and their influence is distributed widely in sub

    cortical regions of the brain, including those specific

    zones where many other forms

    of

    affect are generated

    (Panksepp, 1998b). The pleasure

    of taste

    is

    instanti

    ated by specific subcortical systems

    of the mammalian

    brain (Berridge, 2000). Hunger, in both mouse and

    man, reflects some yet uncomputed combination

    of

    activities in brain Neuropeptide Y dynorphin, orexin,

    and melanocyte stimulating hormone, glutamate, and

    GABA systems in action (Kalra et aI. 1999), with

    general modulation of all systems by the biogenic

    amines. Hunger and all the other basic feelings pene

    trate the higher layers

    of

    the brain-mind, making it an

    issue of utmost cognitive concern when the primordial

    psychic powers are sustained for any length

    of

    time. Also such feelings can also be tokens, like

    any perceptual tokens such as the redness

    of

    apples,

    in our cognitive deliberations. However, it is funda

    mentally incorrect, at least in my reading of the evi

    dence, to believe that evolution left such ultimate

    concerns as biological values to be mere tokens within

    cognitive planning systems. Evolution, just as our sub

    jective experience would suggest, made them pow

    ers that are global state variables in diverse

    parliamentary lobbies

    of

    the mind-brain.

    Compelling hypotheses along these lines can

    fi-

    nally be generated for a host

    of

    basic feelings-emo

    tions. If we take these perspectives seriously, we may

    finally be approaching a substantive understanding of

    the shared foundations of human

    and

    animal nature,

    although most

    of

    the hard experimental work and

    novel neuro-psychoanalytic theorizing lie ahead. It

    will be an exciting chapter of science when we learn

    to sift the basic genetically guided abilities from deriv

    ative socially constructed processes in the analysis

    of

    how brain generates mind stuff.

    In any event, it would be most wonderful, if we

    were willing to invest the effort to make sure that

    we now head toward a century

    of

    mutually beneficial

    understanding rather than a furtherance

    of

    the types

    of

    polarization and misunderstanding that character

    ized our recent past. This may require an intellectual

    rebirth-one

    that abandons outdated modes

    of

    thought

    that were acceptable in a previous era. Perhaps the

    most dangerous ghosts from the past are the varieties

    of

    Cartesian mind-body dualism that attempt to funda

    mentally divide that which is indivisible (for review,

    see Damasio, 1994).

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    13/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    The cabalistic delusion that mind can exist with

    out material dynamics is, I believe, the single most

    destructive idea that we have ever had in the

    brain-mind sciences. Although humans can buffer

    their affective processes, with volitional, working

    memory processesof their frontal, parietal, and tempo

    ral cortices, and thereby withhold vario\ls primitive

    emotional reactions, most animals do not have such

    options, at least anywhere close to our human abilities,

    for emotional repression and regulation. The sustained

    emotional responses of animals probably reflect direct

    read-outs of their emotional states. The reason such

    isomorphisms are not accepted are largely because the

    neuroscientific behaviorists still believe that an analy

    sis of the behavioral and physiological responses are

    the sole issues of importance in any neural analysis.

    Affect, they believe, can be deemed to be a superfluous

    issue. For some reason, they fail to accept or acknowl

    edge that affect is the foremost personal concern that

    people have when they are in emotional states, and

    that animal affective neuroscience is essentially the

    only way we can find out, in any detailed way, how the

    basic human feelings are truly constructed in the brain.

    In any event, mind, brain, and behavior are com

    pletely

    interpenetrant and

    we cannot understand the

    resulting integrated processes unless we are willing to

    take all three perspectives concurrently to the studyof

    animate actions.

    If

    behaviorists continue to just study

    emotional behaviors, with no concern for the affective

    experiences of animals, we will continue to have a

    dualistic view

    of

    the brain.

    If

    experimental psycholo

    gists and psychoanalysts choose to pursue only the

    psychic reflections of brain processes, when the

    ous three-pronged solution is readily available, we

    shall surely continue with another century of misun

    derstanding. However,

    if

    we come to terms with the

    full tridimensional complexities, accepting that there

    are various unified psychic states arising from neuro

    dynamic processes that arouse behavioral urges, then

    we may eventually have unified approaches to knowl

    edge that can truly nourish the intellectual curiosity

    of

    future generations of students. In following such

    paths, we may also eventually generate psychiatric di

    agnostic categories that are based on our knowledge

    of

    brain emotional and motivational systems, and their

    neural substrates Panksepp, 1988, 2001 , rather than

    those that are simply based on catalogs of external

    symptoms.

