the principles of friesian philosophy

Upload: seljakveseljak

Post on 05-Oct-2015

12 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Philosophy, principles

TRANSCRIPT

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 1/6

    The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    Then let us again examine whether that is a sound statement, or do we let it pass,and if one of us, or someone else, merely says that something is so, do we accept

    that it is so? Or should we examine what the speaker means?

    Socrates, Euthryphro 9e [G.M.A. Grube translation, Plato, Five Dialogues, Euthyphro,

    Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo, Hackett Publishing Company, 1981, p. 14]

    The professor of philosophy who forgets that philosophy is about wisdom may stillbe a real lover of knowledge, may still be a great creative scholar, and may even

    still be a very good person, but he will not really be a philosopher. When hespeaks, especially on moral, practical, or political matters, his words may representnothing but the most dangerous folly, without the Socratic perspective and drive tocorrect it. All too often, brilliant fools seem to be the stock-in-trade of academia

    and the intelligentsia.

    Enklinobarangus ( )

    This page is intended as a brief description of ideas and principles characteristic of the Friesian and other

    modifications of Kantian philosophy editorially recommended in the Proceedings of the Friesian School,

    Fourth Series. More detailed explanations will be found elsewhere at the site. For brevity, familiarity with certain

    philosophical issues and theories is often presupposed, so these descriptions may not be as accessible as theessays listed on the Home Page under "Topics and Essays on the Site".

    Epistemology

    Kantian epistemology is foundationalist and rationalistic in a qualified sense. Kant allowed that there were

    synthetic a priori propositions in mathematics, grounded in "pure intuition," in metaphysics, grounded on

    the Principle of the Possibility of Experience, and in morality, grounded on Pure Reason acting as the

    Moral Law. Fries and Nelson modified Kantian epistemology, first, by clarifying that synthetic a priori

    propositions are not proven by Kantian "Deduction," second, by clearly distinguishing immediate

    knowledge, which is the ground of synthetic propositions, from mediate knowledge, which is expressed in

    propositional form and may be justified by immediate knowledge, and, third, by distinguishing intuitive

    from non-intuitive immediate knowledge.

    On Friesian principles, the common argument against the existence of immediate knowledge, that it would

    require us to claim that certain synthetic propositions are infallible and incorrigible, which today no longer

    seems credible, fails. Immediate knowledge as the ground of synthetic propositions may in some sense be

    http://www.friesian.com/euthyph.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/wisdom.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/ross/ross-9.htm#enklinohttp://www.friesian.com/#contentshttp://www.friesian.com/kant.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/fries.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/nelson.htm

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 2/6

    infallible and incorrigible, but the expression of any propositions themselves, as items of knowledge, ismediate. Mediate knowledge presupposes many things that are not part of immediate knowledge, e.g. the

    meanings of words in natural languages, or items of implicit knowledge. Thus, mediate knowledge is

    always fallible and corrigible. This allows Friesian epistemology to accommodate a hermeneutic

    dimension of interpretation and reinterpretation, with the common sense limitation that the interpretationsof synthetic propositions must be recognized as grounded by immediate knowledge in order to be true.

    If synthetic a priori propositions are not grounded in intuitive immediate knowledge, where the groundneed merely be shown ("demonstrated" in Friesian terminology) for fallible and corrigible justification, then

    they can only be grounded in non-intuitive immediate knowledge. Such a ground cannot be "shown." The

    difference between discovery and justification then becomes significant. Discovery is handled by Nelson's

    theory of Socratic Method. But while Nelson's theory of Socratic Method as "abstraction" is intuitionistic

    and inadequate, the theory is easily reformulated in terms of Popper's theory of falsification, which

    winnows out inconsistent items. Popper's theory of scientific method, where theories are imaginatively

    generated, may thus be coupled with the Socratic injunction, "Say what you believe," to recover what

    Kant called the "quid facti" of rational knowledge.

    The theory of non-intuitive immediate knowledge frees the Kantian epistemology of synthetic a priori

    propositions from the narrow confines of the Principle of the Possibility of Experience and from vagueappeals to Pure Reason as the ground of the Moral Law. Instead, independent axiomatic systems become

    possible for varieties of non-empirical knowledge, not just metaphysics but also the multiple value systemsof morality, aesthetics, and religion. However, a difference remains, as follows in the next section, between

    phenomena and things-in-themselves which, among other things, limits mathematical knowledge fromapplication beyond phenomenal reality.

