08 carruthers & ariovitch 2004

Upload: nannydsc

Post on 04-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    1/26

    Annu. Rev. Sociol. 2004. 30:2346doi: 10.1146/annurev.soc.30.012703.110538

    Copyright c 2004 by Annual Reviews. All rights reservedFirst published online as a Review in Advance on January 7, 2004

    THE SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS

    Bruce G. Carruthers and Laura AriovichDepartment of Sociology, Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois 60208;

    email: [email protected]

    Key Words economic sociology, law, transition economies, intellectual property

    I Abstract Property rights matter for their effects on economic inequality andeconomic performance, and they unfold at the intersection of law, the state, politics,and the economy. Five dimensions of property are discussed: the objects of property(what can be owned), the subjects of property (who can own), the uses of property (whatcan be done with it), the enforcement of rights (how property rules are maintained),and the transfer of property (how property moves between different owners). We offerexamples of how property rights systems vary along these dimensions and how theychange over time. We illustrate the arguments with two contemporary empirical cases:the transition economies of Eastern and Central Europe, Russia, and China, and thetransformation of intellectual property rights.

    INTRODUCTION

    Property is ubiquitous. The idea of private property suffuses classic liberal thought.

    Property rights lie at the intersection of law, economy, the state, and culture.

    For example, intellectual property rights (IPR) concern leading-sector industries

    like biotechnology and computers; property constitutes the foundation for many

    kinds of inequality; and property rights preoccupy scholars studying the transition

    economies of Eastern and Central Europe. And yet contemporary sociology has

    said much less about property than its centrality warrants, largely ceding the topic

    to economics and law.

    Ownership involves socially recognized economic rights. Property is that over

    which such rights obtain, and owners are those who possess the rights. In a sense,

    property concerns the dyadic relationship between people and things. Sir William

    Blackstone famously defined property as: . . . that sole and despotic dominion

    which one man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in total

    exclusion of the right of any other individual in the universe(Blackstone 1766,

    p. 2). His definition poses private ownership as an individuals exclusive control

    over property. Yet despite its ideological power, this dyadic conception misses

    the social and political dimensions of property (Fligstein 2001, p. 33; Shipton

    1994, p. 349). The right to control, govern, and exploit things entails the power

    to influence, govern, and exploit people (Roemer 1989). Owners of productive

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    2/26

    24 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    assets can prevent nonowners from using them, and thereby shape nonowners

    life-chances. Furthermore, what separates ownership from mere possession is the

    fact that others recognize ownership rights, either directly or through a formal

    legal system. If private property appears to be dyadic, in reality it always involvestriadic relationships.

    Swedberg (2003, p. 203) observes that property has not been much studied by

    sociologists. Property rights are discussed by some (e.g., Emigh 1999, Fligstein

    2001, Sorensen 2000, Stinchcombe 1983), and they figure into studies of transi-

    tion economies (e.g., Nee 1992, Stark 1996, Walder 1992), class analysis (Wright

    2002), comparative capitalisms (Dore 2000, Hall & Soskice 2001), and specific

    types of property (Patterson 1982), but they have not received an encompassing so-

    ciological treatment. By contrast, economists have long been interested in property

    rights (Alchian & Demsetz 1973, Barzel 1989, Libecap 1989, Eggertsson 1990).Sociologys neglect is unfortunate, for the founders of sociology knew that property

    rights have great sociological relevance (Weber 1981; Marx & Engels 1947, pp. 79

    81; Durkheim 1992, p. 121170). The most obvious connection, Marx recognized,

    is with social stratification. Ownership constitutes one of the most enduring di-

    mensions of inequality (Earle 2000). Property in modern societies is maintained

    by the legal system, and so directly implicates law and the state, but informal prop-

    erty rights emerge as practices decouple from formal institutions. Many instances

    of dramatic political change involved shifts in property rights (e.g., the Russian

    and French Revolutions). In addition, to exchange property rights is the elementalmarket transaction, and so property grows in importance with expanding markets.

    We begin with Reeves (1986, p. 11) definition of property. Owner A owns

    property P if and only if:

    1) A has the right to use P;

    2) A may exclude others from using P;

    3) A may transfer rights defined by rules 1 and 2 to others by consent.

    Property involves a bundle of rights, including the rights of usufruct, exclusivity,and alienability. The entire bundle can be held by one person or divided among

    multiple parties. Property rights confer power. They are rules that constrain and

    enable, and they locate decision-making power over assets. Property rights vary

    over time (Horwitz 1977) and between countries in terms of who (or what) can be an

    owner. Similarly, they differ according to what may be owned, and what constitutes

    legitimate use of property. Property also varies in how it is transferred, alienated,

    or enforced, and in its exclusivity (private versus public).

    DIMENSIONS OF PROPERTY

    Below we discuss five basic dimensions to show how property varies. Property

    systems often cluster into familiar types (e.g., private versus communal property,

    contingent versus absolute property), and recombinations among these produce

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    3/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 25

    new types (Stark 1996). Then we consider propertys implications for inequality

    and economic performance. Lastly, we apply our framework to discuss transitional

    economies and intellectual property.

    Objects of Property

    What can be owned? Different societies give different answers, but none permits

    everything to be owned. The inclusion of new objects or the exclusion of old ones

    is a process variably shaped by political, cultural, economic, and technological

    factors. Changes in the objects of property depend on commodification and de-

    commodification, and on permeable boundaries between legal and illegal markets.

    In agrarian societies, land is key for production. Common law property rights

    reflect the importance of land during the Middle Ages when the law originated

    (Baker 1979, p. 193). Law developed for tangible property had to be adapted to ac-

    commodate new forms of intangible property. The crime of trespass originally con-

    cerned unauthorized entry onto someones physical property, but it was extended

    to cover unauthorized access onto a computer system (Nimmer & Krauthaus 1992,

    pp. 118119). In the early twentieth century, U.S. copyright laws were expanded

    to cover motion pictures and other new media (Merges 2000).

    Various social, cultural, and economic processes alter the set of objects that

    can be legally owned. For many millennia, human beings were property (Patterson

    1982). U.S. abolition meant that humans could no longer be owned and caused

    slaveholders to lose much of their wealth. In the past, ideas were not something

    to own (during the Middle Ages, knowledge was viewed as a gift from God), but

    with patent, trademark, and copyright laws, designs, symbols, and forms of writing

    could become property (Hesse 2002). And current U.S. law states that laws of na-

    ture, physical phenomena, and abstract ideas cannot be patented (Hunt 2001, p. 6).

    Recent developments have allowed living animals, bioengineered bacteria, fi-

    nancial formulae, and business methods to become patentable (Hall 2003, Kevles

    2002). IPR does not expand monotonically, however, for people sought to abolish

    patents in the nineteenth century (Janis 2002), and similar arguments are made

    today to weaken these property rights (Heller & Eisenberg 1998, Lessig 2001).

    Outside of IPR, new forms of property, like SO2 emissions permits for example,

    help shift U.S. environmental policy toward markets (Levin & Espeland 2002).

    The development of radio and television coincided with commodification of the

    electromagnetic radiation spectrum.

    Early objects of property were physical things like land and cattle, but property

    now includes many intangibles (bonds, shares, trademarks, patents). An overall

    shift occurred away from tangible and toward intangible forms of property, but

    intangible property has existed for centuries. Roman law acknowledged incor-

    poreal things as property (Justinians Inst. 1987, p. 61), but also stipulated that

    some things could not be owned (e.g., sacred or religious objects; see Justinians

    Inst. 1987, p. 55). Venal or proprietary offices were common in early modern Eu-

    ropean states and turned owners into political supporters and frequently also into

    public creditors (Ertman 1997, p. 102). By making public functions a matter of

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    4/26

    26 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    ownership rather than merit, however, venality could undercut the efficiency of

    public organizations.

    Why some objects can be owned and others cannot depends on culture and for-

    mal law. Objects possessing powerful, noncommercial social meanings are oftendeemed inappropriate for ownership. For example, traditional Native American

    conceptions of land clashed with those of European settlers, who viewed land as

    private property (McEvoy 1998). Today, tribal lands are owned by Native Amer-

    icans, but the cultural meaning of land precludes its treatment as a mere commodity

    (Espeland 1998). The adoption and enforcement of modern IPR law in contem-

    porary China has been undercut by the fact that Imperial Chinese law and culture

    did not conceive of ideas as property (Alford 1995). Current attempts to patent

    human genetic material violate moral sensibilities about the commercialization of

    life (Bright 1995, Drahos 1999). The appropriateness of property status for objectsis more than just dichotomous, however, for even granted that something can be

    owned, legal rules and social norms still influence how it is owned. For example,

    medieval scholars did not doubt that things could be property, but they disputed

    whether God gave the things of nature to be owned privately or communally (Wood

    2002, pp. 1741).

    Subjects of Property

    Who may own? The set of potential owners varies across societies. One importantdifference lies between natural and fictive persons, but these two groups subdivide

    further. No society grants full ownership rights to all natural persons, and the rights

    of fictive persons often differ across public/private or profit/nonprofit lines. Fur-

    thermore, many societies recognize ownership by households, lineages, villages,

    kin groups, or other collectivities. A single owner often owns multiple pieces of

    property, and multiple owners may have rights in the same piece of property. Such

    arrangements are common in many societies (see, e.g., Kumar 1985), and reach a

    high degree of contractual specificity in time-share condominiums.