    A Practical Proposal Psychoethology

    Considering the high likelihood that all mammals

    share the same fundamental value structures in their

    5

    brains, from various motivational processes to the

    more subtle emotional ones, we can anticipate that

    animal brain research will clarify the fundamental na

    ture of our biological values with a remarkable degree

    of

    clarity. Unfortunately, it will not be able to say

    much about our wider

    concerns the

    cognitive atti

    tudes and strategies that constitute the details of our

    mental lives. For that, there is no substitute for careful

    and insightful exploration

    of

    the human mind, which

    experimentally, at least, has barely begun. At the men

    tal levels, there is bound to be much greater species

    variability Budiansky, 1998 , especially among the

    evolved cognitive adaptations of which evolutionary

    psychologists speak so persistently and eloquently

    Tooby and Cosmides, 2000 , even

    as

    they tend to

    disregard the primitive evolved systems of the brain

    mind that have already been revealed Panksepp,

    1998a; Panksepp and Panksepp, 2000 . Even though

    the debate concerning the experimental analyzability

    and accessibility of the mind is by no means resolved,

    and despite the failures of previous introspective tradi

    tions Uttal, 2000 , in fact a credible form of experi

    mental mentalism has barely started to be

    implemented. We must study the human mind as it

    naturally presents itself, and there is no better tool

    than free association. Although the narrative data

    streams that will need to be analyzed are bound to

    be hypercomplex, it is time to begin evaluating the

    affective-eognitive ramifications of the human mind

    with the best empirical approaches

    available not

    only to describe group tendencies but also the unique

    ness of individuals. New methodologies-naturalistic

    approaches in which scientists and humanists can be

    equally

    involved may

    help in such endeavors. I

    would call one such new approach psy hoethology

    While traditional ethology consisted of the care

    ful and detailed study

    of

    animal and human behavioral

    actions, psychoethology could aspire to do the same

    for the human mind. What is desperately needed is

    a generally acceptable methodology whereby mental

    contents can be observed without all the interference

    that the flow

    of

    life provides.

    Of

    course, the prototypic

    psychoanalytic couch, with a human actively listening

    at the head but not intruding actively in the narrative

    flow, seems to be an ideal methodology. The human

    narrative, unhindered by the momentary pressures of

    life, needs to be the initial database upon which addi

    tional layers of substantive analysis may eventually

    be experimentally imposed.

    The reason such data, especially from regular ev

    eryday folks, have not been collected is obvious the

    data stream is so rich, and an empirical analysis so

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    14/17

    252

    complex, that only a few have had the heart to begin

    Dahl, 1998; Dahl, 1998). As always, there is the per

    sistent

    problem that

    the listener might unduly bias

    the mental

    flow

    with their own remarks, with the

    smallest nuance being able to sway the stream of free

    associations into different eddies and currents. There

    is also the possibility that without the natural verbal

    give and take that can only occur between humans,

    only a chaotic, unsystematic stream

    of

    data might

    emerge. Perhaps a few well-placed standardized ques

    tions would help steer the mind into desired channels

    that can be more easily analyzed. In any event, to

    my

    way of thinking,

    we

    need to give the strategy a vigor

    ous try, before abandoning hope. At present, the meth

    odological problems are not insurmountable.

    Now that

    we

    are in a computational age, where

    voice-recognition technologies and automated tran

    scription

    of

    ongoing narratives is possible, and content

    analysis programs have been created, even for the

    evaluation of emotional issues Pennebaker, Mayne,

    and Francis, 1997), the concept has a realistic chance

    of

    being widely implemented. Also, for the more sub

    tle psychodynamic issues, where layers of meaning

    are embedded in the narrative that no computer could

    yet decode, there may be many individuals, from the

    humanities, with remarkable language skills, who

    might be willing to participate

    as

    decoders in such

    projects. The data stream also needs to be analyzed

    from traditional psychoanalytic perspectives, and the

    three types of analysis need to be contrasted. Obvi

    ously, participants in such studies would have to agree

    to longer term time and emotional commitment than

    is common in most psychological experiments, and

    there might have to be a considerable learning phase

    in order for people

    to

    become comfortable in such

    situations. Participants will have

    to

    feel themselves

    to

    be compatriots in the search for knowledge, as op

    posed to being mere subjects as has long been

    rigu ur in more traditional psychological studies.