    Friesian epistemology is basically an internalist theory of knowledge. "Externalist" theories, based on some

    external relationship, like causality, to account for knowledge, are rejected on the principle that thedifference between knowledge and opinion can only be distinguished on the basis of some internal

    evidence. No external relationship is available for internal examination as evidence for knowledge. Onthe other hand, Kantian metaphysics, as follows, holds that external relationships are internal in that theobjects of experience are phenomenal contents of consciousness. Thus Friesian epistemology in fact can

    subsume externalist considerations within itself. (However, note well, the treatment in "OntologicalUndecidability" and elsewhere shifts the meaning of "external" and "internal" so that Kant-Friesian

    epistemology is neither externalist nor internalist.)

    Similarly, Friesian epistemology combines both the coherence and the correspondence theories of truth:the coherence of mediate with immediate knowledge, but then the correspondence of mediate

    knowledge to the empirically real phenomenal objects that are present in immediate knowledge. Thisavoids traditional criticisms of coherence, that it allows for no relationship to reality, since reality is in

    immediate knowledge, and traditional criticisms of correspondence, that it posits a ground of truthinaccessible to knowledge, since phenomenal objects are within consciousness.

    Thus, on several fronts, Kant-Friesian epistemology passes over into metaphysical considerations.

    Metaphysics

    http://www.friesian.com/immedi-1.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/foundatn.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/popper.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/undecd-1.htm

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 3/6

    Kantian metaphysics recognizes the difference between phenomena and things-in-themselves.

    Schopenhauer thought this was the most important thing about Kant's thought. Nevertheless, Kant'sphenomenalism is often mistaken for some kind of subjectivist, conceptualist, or psychologistic theory. The

    key point about it all, therefore, is that Kant's phenomenalism is a theory ofempirical realism, according to which we are directly acquainted with

    real external objects in space and time. Unlike the familiar case of Descartes,what Kant would call "transcendental realism," we are not merely acquainted

    with the internal and private contents of our minds, though phenomena arethat too (see "Ontological Undecidability"). Instead, we are justified in our

    common sense attitude towards the world, whereby Dr. Johnson refutedBishop Berkeley by kicking the table. This implies that the real objects ofexperience are present in our perception, and Kant's theory is that this is correct. Such a theory precludes

    the Cartesian threats of scepticism or solipsism.

    On the other hand, there are things-in-themselves. Traditionally these could be interpreted as the "real"objects ("transcendental realism"), turning Kant's "transcendental idealism" into just another version of

    Descartes or Berkeley, raising the same classic Cartesian problems of knowledge, mind and body, etc.Schopenhauer realized the most clearly the mistake involved in that interpretation; and, since he didn't

    think that plurality applied beyond perceptual objects, he always carefully referred to the "thing-in-itself"rather than to "things-in-themselves." The scruple is not necessary, but it does reveal that things-in-

    themselves are not a parallel order of objects over and above phenomenal objects. They are just thetranscendent aspect of those very same phenomenal objects. They are indeed things (as we see them) "in

    themselves."

    The transcendence of phenomenal objects encompasses different things:

    1. The existence of objects in so far as they are separate and independent from ourexistence. This is conformable to Heidegger's distinction between beings (nta in Greek, "beingthings"), which are individual and phenomenal, and Being (enai in Greek, "to be"), which is general

    and "hidden," although manifest in the nta. It is also conformable to Spinoza's distinction betweennatura naturata, "nature natured," manifest individual things, and natura naturans, "nature

    naturing," the hidden power that manifests the individual things. What seemed like no more than anepistemological or psychology theory in Descartes is thus a metaphysical distinction instead,

    although this needed clarifying after the way Kant formulated it.

    2. Aspects of reality that may be unconditioned. In phenomenal reality everything conditionseverything else, which requires a deterministic and naturalistic view of the world. Unconditionedobjects, like Kant's "Ideas" of God (an absolutely unconditioned object, as Spinoza had defined

    God), freedom (an unconditioned cause), and immortality (the unconditioned self as the soul),

    simply cannot exist in such a deterministic and naturalistic universe. However, such issues also

    intrude into science, since cosmology deals with the unconditioned object of the universe as awhole. Thus, whether space and time are finite or infinite, and whether the universe has a beginning

    or an end, trouble the consideration of people who are far above metaphysical speculations about

    God or the soul. Kant treated all such problems together, as transcending phenomenal reality: Nounconditioned object is an object of a possible experience. Significantly, the Buddhist philosophical

    doctrines of "dependent origination" and "relative existence" parallel the Kantian theory of

    http://www.friesian.com/arthur.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/undecd-1.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/spinoza.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/buddhism.htm#basic

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 4/6

    conditioned, phenomenal reality -- just as the Buddhist doctrines of Nirvana and space as

    unconditioned things parallel the Kantian theory of "Ideas" and the Antinomies. Furthermore, Kant's

    theory of the Antinomies now can be extended to Set Theory, where it has become evident that anunconditioned whole, like the Universal Set, produces contradictions -- famous paradoxes like

    Russell's, or the Nelson-Grelling Paradox introduced in the pages of the Abhandlungen der

    Fries'schen Schule, Neue Folge itself.