    Natural persons who are foreigners or minors may enjoy only limited ownershiprights, or even no rights at all. People who are owned (slaves) do not themselves

    have full rights to own (Patterson 1982, p. 182). Sometimes specific owner-property

    pairings are prohibited, as with restrictions on foreign investment in strategic in-

    dustries, felon ownership of handguns, or minority ownership of homes in white

    neighborhoods (Rice 1968). Such prohibitions have strong implications for pat-

    terns of exchange. Ownership by natural persons poses problems of what to do

    with property that outlives its owner. Some societies tried to send property

    along with the deceased owner (for example, by burying it with the corpse or

    burning it on the funeral pyre), but the disposition of durable property like landwas governed by rules of inheritance.

    Patriarchy and property are closely connected. Under traditional common law,

    ownership rights varied by gender, and upon marriage a wifes property became

    her husbands (marital status did not matter for men). Marriage was not just a

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    5/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 27

    liability for women, however, because widows had special claims on family prop-

    erty, and marriage settlements also offered wives some protection. Only during

    the nineteenth century did legal reforms bestow full property rights on American

    married women (Salmon 1986). The English practice of primogeniture favoredsons over daughters in inheritance. In early modern China, property rights also

    favored men (Bernhardt 1999). In general, differences over property rights have

    been a central axis of gender inequality (Salmon 1986, Staves 1990) and remain

    so in much of the developing world (Agarwal 1994).

    Since the late nineteenth century, general laws of incorporation have helped to

    make fictive individuals like corporations increasingly important as owners (Per-

    row 2002, pp. 3640; Roy 1997). Corporations function simultaneously as sub-

    jects of property (they own) and objects (they are owned). Some corporations have

    owned property for many centuries (e.g., the Catholic Church), but the prolifera-tion of corporations has made fictive owners more salient. Unlike natural persons,

    fictive persons can continue indefinitely (they possess perpetual succession), and

    so the problem of inheritance need never arise. Through a steady accumulation over

    centuries, the medieval Church became Europes biggest landowner. Corporations

    cannot die, but they can go bankrupt and be liquidated (in which case the property

    goes to the creditors). Corporations also enjoy limited liability, which means that

    shareholders have limited responsibility for corporate debts (Moss 2002).

    Institutional change producesnew combinations of owners and property. Thanks

    to the Bayh-Dole Act of 1980, American universities can now own patent rightsin intellectual property produced by federally funded research. Universities have

    acquired an interest in strong IPR, and their research and pedagogical missions

    are influenced by commercial interests, particularly in areas like biotechnology.

    Science and commerce became conjoined in universities (Powell & Owen-Smith

    1998), and this has shifted the metric of academic success from publications to

    patents (Owen-Smith 2003).

    Articulation of Use

    Usufructuary rights stipulate what can be done with property. As property has

    evolved, so have use rights. Clearly one does not use a negotiable security in the

    same manner as a piece of land: Owners use corporate shares to make claims on

    residual income and to vote in company elections. Pure absolute private ownership

    (sole and despotic dominion) supposes that owners can do whatever they please,

    but use is almost never unlimited. Sometimes, people possess very specific use

    rights, allowing them to exploit property in one particular way. For example,

    different rights over the traditional English commons included the right to hunt,

    fish, cut turf, gatherfirewood, cultivate, graze animals, and fell trees (Neeson 1993;Simpson 1986, pp. 107108). Persons and groups might hold one or two of these

    valuable rights, but seldom more.

    The enclosure movement turned the English commons into private property,

    but that still did not allow owners unrestrained use. Use of real estate is commonly

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    6/26

    28 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    regulated to restrict what owners may do with their property [e.g., requirements to

    build houses with brick or stone rather than flammable wood (Plotkin 1987, p. 77)].

    Many municipalities zone real estate for different uses (commercial, residential,

    etc.) and so dictate spatial patterns of land use. In the United States, the policepowers of government allow it to impinge on private property to protect public

    safety, health, and morals (Ely 1992, p. 60). Eminent domain gives government

    the right to condemn and seize private property (subject to due process and just

    compensation).

    Use of some property requires that owners be properly qualified: One cannot

    drive a car, fly an airplane, or operate a medical hospital without a license. Such li-

    censing is a long-standing American practice (Novak 1996, pp. 9095). Ownership

    may also involve an obligation to pay taxes. All regulations shape how owners use

    their property (in intended and unintended ways), and government intervention inmarkets can repose not in visible regulatory agencies but in the details of property

    rights (Campbell & Lindberg 1990). Some view such regulation as necessary for

    market stability (Polanyi 1944).

    Not all restraints are imposed externally through formal government regula-

    tion. Informal and internal restrictions on the use of corporate property by share-

    holders are reflected in stakeholder models of the firm (Donaldson 1995). In the

    Anglo-Saxon corporate model, owner-shareholders ultimately control the firm,

    although they cede control to their agents, the managers. Stakeholder models,

    in contrast, recognize the importance of other constituents of the firm (employ-ees, creditors, customers, suppliers, etc.), who also influence what a firm does

    (Freeland 2001, Ziegler 2000). What owners do with their property is constrained

    by these other constituencies, whether or not the latter play a formal role in

    governance.

    Some restraints are adopted consensually, through contracts. Restrictive cove-

    nants in loan contracts let creditors constrain how debtors use borrowed money

    (Smith & Warner 1979). Fast-food franchise agreements constrain how owner-

    operators may operate their franchise [this helps achieve extreme uniformity of

    appearance, service, and taste (see Hadfield 1990)]. Other constraints are externaland coercive, but not strictly legal. The production and operation of many kinds

    of equipment, ranging from electrical lighting to steam boilers, are regulated by

    private standard-setting bodies (e.g., Underwriters Laboratory, which currently

    promulgates over 800 different standards). Owners who fail to conform to these

    standards are not acting illegally, but they will find it impossible to obtain insurance

    (Cheit 1990). Some private standards now have a global reach (Braithwaite &

    Drahos 2000).

    Informal, social influences on property use are legion. They include the noblesse

    oblige that comes with wealth. As Ostrower (1995) documents, the culture ofAmerican elites makes certain philanthropic activities crucial to their identity,

    obliging social elites to give away part of their property. But all individual owners,

    not just elites, have reference groups and communities that influence what property

    they acquire and how they use it (Grassby 1995).

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    7/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 29

    Enforcement of Rights

    The social rules that constitute property are neither self-evident nor self-enforcing.

    Who specifies and enforces these rules? According to North (1990), it is the state.

    Specializing in coercion, the state is uniquely qualified to ensure compliance with

    all kinds of rules, including property. For North, the state specifies rules serving

    its own fiscal interests in tax revenues. This linkage between government and

    property has long been recognized (e.g., by Adam Smith in the Wealth of Nations),

    and implies that property and politics are necessarily connected.

    Enforcement varies with property. Enforcement of private property is more

    intensive than for communal property (because the latter involves open access).

    The means for protecting private land will not work when used to protect intangible

    property, like patents. Weak or failing states often cannot maintain property rights,

    and so citizens who wish to protect their property and transfer it securely often rely

    on private enforcement services. Informal coercion is common in contemporary

    Russia, and protection can turn into control as racketeers take over the firms

    they protect (Volkov 2002, p. 51).

    North focuses on formal legal enforcement, but many rules are enforced infor-

    mally, and some compliance occurs voluntarily. Voluntary compliance depends

    on the perceived legitimacy of the rules, and without legitimacy enforcement is

    difficult. As Thompson (1975) argued, much resistance in eighteenth-century Eng-

    land to private ownership of the former commons stemmed from the perception

    that it was illegitimate. The authorities increased coercion by turning many prop-

    erty crimes into capital crimes, but people continued to resist. De facto property

    rights also diverge from de jure rights in the developing world, where on paper

    women often possess property rights equal to men, but in practice they have sub-

    stantially weaker rights (Agarwal 1994). Smarts (1986) discussion of squatter

    housing in Hong Kong demonstrates the effectiveness of informal enforcement.

    Morales (1993) found that community norms and sanctions were effective in en-

    forcing informal property rights over space in an urban flea market.

    The formalization of property does not just crystallize claims but offers sig-nificant opportunities for redistribution. The land registries introduced during the

    early modern era and in todays developing world formalized property claims, but

    they also allowed opportunistic individuals to expand their claims. Complex cus-

    tomary rights were seldom translated perfectly into the new system (Scott 1998,

    pp. 3336). But formalization can also help those with informal rights. Mod-

    ern intellectual property law potentially can protect practitioners of traditional

    medicine and indigenous farmers from uncompensated appropriation of their valu-

    able knowledge by pharmaceutical and agribusiness companies (Cleveland &

    Murray 1997; Zhuge 2003, unpublished manuscript), although this depends ontheir legal and political resources (Brush 1993, p. 664).