    As

    experimental manipulations, one might con

    sider various mood and motivational induction proce

    dures prior to analytic episodes. Also, instead

    of

    allowing a totally free stream of associations, it may

    be wise

    to

    utilize a few existential questions e.g.,

    What kind

    of

    person would you like

    to

    be?)

    to

    help

    guide the narrative

    flow

    onto some common issues.

    Eventually investigators may be able to devise a vari

    ety of standard challenges to systematically evaluate

    resulting emotional tendency. It would be important

    to

    have good emotional-personality measures on sub

    jects to evaluate output differences

    as

    a function of

    temperament. It would also be good to monitor the

    Jaak Panksepp

    facial expressions and changes in vocal prosody

    as

    people systematically share their lives. The utility

    of

    drug manipulations will,

    of

    course, be enormous, es

    pecially

    if

    stable baselines can be established e.g.,

    Knutson et

    aI

    1998). Indeed, an enormous number

    of

    psychobiological predictions from animal studies

    can already be generated for such interventions Pank

    sepp, 1998a). The systematic study of psychiatric and

    neurological patients should be highly informative

    e.g., Solms, 1997). In any event, the establishment

    of

    adequate psychological descriptions

    of

    normal human

    mental activities, in their full richness, seems to be a

    project deserving a great deal

    of

    experimental atten

    tion.

    f

    such methodologies proved to be effective,

    they may eventually be capable of being used for diag

    nostic and prognostic purposes in a new era

    of

    human

    istic psychiatry.

    The issue of how accessible the human mind is

    to

    systematic measurement i.e., Uttal, 2000) must re

    main an open issue until a great deal more research

    has been conducted. I am optimistic that some credible

    and replicable signals, especially in the study

    of

    basic

    emotional systems, will emerge from such analyses

    once they are adequately implemented. Psychoanalytic

    approaches,

    as

    molded by the constraints

    of

    empiri

    cism, provide an excellent model

    of

    how we might

    proceed. Of course, it will be impossible to fathom

    the internal structures of mind simply from an analysis

    of

    input and output functions since there are an infin

    ity

    of

    intervening possibilities). However, with solid

    neuroscience conceptions concerning the sources

    of

    the basic emotions and motivations shared by all mam

    malian brains e.g., MacLean, 1990; Panksepp, 1998a;

    Damasio, 1999), we should be able to make great

    strides in analyzing the Niagara of psychoanalytic data

    that could be extracted from human narratives. It will

    be fascinating to see how basic affective processes, the

    natural kinds of the mind, guide the environmentally

    constructed meanderings of the cognitive stream. It

    will be interesting

    to

    see whether many psychoanalytic

    concepts like the defense mechanisms of repression

    and reaction formation can be demonstrated to be nat

    ural kinds of the brain-mind, or whether they are sim

    ply derivative processes of how memory fields are

    constructed.

    Also, when

    we

    begin to take a deep emo

    tional-motivational perspective to human mind, the

    notion that introspective reports have to be veridical

    descriptions of relationships in the external world be

    comes less relevant than they might be from more

    strictly cognitive vantages e.g., Kahneman, Slovic,

    and Tversky, 1982; Nisbett and Wilson, 1997). The

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    15/17

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    human mind may have more affective irrationality

    in it than logical clarity. Experimental psychologists

    have too often wished to ignore that, but it should be

    studied rather than being seen

    s

    a shortcoming. In

    any event, to determine whether stable patterns

    of

    cog

    nitive activities emerge during emotional states,

    psy-

    choethology

    needs to be given a fair empirical hearing.

    Coda

    I am in complete agreement with Whittle in his call

    for a new pluralism in the way in which we approach

    the systematic study of the human mind, especially its

    emotional forces. Brain psychodynamics can only be

    realistically approached from many concurrent, and

    mutually respectful, points

    of

    view. A long time ago,

    physicists realized that they could not understand the

    hidden underbelly

    of

    nature by simply ascribing to one

    perspective. Subatomic entities needed to be conceptu

    alized not only s particles but also s wave dynamics.