    3. The dimension of value in objects. Hume's famous distinction between matters of fact and

    matters of value has led many people to assume that "value judgments" have no basis in reality,

    since the reality that we perceive is factual. Hume's distinction, however, would be no surprise to

    Plato, who believed that value was based, not on the things of experience, but on the transcendentForms. Kantian theory is that such a transcendent aspect of things is not a separate World, as

    Plato had thought, but is present in things-in-themselves. The view that all we perceive in

    phenomenal objects is factual, however, is mistaken. Plato himself esteemed beauty as theparticular form of value that actually can be seen in things. To make this consistent with the rest of

    his theory, however, he had to say that beautiful objects were only "shadows" of the higher reality,

    "participating" in the Form of Beauty. Although Kant's own aesthetics were subjectivist (the theory

    of the Critique of Judgment), his metaphysics could allow for a more literal rendering of Plato'sown claim about beauty: Since transcendence is in phenomenal objects, the beauty that we see in

    things is in fact a perception right through factual reality to Beauty Itself.

    Kantian metaphysics, with some minor clarifications and modifications, thus accomplishes a great deal,especially in providing a sort of "phase space" for matters of value, although much the same thing had

    originally been done by Plato. See also "A New Kant-Friesian System of Metaphysics" and "Meaning and

    the Problem of Universals, A Kant-Friesian Approach."

    Ethics and Value Theory

    Kant's desire to derive the ultimate principle of morality, and really of all value, from the pure form,

    universality, and rule making function of reason itself was not well conceived, successful, or persuasive.Nevertheless, his project can be sympathetically interpreted and reformed. The Moral Law, as a synthetic

    a priori proposition, actually cannot be derived from anything, let alone some logician's version of what

    reason is. Nelson was correct that Socratic Method would be the means to the discovery of such

    propositions, though, as I have noted, the logic of Socratic Method must be clarified through Popper'sinsights into falsification. The Moral Law, indeed, may be formulated rather like Kant's own "means and

    ends" version, though Schopenhauer claimed not to understand what this was supposed to mean.

    The other problem with Kant's project was its moralism: The view that morality is ultimately the only formof value, which is implied by the idea that morality is the direct dictation of the form of reason itself.

    Following Schiller's denial of this, Nelson ultimately developed a complete theory of ethical "Ideals" that

    were not merely moral ideals. This kind of theory is here labelled the Polynomic Theory of Value, and is

    elaborated beyond Nelson to specify that there are six "domains" of value that are axiomaticallyindependent of each other. This allows for a realistic view of aesthetics, as suggested under "Metaphysics"

    above.

    http://www.friesian.com/antinom.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/key.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/system.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/universl.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/moral-1.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/poly-1b.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/poly-1.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/domain.htm

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 5/6

    Political Economy

    A conspicuous thing about the lives of both Fries and Nelson was their political activism. In both cases,

    this was not always to good effect. In the long run, Fries may be said to have been on the "right side" inresistance to Prussian and Austrian Reaction, but this also involved a promotion of German racialist

    nationalism that ultimately very much became the "wrong side." Nelson, in turn, was forthrightly opposed

    to the nationalism that would eventually motivate Germans to draw much of Europe down into a living hell

    of tyranny, war, and mass murder; but he also mistakenly subscribed to socialist principles that helpedpromote totalitarian regimes and also introduced corrupting and dangerous influences even into the

    democracies, the consequences of which, with the election and relection of Bill Clinton in the United

    States in 1992 and 1996, and the return to power of the British Laborites and French Socialists in 1997,

    and German Socialists in 1998, have still not played out entirely.