    Despite informal arrangements, the modern state remains a primary locus of

    property enforcement. With the emergence of global markets, however, the locus of

    enforcement is shifting to an international level. International treaties, agreements,

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    8/26

    30 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    and institutions now specify and protect property rights, and the politics of prop-

    erty has shifted to different arenas (Braithwaite & Drahos 2000, pp. 5457). The

    Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement of 1994

    established rules to govern intellectual property as part of the trade negotiationsthat established the World Trade Organization (Maskus 2000). Less encompass-

    ing agreements were also negotiated during the nineteenth century (e.g., Paris and

    Berne Conventions on copyrights and industrial property rights).

    Transfer of Rights

    Property rights are established and extinguished, and they move between owners.

    Today, many transfers are accomplished through market exchanges, but other types

    also occur. Consider the establishment of property, when objects not subject to

    rights become owned by someone. Physical property, like land, which belongsnominally to the king, ruler, or government (by treaty, conquest, fiat, or some

    other method) may be distributed to settlers, political supporters, or clients. More

    interesting are situations in which individuals unilaterally seize land as squatters

    rather than receive it in a grant. Much of Australia was settled via squatting and

    encroachment by white settlers, whose illegal actions could not be controlled by

    a distant government (Weaver 1996). The state played catch-up, giving de jure

    status to de facto facts on the ground.

    Intangible property does not precede the property rights that govern it. Patents,

    for example, are created through a bureaucratic process in a government patent

    office. In the United States, innovations must satisfy three criteria to be patented:

    utility, novelty, and nonobviousness (Hunt 2001). Like beauty, these criteria exist

    in the eyes of the beholderthe U.S. Patent and Trademark Office (USPTO)

    and their application and interpretation have evolved (Lerner 2002). Considerable

    cross-national variation characterizes patent office standards and practiceswhat

    is patentable in one country may not be elsewhere (Somaya 2000). For example,

    Amazon.com obtained a U.S. patent for its one-click purchase method but the

    companys patent application was denied in Japan.

    Intellectual property not only appears at discrete points in time (when a patent is

    granted, a trademark filed, etc.), but it also lapses. Unlike other forms of property,

    intellectual property rights are only temporary (e.g., U.S. patents last for 20 years).

    Tangible property rights can also be extinguished. For example, lost property that

    is turned in to the authorities and unclaimed often becomes the finders [but these

    rules vary substantially over time and across jurisdictions (West 2003)]. A more

    significant termination of property rights occurs in formal bankruptcy, where the

    assets belonging to an individual or corporate debtor are distributed to creditors

    (Carruthers & Halliday 1998, Skeel 2001), and the debtors property rights are

    extinguished.

    Almost all property is alienable in some measure and so shifts between different

    owners. Its movement may occur through bilateral market exchange or as a unilat-

    eral gift. Gift exchange helps to build and sustain social relations, and so it is deeply

    embedded in social structure (Caplow 1982). But even market exchange is shaped

    by social factors Purnell (1999) for example discusses informal prohibitions on

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    9/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 31

    the sale of land to outsiders in Mexico. Property also shifts intergenerationally

    through inheritance. Normally this occurs after the owners death and may or

    may not be governed by a formal will, but bequests also occur inter vivos (e.g.,

    investment in a childs college education, dowries, marriage settlements).The state has not been the only enforcer of inheritance rules. For centuries,

    inheritance was heavily influenced by the Church and ecclesiastical law (Berman

    1983, pp. 230237). Many inheritance rules (e.g., primogeniture, impartible inher-

    itance) favor particular heirs (sons over daughters, close kin over distant kin, eldest

    sons over others) and thus structure how patterns of inequality are reproduced in-

    tergenerationally (Spring 1993). Inheritance rules differ significantly across legal

    traditions and even within the same country (Erickson 1990, Shammas et al. 1987).

    Societies that support testamentary freedom allow the decedent to determine how

    property will be distributed post mortem, and this allows sentiment and otherpersonal factors to influence inheritance.

    IMPLICATIONS OF PROPERTY

    The five dimensions just summarized lay out the important ways in which property

    varies, but propertys importance stems from its consequences. Two in particular

    have been of interest to sociologists: inequality and economic performance.

    Inequality

    Property rules govern access and control over things of value, and consequently

    undergird social inequality (Brudner & White 1997). Most stratification research

    focuses on occupational and income differences, although Sorensen (2000) and

    Wright (2002) make property rights the center of their class analysis. Property

    rights matter most for wealth inequality, which tends to be more extreme and stable

    than income inequality (Jianakoplos & Menchik 1997, Keister 2000). Inheritance

    concerns how unequal accumulations of property are transmitted down through

    succeeding generations.

    Unequal ownership of certain kinds of property engenders other inequalities.

    Secure title over land allows it to function as collateral for loans andhence generates

    access to credit (Islam 1995; Soto 2000, p. 39). U.S. racial differences in the level

    and composition of household wealth have been a topic of recent interest (Conley

    1999, Oliver & Shapiro 1997). Racial patterns in home ownership lead to other

    differences because education and jobs are tied to residential geography (Massey &

    Denton 1993, Stuart 2003). Although dejure property rights are now formally equal

    between whites and blacks, persistent differences in wealth and home ownership

    show how substantially de facto property rights can diverge from the ideal of

    equality (Munnell et al. 1996).

    Sometimes, property rights are used to alter patterns of social inequality. Dra-

    matic changes like mass privatization in the transition economies of the 1990s,

    or the abolition of feudal property during the French Revolution, were clearly

    intended to alter the social distribution of wealth Other manipulations have been

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    10/26

    32 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    more specific. In the early eighteenth century, Englands parliament imposed part-

    ible inheritance on Catholic Ireland and forbade land sales from Protestants to

    Catholics (Staves 1990, p. 93). By prohibiting primogeniture, the chief strategy

    for reproducing aristocratic landholdings, and by proscribing land purchases, theEnglish hoped that within two or three generations their opponents, the Irish aris-

    tocracy, would have so subdivided their estates among their heirs as to be reduced

    to yeoman farmer status.

    The extent to which wealth depends on inheritance (as opposed to savings) is a

    matter of some debate (Altonji et al. 2000), but by most estimates a considerable

    proportion of wealth is inherited (Gale & Scholz 1994, Keister & Moller 2000).

    The reproduction of inequality depends on the heritability of assets, which in

    turn depends on rules of inheritance, demographic and economic circumstances

    (number of surviving children, divisibility and liquidity of assets), strategies ofinheritance, and the unit of social reproduction (nuclear families, patrilineages,

    villages, etc.). Longhofer (1993) shows how Mennonites adapted their inheritance

    practices to reproduce their community as they migrated from Russia to the United

    States. Marcus (1980) describes the use of formal trusts to maintain elite Galveston

    families through multiple generations. Giesey (1977) shows that venal offices in

    old regime France were part of the family patrimony, to be passed down through

    the generations (see Adams 1994 on the United Provinces).

    Intergenerational transmission of wealth also depends on formal and informal

    rules governing the legitimacy of inequality and the ability of the wealthy to passon their assets. In the United States, estate taxes influence how wealthy families

    make their bequests (Brownlee 2000), whereas Islamic economies grapple with

    Koranic strictures against excessive wealth inequality (Kuran 1995). Intergenera-

    tional conflict occurs as testators try to restrict the rights enjoyed by inheritors so

    as to preserve the estate for subsequent generations (Alexander 1997, Chapter 10).

    Family trusts are designed not only to avoid taxes, but also to protect wealth from

    spendthrift heirs. Inheritance rules that treat heirs unequally facilitate the accumu-

    lation and preservation of capital (Nazzari 1995).

    Differences in property ownership beget different political interests. For ex-ample, most of the worlds intellectual property is owned by Europe, the United

    States, and Japan. Developing countries consume intellectual property. This dif-

    ference emerges in trade negotiations where advanced countries want strong IPR

    and developing countries seek weaker rules (Drahos 1999). Sub-Saharan African

    countries want weaker patents for HIV drugs so that they can offer cheaper medical

    treatment to their citizens (Nash 2000). Similar differences exist over copyright

    rules and intellectual piracy (Neigel 2000).

    PerformanceProperty rights determine who controls which resources and set the incentives

    that property owners face. According to the Coase Theorem, when there are

    no transaction costs, the initial allocation of property rights makes no difference

    for outcomes; rational actors will simply do what is most efficient (Coase 1960).

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    11/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 33

    Of course, transaction costs are never zero (and are seldom trivial), so property

    rights matter. This means that property rights influence economic performance,

    both within firms (Hart & Moore 1990) and without. Economists studying the

    connection between property rights and efficiency recommend private propertyas best for economic growth (Soto 2000) and have argued that property rights

    matter for resource exploitation, investment, growth, firm performance, credit,

    and innovation.

    As legal claims, property rights invoke Webers famous argument about the

    necessity of calculable law for capitalism (Weber 1981). Economists echo Weber

    in claiming that insecure property rights erode market activity (Johnson et al.

    2002, Soto 2000) and this claim has become a centerpiece of IMF and World Bank

    policymaking (Stiglitz 2002). Others, however, have shown that uncertain property

    rights are not nearly so problematic and may even be advantageous under somecircumstances (Wank 1999, Shipton 1994).