    We are now approaching a comparable stage

    of

    intel

    lectual development in the brain-mind sciences. Every

    brain-mind phenomenon must be approached from

    multiple points of view. The idea that one should dis

    card psychological analysis completely in preference

    for a neural

    eliminativism

    (Churchland, 1995), al

    though rather popular among neuroscientists and per

    haps even appropriate for many brain phenomena, is

    a view that encourages polarization of attitudes as op

    posed to a realistic, multidimensional confrontation

    with many of the most important mind-brain issues.

    Although mental events, s typically conceptual

    ized in psychology, often do not help much in ex

    plaining specific behavioral acts, we often fail to

    acknowledge that adaptive actions are often long-term

    processes rather than ones that can be captured by brief

    laboratory experiments.

    If

    we recognized that mind is

    just another way of viewing the complexity of the

    brain in action (Searle, 1983), we would be more

    tempted to open up the intellectual campfire round

    which we share our perspectives rather than narrowing

    it. Unfortunately, a penetrating institutionalized

    strength

    of

    will to stand behind the utility

    of

    pluralist

    points

    of

    view has yet to emerge within our prevailing

    scientific disciplines. This, I believe, simply reflects

    our desire to divide and conquer rather than our desire

    to create a rich banquet

    of

    mind-brain science that can

    nourish our desire to understand the human condition.

    The basic emotions are a poignant case in point.

    Experimental psychology, especially its cognitive and

    behavioral neuroscience forms, have not been able to

    5

    construct a realistic way to discuss and analyze such

    important issues. We are stuck in dualistic modes

    of

    thought where emotional feelings supposedly have no

    causal efficacy (because they are matters

    of mind )

    and all

    of

    the weight

    of

    responsibility is placed on

    supposedly nonfeeling neural circuits, with perhaps a

    causally inefficacious (epiphenomenal) form

    of

    feel

    ing

    emerging from higher cortical systems that deal

    informationally with tokens

    of

    subcortical infor

    mation (e.g., LeDoux, 1996).

    Is it not much more reasonable, at least from an

    evolutionary point

    of

    view, that emotional feelings are

    part and parcel

    of

    ancient instinctual neural systems in

    action? In other words, emotional feelings arise rather

    directly from the arousal

    of

    certain primitive neural

    systems (Panksepp, 1998b). That is the view that most

    of

    the critical evidence is pointing toward. In my esti

    mation, no dualistic-type readout by a higher mind is

    needed to create affective states, even though higher

    memorial abilities are surely able to extend those neu

    ral activities, those feelings, in space and time, as to

    kens in working memory so

    s

    to permit more

    sophisticated cognitive strategies.

    A moving image for one fundamental emotional

    process that I have studied extensively by focusing on

    the separation-distress circuitry

    of the vertebrate brain

    comes from James Saunders play ext Time ll Sing

    or ou and it goes like this:

    There lies behind every thing, and you can believe

    this or not as you wish, a certain quality which we

    may call grief. I t s always there, just under the sur

    face, just behind the f ~ d e sometimes very nearly

    exposed, so that you can dimly see the shape

    of

    it

    as you can see sometimes through the surface

    of

    an

    ornamental pond on a still day, the dark, gross, inhu

    man outline

    of

    a carp gliding slowly past; when you

    realize suddenly that the carp were always there be

    low the surface, even while the water sparkled in the

    sunshine, and while you patronized the quaint ducks

    and the supercilious swans, the carp were down there,

    unseen. It bides its time, this quality. And if you do

    catch a glimpse of it, you may pretend not to notice

    or you may turn suddenly away and romp with your

    children on the grass, laughing for no reason. The

    name

    of

    this quality is grief.

    By studying the neural shapes and dynamics

    of

    these

    carp that glide under the surface

    of

    our every

    day experiences, we can come to terms with the intrin

    sic coherences

    of the affective mechanism that

    evolution created with the mammalian brain. We can

  • 7/25/2019 23 on Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience and a Ps

    16/17

    5

    finally understand the urges and pleasures of sex, the

    pains of

    hunger and cold, and the pleasures

    of

    food and

    warmth.

    We

    can come to terms with th