    The Friesian tradition, however, leads to classic and brilliant defenses of capitalism. Popper's

    understanding of falsification inspired his friend F.A. Hayek in his formulation of the principles of Austrian

    Economics originally developed by Ludwig von Mises. In retrospect, the Austrian theory that the freemarket serves to cordinate limited and diffused knowledge may be assimilated to a Popperian

    reformulation of Socratic Method, in that each is a means of dealing with our own ignorance, a self-aware

    Socratic Ignorance. Similarly, Nelson's suspicions of democracy can be set aside on the same principles.The defense of capitalism may also be assimilated to the Polynomic Theory of Value; for capitalism on the

    Austrian interpretation requires that the values exchanged in the free market be relative and different:

    Parties A and B exchange goods X and Y because X really is more valuable to B than to A and Y really

    is more valuable to A than to B. That is why the exchange takes place. Thus, the relativity of non-moralethical value ("hortative" value here) is distinct from the absolute requirements of moral value ("imperative"

    value ever since Kant).

    The Friesian tradition has long been playing catch up with Adam Smith, but fortunately, with F.A. Hayek,it caught up and went ahead. In the Proceedings of the Friesian School, Fourth Series, the tradition

    may now be fully integrated into the great heritage of Classical Liberalism. As Karl Popper and Julius

    Kraft moved the focus of the School to Britain, it is appropriate that the English language continuation ofthe School in this journal should more fully assimilate the Liberal content of the English tradition, which is

    at once so characteristic of it and at the same time so different from the hostility to Liberal principles that

    marked Germany and German philosophy in the days of both Fries and Nelson (e.g. Hegel and

    Heidegger) and even still today (when Heidegger has been turned into "deconstruction" and "post-modernism" -- both bywords for trendy leftism, as in the case of Richard Rorty).

    Philosophy of Religion

    Fries's view of religion had added an aesthetic dimension to Kant's moralistic "religion within the limits ofreason alone." Nelson's associate Rudolf Otto, however, recognized that religion contained even more

    than this: The sense of the "sacred" or the "holy" was not just a matter of moral judgment, as Kant had

    thought, nor even also just a matter of aesthetic judgment, as Fries had added, but was special and sui

    generis in its own independent modality. The only argument Otto needed for this was a descriptive andphenomenological one based on historical religions. That God might ask Abraham to sacrifice his son, or

    that Jesus might take the sins of the world upon himself in the Crucifixion, or that Salvation might be by

    http://www.friesian.com/hayek.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/foundatn.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/socrates.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/quiz.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/otto.htm

  • 6/22/2014 The Principles of Friesian Philosophy

    http://www.friesian.com/friesian.htm 6/6

    "faith alone," as separately taught by Luther and Shinran, are

    all aspects of religion that could not be captured either by

    morality or by aesthetics. The traditional response of

    philosophers, ever since Xenophanes and Socrates, was to

    ignore or dismiss them as immoral or unedifying; but thisclearly fails to "save the phenomena." Only Otto, on the

    basis of Friesian epistemology and metaphysics, could

    realize their significance. "Salvation" as a religious concept,whether in Christianity, Islam, Hinduism, or Buddhism, is

    independent of morality and aesthetics. Even in Judaism,

    "walking in the ways of the Lord," clearly involves obeying

    regulations for ritual purity and distinctive behaviors thatcannot be given either a moral or aesthetic justification.

    While the bien pensants at the beginning of the 20th

    Century figured that religion would wither away in the face ofscientific enlightenment, this did not happen; and at the

    beginning of the 21th Century the danger of religious

    fanaticism feeding large scale wars is greater than it has been

    since perhaps the Thirty Years War. While this has enabledfrank atheists (e.g. Christopher Hitchens, Richard Dawkins)

    to again blame human evils on religion, they are in the awkward position of explaining why their alternative

    has remained so unpopular (or, for that matter, was associated with ideological mass murder in the 20th

    Century). Instead, people have understood all too well that a world merely of science, without religioustranscendence, is a bleak Existential desert, devoid of meaning. With the addition of Otto and Hayek, the

    Friesian School hopefully achieves a broad, enlightened, and non-reductionistic approach to all the

    problems of philosophy and of the human condition.

    Return to Friesian School on the Home Page

    Return to The Project of the Friesian School on the Home Page

    The Sources and Influence of the Kant-Friesian School

    History of Philosophy

    Home Page Contents

    Copyright (c) 1997, 1998, 1999, 2000, 2001, 2007 Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved

    http://www.friesian.com/six.htm#japanhttp://www.friesian.com/afghan.htm#fascismhttp://www.friesian.com/francia.htm#hapsburg-2http://www.friesian.com/existent.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/#schoolhttp://www.friesian.com/#criticalhttp://www.friesian.com/school.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/history.htmhttp://www.friesian.com/#contentshttp://www.friesian.com/ross/http://www.friesian.com/#ross