    Unlike communal property, private property internalizes externalities. The

    extension of private property is behind new market-based environmental pol-

    icy, in which SO2 emissions permits internalize the externality of air pollution

    (Levin & Espeland 2002). Private property is also touted as a solution to tropi-

    cal deforestation (Mendelsohn 1994). Internalization of externalities supposedly

    helps to avoid overexploitation of common-pool resources [the tragedy of the

    commons (see Eggertsson 1990, pp. 8491)]. However, even with fully specified

    private property, owners may not act rationally (Moxnes 1998), and people findmany other ways to avoid such tragedies (Ellickson 1991, Ostrom 1990). In the

    case of the English commons, informal social institutions effectively prevented

    overexploitation (Neeson 1993). Similarly, the effects of IPR have not been sorted

    out. Some claim that strong IPR produces high levels of foreign direct investment

    (Lee & Mansfield 1996) and encourages innovation and technological progress

    (Khan 1995). Others do not find simple relationships between patent strength and

    patent filings (Lerner 2002).

    DYNAMICS OF PROPERTY

    Property changes along the five dimensions discussed above. New forms of own-

    ership may be constituted, and new objects may appear and old ones disappear.

    Different uses of property can be discovered and old ones may be prohibited or

    become dormant. Changes in the transferability and heritability of property rights

    have important implications for markets and patterns of inequality. Altered prop-

    erty rights have an impact on the economy, but economic change can also transform

    property rights (Ensminger & Rutten 1991).

    Given that property rights depend on the state, dramatic transformations in prop-

    erty often coincide with big political changes: the French, Russian, and Chinese

    Revolutions all altered property as well as politics. The enclosure movement that

    privatized the English commons was largely accomplished through acts of Par-

    liament (Neeson 1993). The experience of the transition economies underscores

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    12/26

    34 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    that property rights are sustained by particular political constituencies (Stiglitz

    2002), and interest groups exploit their political clout to advocate favorable kinds

    of property rules. Political rhetoric, legal argumentation, and cultural framings are

    all used to push the envelope on what is legitimate property, especially in controver-sial areas like biotechnology. But the role of political factors, economic interests,

    and ideology are equally visible among older forms of property (Firmin-Sellers

    1995).

    Some economists offer efficiency explanations for how property rights change

    (Barzel 1989). Private property rights are more specific and costly to enforce than

    public property rights, but an increase in the value of a resource makes it efficient

    to move from public to private property rights. Others acknowledge that change

    does not always lead to greater efficiency (North 1990). In particular, property

    rights have distributional implications, and these unleash conflicts that can preventefficiency-enhancing changes (Kantor 1998, Knight 1992).

    Property rights sometimes change through legal transplantation, whereby legal

    codes developed in one jurisdiction diffuse to other jurisdictions. Sometimes legal

    transplants are part of the legacy of colonialism (Benton 2002), but many countries

    have modified their own legal codes to emulate foreign models. Japan, for example,

    looked to French and German law at the end of the nineteenth century, whereas

    India and Malaysia inherited common law from Britain (Pistor & Wellons 1998,

    pp. 3649). Formal adoption of a new property system starts off a variable and

    complex process of implementation that may result in substantial decoupling.Some legal transplants are more successful than others (Berkowitz et al. 2003).

    Transition Economies

    The transformation of property rights in transition economies illustrates our analy-

    sis. It reveals the political and institutional foundations of property because transi-

    tion governments have deliberately attempted to create the property rights appro-

    priate for a market economy. In most transition economies, privatization remains

    a central aspect of reform: Individuals and private organizations gained owner-ship over state-owned property. Transition economies involve new property ar-

    rangements and means of enforcement, with various consequences for economic

    performance and social stratification.

    Understanding property arrangements in transition economies requires unty-

    ing the bundle of property rights. King (2001, p. 39) concludes that rights to

    take residual profits, to control and organize production, and, to a lesser ex-

    tent, to sell property are mostly with nonstate actors. But private ownership

    in Eastern Europe often differs from that in the West: Control belongs to man-

    agers embedded in networks, but ownership resides in the firms themselves. Byearly 1996, 77.2% of large and mid-size Russian enterprises had been privatized

    (Blasi et al. 1997, p. 2). The result, however, was often a fragmented ownership

    structure and the consolidation of insider control (Heller 2001). By contrast, in

    China there has been little outright privatization. But extensive change of property

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    13/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 35

    rights created new ownership forms, including reformed state firms, government-

    management partnerships, leased public assets, and private companies (Walder &

    Oi 1999).

    The creation of a legal infrastructure often lagged behind economic change.Initially, policymakers in Eastern Europe and Russia followed Western advice

    and put privatization, liberalization, and macroeconomic stabilization ahead of

    legal reforms. Many believed that a legal framework would be superfluous before

    markets developed (Rapaczynski 1996). But after some disappointments, Western

    advisors began to recognize the importance of legal institutions for the success of

    transition (Clement & Murrell 2001, pp. 56).

    Cross-national comparisons suggest that the perceived security of property

    rights affects investment. Thus, Russia has fared worse than Poland in both re-

    spects (Johnson et al. 2002). In Russia, weak laws in combination with high busi-ness costs fostered mafia-type arrangements to protect property (Volkov 2002,

    p. 44). One cultural legacy of socialism, the perception of law as an arbitrary tool

    of the state, also encouraged extralegal means of enforcement (Hendley 1997,

    p. 237).

    Networks are another response to an inadequate legal framework (Boisot &

    Child 1996, Wank 1999). However, some scholars consider particularistic net-

    works a poor substitute for a formal legal system. Selecting business partners

    based on personal trust instead of market conditions discriminates against new

    entrants and reduces the number of partners (Hendley 1997, p. 243; Kali 2001,p. 223).

    One of the main goals of privatization was to encourage economic restruc-

    turing. Privatization would eliminate soft budget constraints and the agency

    problems associated with public ownership (Kornai 1992). Although there is ev-

    idence of company restructuring in Eastern Europe (Brada & Singh 1999), in

    Russia privatized companies seem locked in a vicious circle of capital starvation,

    asset stripping, and demodernization (King 2003, p. 15). Neoliberal thinkers

    blame lax monetary policy and continuous government subsidies for the failure

    to restructure (Aslund 1995). Others point to poor privatization policies, blamingthe rapid and massive transfer of state property in the absence of laws for cor-

    porate governance and the ownership structure (Black et al. 2000). Heller (2001,

    p. 297), for example, argues that privatization in Russia gave different groups of

    owners, including workers, managers, and local governments, enough power to

    block each other but not enough to restructure the firm in a value-enhancing

    direction.

    Some look to China to show how to run state companies efficiently. Accord-

    ing to Naughton (1995), Chinese authorities changed state managers incentives

    by relaxing the state monopoly in industry and establishing long-term profit con-tracting for state-owned companies. Walder (1995) argues that local governments

    are more likely than central authorities to impose hard budget constraints, espe-

    cially when they face market and fiscal pressures. However, some dispute Chinas

    achievements. They downplay Chinas recent economic growth as easy gains from

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    14/26

    36 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    limited reforms, and they also contend that many township and village companies,

    the engines of Chinese economic performance, are not really publicly owned but

    a case of hidden privatization (Putterman 1995).

    The transformation of property relations, combined with other reforms, alteredstratification patterns. According to Nees theory, marketization and new property

    rights reduce the advantage ofredistributive power and increase returns to human

    capital. Producers (including entrepreneurs, managers, and technicians) gain in

    relation to cadres (Nee 1996, pp. 916917; Nee & Matthews 1996). But Bian &

    Logan (1996) report increased income inequality in the early 1990s, when mar-

    ket reforms accelerated, with the winners including both workers with market

    connected jobs and workers with redistributive power. Income inequality also in-

    creased in Russia during the early 1990s (Gerber & Hout 1998). Market reform

    benefited proprietors but hurt professionals, skilled and unskilled manual work-ers, and technicians. Additionally, workers in the service branches did better than

    workers in manufacturing. In Gerber and Houts view, these outcomes are less

    consistent with Nees vision than with Burawoy & Krotovs (1992) model of

    merchant capitalism.

    Like other large-scale changes, privatization created winners and losers, set off

    conflicts, and had enduring social and political effects. Two circumstances made

    privatization politically challenging. First, various stakeholders, including branch

    ministers, regional authorities, managers, and workers had overlapping property

    claims on public companies (Aslund 1995, p. 240). Second, in Russia and East-ern Europe, privatization occurred simultaneously with political democratization

    (Przeworski 1991).

    Neoliberal advice to Russian and Eastern European reformers was based on

    the window of opportunity argument. Policymakers had to privatize quickly and

    comprehensively before interest groups could mount a counterattack and before the

    general public lost its faith in reform (Aslund 1995). Critics raised two arguments

    against this policy. First, fast privatization in an unfriendly business climate and

    before the creation of a legal infrastructure involves political risks. In Russia, pri-

    vatization of the largest companies led to a self-reinforcing kleptocracy devotedto asset stripping and opposed to the rule of law. The kleptocrats rise to power

    nurtured a political backlash against privatization (Black et al. 2000; Stiglitz 2002,

    pp. 157160). Second, a more gradual approach allows policymakers to experi-

    ment with limited changes without major social costs and then to build on initial

    successes. For example, the rural responsibility system in China, which involved

    a partial transfer of property rights to peasant families, set in motion a virtuous

    circle of reform, economic growth, political support for reform, and further reform

    (Naughton 1995, pp. 138142).

    Another dimension concerns the states role in company restructuring and eco-nomic growth. Extolling the virtues of state-led development in East Asia, scholars

    have called for active state engagement in industrial policy and company restruc-

    turing. From this perspective, reinventing planning, in fact, is the other side of

    effective privatizations coin (Amsden et al. 1994, p. 210). However, pervasive

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    15/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 37

    state weakness in Russia and Eastern Europe undermines the feasibility of state-led

    development (Stark & Bruszt 1998).

    Scholars disagree on the roles of elites and civil society in policy design and

    implementation. In the neoliberal conception, reformist elites carry out socialchange from above, avoiding compromise with interest groups and using demo-

    cratic institutions to legitimate a preset reform agenda (Aslund 1995, pp. 291311;

    Przeworski 1991, pp. 136187). Advocates of Asian-style industrial policy, in turn,

    seek to create an economically functional bureaucracy to control restructuring,

    privatization, and then regulation and guidance of efficient enterprises (Amsden

    et al. 1994, p. 210). Some scholars dispute the possibility of combining democ-

    racy and economic development in transitional economies. For Burawoy & Krotov

    (1992, pp. 3336), the withdrawal of the party-state aggravated the distortions of

    the socialist economy, and the task of building market institutions is too dauntingfor liberal democracy. In contrast, Stark & Bruszt (1998, p. 135) dismiss social

    change from above, arguing that deliberative associations, connecting local gov-

    ernments, banks, firms, and community actors, should lead property transformation

    and company restructuring.

    Some authors address the connections among institutions, politics, and property

    transformation. Stark & Bruszt (1998, p. 101) conclude that different paths of ex-

    trication from state socialism brought about different forms of interest mediation,

    which produced divergent privatization strategies. Appel (2000) emphasizes ideo-

    logical variables. In contrast to Russia, anticommunist ideology in the Czech Re-public eroded interest groups capacity to affect the privatization program. Roland

    (2002), however, stresses geopolitics. Whereas transition in Russia meant the loss

    of the Soviet empire, in Central Europe it created the opportunity to join Western

    Europe. Central European nations geopolitical position enhanced the credibility

    of market reforms, cementing government authority and strengthening property

    rights.

    Intellectual Property

    Intellectual property illustrates the political, economic, legal, and cultural pro-

    cesses through which property rules in capitalist economies are extended into

    new realms. Intellectual property rights have existed since the first patent laws

    (Venice passed one in 1474), but recent developments in biotechnology, computer

    software, and information processing have subverted older rules (Merges 2000).

    For example, computer programs are like text written in an artificial language.

    As property, text is traditionally protected by copyright law. But computer pro-

    grams also embody algorithms, and so resemble patentable industrial procedures

    (Nalley 2000). Which applies, patent or copyright law? Or consider that bioengi-neers can now genetically modify forms of life. Traditionally, products of nature

    could not be patented (Eisenberg 2002, p. 4), but after the U.S. Supreme Court

    upheld the patentability of genetically engineered organisms in the 1980 Diamond

    v. Chakrabarty decision, and after the USPTO patented an animal in 1988, the

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    16/26

    38 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    distinction between artificial and natural became much fuzzier (Kevles 2002).

    These developments also challenge cultural prohibitions against the commodifi-

    cation of life (Andrews & Nelkin 2001). Furthermore, the extreme mobility of

    informational products eludes the political boundaries that make clear which ju-risdiction, and therefore which property rules, applies. Samuelson (1996) offers

    the example of a digitized, colorized silent movie, part of the U.S. public do-

    main, uploaded onto an Internet server and then accessed by someone in France

    or Germany. The movie may not be in the public domain in Germany because

    that country offers longer periods of protection than the United States, and to col-

    orize a black-and-white movie violates French rules about the integrity of artistic

    products. Which countrys law applies? Is the movie illegal?

    Intellectual property rights today reflect a set of changes: new objects and sub-

    jects of property, a shifting locus of enforcement, and new political coalitionsfavoring (or opposing) particular property rights. These changes unfold at the na-

    tional and international levels. Consider the objects of intellectual property: thanks

    to scientific and technological progress, biotechnological and pharmaceutical re-

    searchers invent products with enormous commercial potential. But to capture

    those profits, new products must be brought within intellectual property law and

    constituted as legitimate objects of property. Similarly, the development of com-

    puters and networks has not only supported a large software industry, but also

    made it much easier to copy and distribute digital products (Healy 2002; Shapiro &

    Varian 1999, pp. 34). To profit, producers of informational products seek effectiveenforcement of their property rights and deterrence of cyber-piracy.

    In general, those who create informational, biotechnological or pharmaceutical

    products want to see IPR defined expansively and enforced rigorously. Business

    groups like the International Intellectual Property Alliance and the Business Soft-

    ware Alliance lobby governments on behalf of industries producing intellectual

    property (Braithwaite & Drahos 2000, pp. 7071). Producers also use contracts to

    augment property rights law if they deem the latter inadequate (see Nimmer 1999

    on shrink-wrap licensing agreements between software companies and users) or

    inappropriate (general public licenses and open-source code, see OMahony 2003).The U.S. government has been particularly responsive to such concerns and

    pushes for strong IPR internationally (Braithwaite & Drahos 2000, pp. 66, 79).

    The costs of duplication and distribution of many informational products are close

    to zero, so global trade has developed rapidly (Maskus 2000, pp. 7383). Along

    with global markets, the locus for enforcement has shifted from the national to

    the supranational level, changing the politics of IPR. As international organiza-

    tions harmonize varying national rules and standards, interest groups can use their

    domestic political power to influence global rules. For example, the criteria for

    patentability enshrined in TRIPS are essentially U.S. standards. However, harmo-nization remains very incomplete, and national differences persist.

    U.S. sponsorship of agreements like TRIPS represents a turnaround from the

    nineteenth century when American support for intellectual property was much

    weaker. The Copyright Act of 1790 protected only U.S. citizens and residents

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    17/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 39

    and permitted literary piracy by domestic publishers (something Charles Dickens

    complained about; see Vaidhyanathan 2001, pp. 5052). But as the United States

    began to produce and export intellectual property, its position in international trade

    negotiations altered. Like other countries, however, the United States will entertainloosening IPR in case of national emergency. For example, during the anthrax scare

    of 2001, politicians debated whether to override Bayers patent on the antibiotic

    CIPRO (Resnik 2002).

    Today, the United States faces opposition from developing countries whose

    citizens seek cheaper medicines and who pirate videos, software, recordings,

    and other information products. Given the imbalance of power, countries seldom

    oppose the United States directly but instead combine formal compliance with

    weak implementation (a decoupling strategy). As countries develop their own

    internal producers of intellectual property, however, domestic political pressurefor stronger protections emerges (Maskus 2000, p. 97). Of course, U.S. citizens

    practice their own piracy by downloading and exchanging popular music (witness

    Napster), but two streams of scholarly argumentation have emerged in the United

    States to oppose strong IPR.

    The first recognizes that whether an innovation becomes property depends on

    the patent office. Patent offices operate by fiat: if they bestow a patent on an

    idea, that idea becomes property. Yet observers note the variable competence and

    capacity of patent offices. Patent examiners evaluate submissions by the three

    criteria mentioned earlier, often in highly esoteric areas for which they are notwell qualified. The USPTO has been criticized for being overly generous to patent

    applicants. Lerner (2003) observes that in awarding patents on financial methods

    and formulas, the USPTO often ignored academic research that anticipated the

    supposed discovery, while Hall (2003, p. 12) emphasizes the low quality of

    many recent patent decisions.

    The second, more fundamental criticism addresses the purpose of intellectual

    property law. Intellectual property is created, not found, and owners receive a

    temporary monopoly (Posner 2002, pp. 89). They enjoy monopoly rents, but

    when the patent or copyright expires, their contribution joins the public domain,where others can freely use or exploit it. This arrangement encourages innovation

    in a way that provides both public and private benefits. But a number of schol-

    ars worry that in the rush to extend private property rights into new realms, the

    balance has tipped too much toward private interests and now discourages innova-

    tion and creativity. Lessig (2001), Rose (1998), Eisenberg & Nelson (2002), and

    Vaidhyanathan (2001) discuss the tension between information as property (with

    the emphasis on exclusivity and controlled access) and information as expression

    (open access becomes predominant). Free expression is one of the foundations

    of a liberal society, and the information commons is a source of creativity andoriginality. Locking up ideas with strong property rights privileges owners at the

    expense of everyone else, and ultimately stifles scientific and artistic invention.

    Others contest the status quo directly and have tried to decommodify computer

    software through the open-source software movement (Boyle 2002). Universities

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    18/26

    40 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    are now caught on both sides of the issue: As patent owners they prefer strong

    property rights, but as academic institutions they try to sustain an information

    commons (Eisenberg 2003).

    CONCLUSION

    Property rights encompass law, economy, state, politics, science, and culture, and

    so they possess much sociological relevance. Future research should focus on

    variations in property rights along the dimensions discussed above, document-

    ing empirical patterns and building toward explanations. Some obvious questions

    include: how do new objects and new subjects of property become constituted?

    Does the distribution of new assets reflect older inequalities, and what are the

    implications for the reproduction of inequality? Will global integration lead to

    a single, dominant, property rights regime? What balance exists between formal

    and informal property rights, and are these two substitutes or complements? How

    do the politics of property unfold during periods of institutional transformation?

    What is the interplay between formal property interests in things and social or

    cultural interests (e.g., formal ownership fails to capture the pricelessness of a

    family heirloom)? How necessary are transparent and predictable property rights?

    Doubtless, many other questions will arise.

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

    We thank Lisa Bruggeman and Aaron Novod for their able research assistance,

    John L. Campbell, Neil Fligstein, and Wendy Espeland for very helpful comments,

    and the Lochinvar Society for its warm support.

    The Annual Review of Sociology is online at http://soc.annualreviews.org

    LITERATURE CITED

    Adams J. 1994. The familial state: elite fam-

    ily practices and state-making in the early

    modern Netherlands. Theory Soc. 23:505

    39

    Agarwal B. 1994. A Field of Ones Own: Gen-

    der and Land Rights in South Asia. New

    York: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Alchian AA, Demsetz H. 1973. The property

    right paradigm. J. Econ. Hist. 33(1):1627Alexander GS. 1997. Commodity and Prop-

    erty: Competing Visions of Property in Amer-

    ican Legal Thought. Chicago: Univ. Chicago

    Press

    Alford WP. 1995. To Steal a Book Is an Elegant

    Offense: Intellectual Property Law in Chi-

    nese Civilization. Stanford: Stanford Univ.

    Press

    Altonji JG, Doraszelski U, Segal L. 2000.

    Black/white differencesin wealth.Econ. Per-

    spect. 24:3850

    Amsden AH, Kochanowicz J, Taylor L. 1994.

    The Market Meets Its Match: Restructur-

    ing the Economies of Eastern Europe. Cam-bridge: Harvard Univ. Press

    Andrews L, Nelkin D. 2001. Body Bazaar: The

    Market for Human Tissue in the Biotechnol-

    ogy Age. New York: Crown

    Appel H. 2000. The ideological determinants

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    19/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 41

    of liberal economic reform: the case of pri-

    vatization. World Polit. 52:52049

    Aslund A. 1995. How Russia Became a Market

    Economy. Washington, DC: Brookings Inst.

    Baker JH. 1979. An Introduction to English Le-

    gal History. London: Butterworths. 2nd ed.

    Barzel Y. 1989. Economic Analysis of Property

    Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Benton L. 2002. Law and Colonial Cultures:

    Legal Regimes in World History, 14001900.

    Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Berkowitz D, Pistor K, Richard J-F. 2003. Eco-

    nomic development, legality, and the trans-

    plant effect. Eur. Econ. Rev. 47:16595Berman HJ. 1983. Law and Revolution: The

    Formation of the Western Legal Tradition.

    Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press

    Bernhardt K. 1999. Women and Property in

    China, 9601949. Stanford: Stanford Univ.

    Press

    Bian Y, Logan JR. 1996. Market transition and

    the persistence of power: the changing strat-

    ification system in urban China. Am. Sociol.

    Rev. 61:73958Black B, Kraakman R, Tarassova A. 2000.

    Russian privatization and corporate gover-

    nance: What went wrong? Stanford Law Rev.

    52:1731808

    Blackstone W. 1766 (1979). Commentaries on

    the Laws of England, Vol. 2. Chicago: Univ.

    Chicago Press

    Blasi JR, Kroumova M, Kruse D. 1997.Kremlin

    Capitalism: The Privatization of the Russian

    Economy. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. PressBoisot M, Child J. 1996. From fiefs to clans

    and network capitalism: explaining Chinas

    emerging economic order. Admin. Sci. Q.

    41:60028

    Boyle J. 2002. Fencing off ideas: enclosure

    and the disappearance of the public domain.

    Daedalus 131:1325

    Brada JC, Singh I. 1999. Corporate Gover-

    nance in Central Eastern Europe: Case Stud-

    ies of Firms in Transition. Armonk, NY:

    Sharpe

    Braithwaite J, Drahos P. 2000. Global Business

    Regulation. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ.

    Press

    Bright C. 1995. Who owns indigenous peoples

    DNA? Humanist 55(1):44

    Brownlee WE. 2000. Historical perspective

    on U.S. tax policy. In Does Atlas Shrug?

    The Economic Consequences of Taxing the

    Rich,ed. JB Slemrod, pp. 2973. New York:

    Russell Sage Found.

    Brudner LA, White DR. 1997. Class, property,

    and structural endogamy: visualizing net-

    worked histories. Theory Soc. 26(2/3):161

    208

    Brush SB. 1993. Indigenous knowledge of bi-

    ological resources and intellectual property

    rights: the role of anthropology. Am. Anthro-pol. NS 95:65371

    Burawoy M, Krotov P. 1992. The Soviet tran-

    sition from socialism to capitalism: worker

    control and economic bargaining in the wood

    industry. Am. Sociol. Rev. 57:1638

    Campbell JL, Lindberg LN. 1990. Property

    rights and the organization of economic ac-

    tivity by the state.Am. Sociol. Rev. 55:63447

    Caplow T. 1982. Christmas gifts and kin net-

    works. Am. Sociol. Rev. 47:38392Carruthers BG, Halliday TC. 1998. Rescu-

    ing Business: The Making of Corporate

    Bankruptcy Law in England and the United

    States. Oxford: Clarendon

    Cheit RE. 1990. Setting Safety Standards: Reg-

    ulation in the Public and Private Sectors.

    Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press

    Clement C, Murrell P. 2001. Assessing the value

    of law in transition economies. An introduc-

    tion. See Murrell 2001, pp. 119Cleveland DA, Murray SC. 1997. The worlds

    crop genetic resources and the rights of in-

    digenous farmers. Curr. Anthropol. 38:477

    515

    Coase RH. 1960. The problem of social cost. J.

    Law Econ. 3:144

    Conley D. 1999.Being Black, Living in the Red:

    Race, Wealth, and Social Policy in America.

    Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press

    Donaldson T. 1995. The stakeholder the-

    ory of the corporation. Acad. Manag. Rev.

    20(1):6591

    Dore R. 2000. Stock Market Capitalism: Wel-

    fare Capitalism. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    20/26

    42 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    Drahos P. 1999. Biotechnology patents, mar-

    kets and morality. Eur. Intellect. Prop. Rev.

    21(9):44149

    Durkheim E. 1992. Professional Ethics and

    Civic Morals. Transl. C Brookfield. London:

    Routledge.

    Earle T. 2000. Archeology, property, and pre-

    history. Annu. Rev. Anthropol. 29:3960

    Eggertsson T. 1990.EconomicBehavior and In-

    stitutions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ.

    Press

    Eisenberg RS.2002. How can you patent genes?

    Am. J. Bioeth. 2(3):311

    Eisenberg RS. 2003. Patent swords and shields.Science 299:101819

    Eisenberg RS, Nelson RR. 2002. Public vs. pro-

    prietary science. Daedalus 131:89101

    Ellickson RC. 1991. Order without Law: How

    Neighbors Settle Disputes. Cambridge: Har-

    vard Univ. Press

    Ely JW Jr. 1992. The Guardian of Every Other

    Right: A Constitutional History of Property

    Rights. New York: Oxford Univ. Press

    Emigh RJ. 1999. Means and measures: prop-erty rights, political economy, and productiv-

    ity in fifteenth-century Tuscany. Soc. Forces

    78:46190

    Ensminger J, Rutten A. 1991. The political

    economy of changing property rights: dis-

    mantling a pastoral commons. Am. Ethnol.

    18(4):68399

    Erickson AL. 1990. Common law versus com-

    mon practice: the use of marriage settlements

    in early modern England.Econ. Hist. Rev. NS43(1):2139

    Ertman T. 1997. Birth of Leviathan: Build-

    ing States and Regimes in Medieval and

    Early Modern Europe. Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge Univ. Press

    Espeland W. 1998. The Struggle for Water:Poli-

    tics, Rationality, and Identity in the American

    Southwest. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press

    Firmin-Sellers K. 1995. The politics of property

    rights. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 89:86781

    Fligstein N. 2001. The Architecture of Mar-

    kets: An Economic Sociology of Twenty-

    First-Century Capitalist Societies. Prince-

    ton: Princeton Univ. Press

    Freeland RF. 2001. The Struggle for Con-

    trol of the Modern Corporation: Organiza-

    tional Change at General Motors, 1924

    1970. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge Univ.

    Press

    Gale WG, Scholz JK. 1994. Intergenerational

    transfers and the accumulation of wealth. J.

    Econ. Perspect. 8(4):14560

    Gerber TP, Hout M. 1998. More shock than

    therapy: market transition, employment, and

    income in Russia, 19911995. Am. J. Sociol.

    104:150

    Giesey RE. 1977. Rules of inheritance and

    strategies of mobility in prerevolutionaryFrance. Am. Hist. Rev. 82:27189

    Grassby R. 1995. The Business Community of

    Seventeenth-Century England. Cambridge:

    Cambridge Univ. Press

    Hadfield GK. 1990. Problematic relations: fran-

    chising and the law of incomplete contracts.

    Stanford Law Rev. 42:92783

    Hall BH. 2003. Business method patents, inno-

    vation, and policy. Work. Pap. 9717, NBER,

    Cambridge, MAHall PE, Soskice D, eds. 2001. Varieties of

    Capitalism: The Institutional Foundations of

    Comparative Advantage. New York: Oxford

    Univ. Press

    Hart O, Moore J. 1990. Property rights and the

    nature of the firm.J. Polit. Econ. 98:111958

    Healy K. 2002. Survey article: digital technol-

    ogy and cultural goods.J. Polit. Philos. 10:1

    23

    Heller MA. 2001. A property theory perspec-tive on Russian enterprise reform. See Mur-

    rell 2001, pp. 288313

    Heller MA, Eisenberg RS. 1998. Can patents

    deter innovation? The anticommons in

    biomedical research. Science 280:698701

    Hendley K. 1997. Legal development in post-

    Soviet Russia. Post-Soviet Aff. 13:22851

    Hesse C. 2002. The rise of intellectual property,

    700 B.C.A.D. 2000 Daedelus 131:2645

    Horwitz MJ. 1977. The Transformation of

    American Law, 17801860. Cambridge: Har-

    vard Univ. Press

    Hunt RM. 2001. You can patent that? Are

    patents on computer programs and business

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    21/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 43

    methods good for the new economy? Bus.

    Rev. Q1:515

    Islam MM. 1995. The Punjab Land Alienation

    Act and the professional moneylenders.Mod.

    Asian Stud. 29:27191

    Janis MD. 2002. Patent abolitionism. Berkeley

    Technol. Law J. 17:899952

    Jianakoplos NA, Menchik PL. 1997. Wealth

    mobility. Rev. Econ. Stat. 79(1):1831

    Johnson S, McMillan J, Woodruff C. 2002.

    Property rights and finance. Am. Econ. Rev.

    92:133556

    Justinians Inst. 1987. Ithaca: Cornell Univ.

    PressKali R. 2001. Business networks in transition

    economies. See Murrell 2001, pp. 21128

    Kantor SE. 1998. Politics and Property Rights:

    The Closing of the Open Range in the Post-

    bellum South. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press

    Keister LA. 2000. Wealth in America: Trends

    in Wealth Inequality. Cambridge: Cambridge

    Univ. Press

    Keister LA, Moller S. 2000. Wealth inequal-

    ity in the United States. Annu. Rev. Sociol.26:6381

    Kevles D. 2002. Of mice and money. Daedelus

    131:7888

    Khan ZB. 1995. Property rights and patent lit-

    igation in early nineteenth-century America.

    J. Econ. Hist. 55:5897

    King L. 2003. Shock privatization: the effects of

    rapid large-scale privatization on enterprise

    restructuring. Polit. Soc. 31:330

    King LP. 2001. The Basic Features of Postcom-munist Capitalism in Eastern Europe: Firms

    in Hungary, The Czech Republic, and Slo-

    vakia. Westport, CT: Praeger

    Knight J. 1992.Institutions and Social Conflict.

    Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Kornai J. 1992. The Socialist System: The Po-

    litical Economy of Communism. Princeton:

    Princeton Univ. Press

    Kumar D. 1985. Private property in Asia? The

    case of medieval South India. Comp. Stud.

    Soc. Hist. 27(2):34066

    Kuran T. 1995. Islamic economics and the

    Islamic subeconomy. J. Econ. Perspect.

    9(4):15573

    Lee J-Y, Mansfield E. 1996. Intellectual prop-

    erty protection and U.S. foreign direct invest-

    ment. Rev. Econ. Stat. 78(2):18186

    Lerner J. 2002. Patent protection and innova-

    tion over 150 years. Work. Pap. 8977, NBER

    Lerner J. 2003. Patent policy reform and its im-

    plications. NBER Report. Winter:1719

    Levin P, Espeland W. 2002. Pollution futures:

    commensuration, commodification, and the

    market for air. In Organizations, Policy, and

    the Natural Environment, ed. AJ Hoffman,

    MJ Ventresca, pp. 11947. Stanford: Stan-

    ford Univ. Press

    Lessig L. 2001. The Future of Ideas: The Fateof the Commons in a Connected World. New

    York: Vintage Books

    Libecap G. 1986. Contracting for Property

    Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Longhofer J. 1993. Toward a political econ-

    omy of inheritance: community and house-

    hold among the Mennonites. Theory Soc.

    22(3):33762

    Marcus GE. 1980. Law in the development of

    dynastic families among American businesselites. Law Soc. Rev. 14(4):859903

    Marx K, Engels F. 1947. The German Ideology.

    New York: International

    Maskus KE. 2000. Intellectual Property Rights

    in the Global Economy. Washington, DC:

    Inst. Int. Econ.

    Massey DS, Denton NA. 1993. American

    Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of

    the Underclass. Cambridge: Harvard Univ.

    PressMcEvoy A. 1998. Markets and ethics in U.S.

    property law. In Who Owns America? Social

    Conflict Over Property Rights, ed. HM Ja-

    cobs, pp. 94113. Madison: Univ. Wis. Press

    Mendelsohn R. 1994. Property rights and tropi-

    cal deforestation. Oxford Econ. Pap. 46:750

    56

    Merges RP. 2000. One hundred years of solic-

    itude: intellectual property law, 19002000.

    Calif. Law Rev. 88(6):2187240

    Morales A. 1993. Making money at the mar-

    ket: the social and economic logic of infor-

    mal markets. PhD Diss. Northwest. Univ.,

    Evanston, IL

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    22/26

    44 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    Moss DA. 2002. When All Else Fails: Govern-

    ment as the Ultimate Risk Manager. Cam-

    bridge: Harvard Univ. Press

    Moxnes E. 1998. Not only the tragedy of the

    commons: misperceptions of bioeconomics.

    Manag. Sci. 44:123448

    Munnell AH, Tootell GMB, Browne LE, McE-

    neaney J. 1996. Mortgage lending in Boston:

    interpreting HMDA data. Am. Econ. Rev.

    86(1):2553

    Murrell P, ed. 2001. Assessing the Value of Law

    in Transition Economies. Ann Arbor: Univ.

    Mich. Press

    Nalley ET. 2000. Intellectual property in com-puter programs. Bus. Horiz. 43(4):4351

    Nash D. 2000. South Africas Medicines and

    Related Substances Control Amendment Act

    of 1997. Berkeley Technol. Law J. 15:485

    502

    Naughton B. 1995. Growing Out of the Plan:

    Chinese Economic Reform, 19781993.

    Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Nazzari M. 1995. Widows as obstacles to busi-

    ness: British objections to Brazilian marriageand inheritance laws. Comp. Stud. Soc. Hist.

    37(4):781802

    Nee V. 1992. Organizational dynamics of mar-

    ket transition: hybrid forms, property rights,

    and mixed economy in China.Admin. Sci. Q.

    37:127

    Nee V. 1996. The emergence of a market soci-

    ety: changing mechanisms of stratification in

    China. Am. J. Sociol. 101:90849

    Nee V, Matthews R. 1996. Market transition andsocietal transformation in reforming state so-

    cialism. Annu. Rev. Sociol. 22:40135

    NeesonJM.1993. Commoners:Common Right,

    Enclosure and Social Change in England,

    17001820. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ.

    Press

    Neigel C. 2000. Piracy in Russian and China: A

    different U.S. reaction.Law Contemp. Probl.

    63:17999

    Nimmer RT. 1998. Breaking barriers: the rela-

    tion between contract and intellectual prop-

    erty law.BerkeleyTechnol. Law J. 13(3):827

    89

    Nimmer RT, Krauthaus P. 1992. Information as

    a commodity. Law Contemp. Probl. 55:103

    30

    North DC. 1990. Institutions, Institutional

    Change and Economic Performance. Cam-

    bridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Novak WJ. 1996. The Peoples Welfare: Law

    and Regulation in Nineteenth-Century Amer-

    ica. Chapel Hill: Univ. N.C. Press

    Oi JC, Walder AG, eds. 1999. Property Rights

    and Economic Reform in China. Stanford:

    Stanford Univ. Press

    Oliver ML, Shapiro TM. 1997. Black

    Wealth/White Wealth: A New Perspective on

    Racial Inequality. New York: RoutledgeOMahony S. 2003. Guarding the commons:

    how community managed software projects

    protect their work. Res. Policy 1615:120

    Ostrom E. 1990. Governing the Commons: The

    Evolution of Institutions for Collective Ac-

    tion. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Ostrower F. 1995. Why the Wealthy Give:

    The Culture of Elite Philanthropy. Princeton:

    Princeton Univ. Press

    Owen-Smith J. 2003. From separate systemsto a hybrid order: accumulative advantage

    across public and private science at Research

    One universities. Res. Policy 32:1081104

    Patterson O. 1982. Slavery and Social Death:

    A Comparative Study. Cambridge: Harvard

    Univ. Press

    Perrow C. 2002. Organizing America: Wealth,

    Power, and the Origins of Corporate Capi-

    talism. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press

    Pistor K, Wellons P. 1998. The Role of Lawand LegalInstitutions in Asian EconomicDe-

    velopment, 19601995. New York: Oxford

    Univ. Press

    Plotkin S. 1987. Keep Out: The Struggle for

    Land Use Control. Berkeley: Univ. Calif.

    Press

    Polanyi M. 1944. The Great Transformation.

    Boston: Beacon

    Posner R. 2002. The law and economics of in-

    tellectual property. Daedelus 131:512

    Powell WW, Owen-Smith J. 1998. Universities

    and the market for intellectual property in

    the life sciences. J. Policy Analysis Manag.

    17(2):25377

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    23/26

    SOCIOLOGY OF PROPERTY RIGHTS 45

    Przeworski A. 1991. Democracy and the Mar-

    ket: Political and Economic Reforms in East-

    ern Europe and Latin America. Cambridge:

    Cambridge Univ. Press

    Purnell J. 1999. With all due respect: popular

    resistance to the privatization of communal

    lands in nineteenth-century Michoacan. Lat.

    Am. Res. Rev. 34:85121

    Putterman L. 1995. The role of ownership and

    property rights in Chinas transition. China

    Q. 144:104764

    Rapaczynski A. 1996. The roles of the state and

    the market in establishing property rights. J.

    Econ. Perspect. 10:87103Reeve A. 1986. Property. Atlantic Highlands:

    Humanities

    Resnik DB. 2002. Bioterrorism and patent

    rights: compulsory licensure and the case

    of CIPRO. Am. J. Bioeth. 2(3):2939

    Rice R. 1968. Residential segregation by law,

    19101917. J. South. Hist. 34:17999

    Roemer JE. 1989. What is exploitation?Philos.

    Public Aff. 18:9097

    Roland G. 2002. The political economy of tran-sition. J. Econ. Perspect. 16:2950

    Rose CM. 1998. The several futures of property.

    Minn. Law Rev. 83:12982

    Roy W. 1997. Socializing Capital: The Rise of

    the Large Industrial Corporation in America.

    Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press

    Salmon M. 1986. Women and the Law of Prop-

    erty in Early America. Chapel Hill: Univ.

    N.C. Press

    Samuelson P. 1996. Intellectual property rightsand the global information economy. Com-

    mun. ACM39(1):2328

    Scott JC. 1998. Seeing Like a State: How Cer-

    tain Schemes to Improve the Human Con-

    dition Have Failed. New Haven: Yale Univ.

    Press

    Shammas C, Salmon M, Dahlin M. 1987.Inher-

    itance in America: From Colonial Times to

    the Present. New Brunswick: Rutgers Univ.

    Press

    Shapiro C, Varian HR. 1999. Information

    Rules: A Strategic Guide to the Network Eco-

    nomy. Boston: Harvard Bus. Sch. Press

    Shipton P. 1994. Land and culture in tropi-

    cal Africa. Annu. Rev. Anthropol. 23:347

    77

    Simpson AWB. 1986. A History of the Land

    Law. Oxford: Clarendon. 2nd ed.

    Skeel DA Jr. 2001.Debts Dominion: A History

    of Bankruptcy Law in America. Princeton:

    Princeton Univ. Press

    Smart A. 1986. Invisible real state: investiga-

    tions into the squatter property market. Int.

    J. Urban Reg. Res. 10:2945

    Smith CW, Warner J. 1979. On financial con-

    tracting. J. Financ. Econ. 7:11761

    Somaya D. 2000. Obtaining and protecting

    patents in the United States, Europe, andJapan. In Regulatory Encounters: Multina-

    tional Corporations and American Adver-

    sarial Legalism, ed. RA Kagan, L Axelrad,

    pp. 255310. Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press

    Sorensen AB. 2000. Toward a sounder basis

    for class analysis. Am. J. Sociol. 105:1523

    58

    Soto H de. 2000. The Mystery of Capital: Why

    Capitalism Triumphs in the West and Fails

    Everywhere Else. New York: Basic BooksSpring E. 1993.Law, Land, and Family: Aristo-

    cratic Inheritance in England, 1300 to 1800.

    Chapel Hill: Univ. N.C. Press

    Stark D. 1996. Recombinant property in

    East European capitalism. Am. J. Sociol.

    101:9931027

    Stark D, Bruszt L. 1998. Postsocialist Path-

    ways: Transforming Politics and Property in

    Eastern Central Europe. Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge Univ. PressStaves S. 1990. Married Womens Separate

    Property in England, 16601833. Cam-

    bridge: Harvard Univ. Press

    Stiglitz JE. 2002. Globalization and Its Discon-

    tents. New York: Norton

    Stinchcombe A. 1983. Economic Sociology.

    New York: Academic

    Stuart G. 2003. Discriminating Risk: The U.S.

    Mortgage Lending Industry in the Twentieth

    Century. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press

    Swedberg R. 2003. Principles of Economic So-

    ciology. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press

    Thompson EP. 1975. Whigs and Hunters: The

    Origin of the Black Act. New York: Pantheon

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    24/26

    46 CARRUTHERS ARIOVICH

    Vaidhyanathan S. 2001. Copyrights and Copy-

    wrongs:The Rise of Intellectual Property and

    How It Threatens Creativity. New York: New

    York Univ. Press

    Volkov V. 2002. Violent Entrepreneurs: The

    Use of Force in the Making of Russian Cap-

    italism. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press

    Walder AG. 1992. Property rights and stratifi-

    cation in socialist redistributive economies.

    Am. Sociol. Rev. 57:52439

    Walder AG. 1995. Local governments as in-

    dustrial firms: an organizational analysis of

    Chinas transitional economy. Am. J. Sociol.

    101:263301Walder AG, Oi JC. 1999. Property rights in the

    Chinese economy: contours of the process of

    change. See Oi & Walder 1999, pp. 124

    Wank DL. 1999. Producing property rights:

    strategies, networks, and efficiency in urban

    Chinas nonstate firms. See Oi & Walder

    1999, pp. 24872

    Weaver JC. 1996. Beyond the fatal shore: pas-

    toral squatting and the occupation of Aus-

    tralia, 1826 to 1852.Am. Hist. Rev. 101:981

    1007

    Weber M. 1981. General Economic History.

    New Brunswick: Transaction Books

    West MD. 2003. Losers: recovering lost prop-

    erty in Japan and the United States. Law Soc.

    Rev. 37:369423

    Wood D. 2002. Medieval Economic Thought.

    Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Wright EO. 2002. The shadow of exploitationin Webers class analysis. Am. Sociol. Rev.

    67:83253

    Ziegler JN. 2000. Corporate governance and the

    politics of property rights in Germany. Polit.

    Soc. 28(2):195221

    bybon:

    UniversidadeNovadeLisboa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    25/26

    Annual Review of Sociology

    Volume 30, 2004

    CONTENTS

    FrontispieceW. Richard Scott xii

    PREFATORY CHAPTER

    Reflections on a Half-Century of Organizational Sociology,

    W. Richard Scott 1

    THEORY AND METHODS

    Narrative Explanation: An Alternative to Variable-Centered Explanation?

    Peter Abell 287

    Values: Reviving a Dormant Concept, Steven Hitlin and

    Jane Allyn Piliavin 359

    Durkheims Theory of Mental Categories: A Review of the Evidence,

    Albert J. Bergesen 395

    Panel Models in Sociological Research: Theory into Practice,

    Charles N. Halaby 507

    SOCIAL PROCESSES

    The New Science of Networks, Duncan J. Watts 243

    Social Cohesion, Noah E. Friedkin 409

    INSTITUTIONS AND CULTURE

    The Use of Newspaper Data in the Study of Collective Action,

    Jennifer Earl, Andrew Martin, John D. McCarthy,

    and Sarah A. Soule 65

    Consumers and Consumption, Sharon Zukin and Jennifer Smith Maguire 173

    The Production of Culture Perspective, Richard A. Peterson and N. Anand 311

    Endogenous Explanation in the Sociology of Culture, Jason Kaufman 335

    POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC SOCIOLOGY

    The Sociology of Property Rights, Bruce G. Carruthers and

    Laura Ariovich 23

    Protest and Political Opportunities, David S. Meyer 125

    The Knowledge Economy, Walter W. Powell and Kaisa Snellman 199

    v

    bybon:UniversidadeNovadeLis

    boa(UNL)on10/26/05.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 7/30/2019 08 Carruthers & Ariovitch 2004

    26/26

    vi CONTENTS

    New Risks for Workers: Pensions, Labor Markets, and Gender,

    Kim M. Shuey and Angela M. ORand 453

    Advocacy Organizations in the U.S. Political Process, Kenneth T. Andrews

    and Bob Edwards 479

    Space in the Study of Labor Markets, Roberto M. Fernandez and Celina Su 545

    DIFFERENTIATION AND STRATIFICATION

    Gender and Work in Germany: Before and After Reunification,

    Rachel A. Rosenfeld, Heike Trappe, and Janet C. Gornick 103

    INDIVIDUAL AND SOCIETY

    The Sociology of Sexualities: Queer and Beyond, Joshua Gamson and

    Dawne Moon 47

    DEMOGRAPHY

    Americas Changing Color Lines: Immigration, Race/Ethnicity, and

    Multiracial Identification, Jennifer Lee and Frank D. Be