technological knowledge and technological change

16
!&chnolqgy in Society, Vol. 13, pp. 289-304,1991 Printed in the USA. All rights reserved. 0160-79lX/91$3.00 + .OO Copyright Q 1991 Pergamon Press plc Technological Knowledge and Technological Change Govindan Parayil* ABSTRACT. Interest in technological change stems from our belief that it is responsible for inducing lasting social and economic changes. One important aspect of technological change that is often overlooked in the literature on the history of technology in general and technological change in particular is its cognitive aspect. This is because of the apparently tacit nature of technological knowledge. It is argued that instead of putting primary emphasis on change in the physical artifacts of this phenomenon, moo!els and theories of technological change should take into consideration how the knowledge content of technology itself changes. Hence, technological change should be conceptualized and modeled within the framework of an evolutionary epistemology of technological knowledge. Introduction Technological change, one of the most important conceptual problems and also a major research program in the newly emerging field of science and technology studies (STS), is a dynamic and multidimensional phe- nomenon involving invention, innovation, assessment, and transfer of technology. The profound interest in technological change stems from the belief that it is responsible for lasting social changes and rapid economic development. ‘Ibchnology is not only tools, machines, and other such arti- facts, but also a form of knowledge created by humans. Technological change involves social, economic, organizational, and cognitive factors. My objective in this article is to provide a theoretical and epistemological framework for conceptualizing the phenomenon of technological change. Govindan Parayil is an Assistant Professor in the Humanities, Science, and !&chnology Progmm at Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University. His major research interests are history of technology, technological change in its social and cultuml context, and technology transfer. He has published numerous articles in these areas. Originally trained as an engineer, he received the first Ph.D. in Science and Technology Studies (STS) from Viiinia Polytechnic Institute and State University in May, 1999. 289

Upload: govindan-parayil

Post on 21-Jun-2016

224 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Technological knowledge and technological change

!&chnolqgy in Society, Vol. 13, pp. 289-304,1991 Printed in the USA. All rights reserved.

0160-79lX/91$3.00 + .OO Copyright Q 1991 Pergamon Press plc

Technological Knowledge and Technological Change

Govindan Parayil*

ABSTRACT. Interest in technological change stems from our belief that it is responsible for inducing lasting social and economic changes. One important aspect of technological change that is often overlooked in the literature on the history of technology in general and technological change in particular is its cognitive aspect. This is because of the apparently tacit nature of technological knowledge. It is argued that instead of putting primary emphasis on change in the physical artifacts of this phenomenon, moo!els and theories of technological change should take into consideration how the knowledge content of technology itself changes. Hence, technological change should be conceptualized and modeled within the framework of an evolutionary epistemology of technological knowledge.

Introduction

Technological change, one of the most important conceptual problems and also a major research program in the newly emerging field of science and technology studies (STS), is a dynamic and multidimensional phe- nomenon involving invention, innovation, assessment, and transfer of technology. The profound interest in technological change stems from the belief that it is responsible for lasting social changes and rapid economic development. ‘Ibchnology is not only tools, machines, and other such arti- facts, but also a form of knowledge created by humans. Technological change involves social, economic, organizational, and cognitive factors. My objective in this article is to provide a theoretical and epistemological framework for conceptualizing the phenomenon of technological change.

Govindan Parayil is an Assistant Professor in the Humanities, Science, and !&chnology Progmm at Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University. His major research interests are history of technology, technological change in its social and cultuml context, and technology transfer. He has published numerous articles in these areas. Originally trained as an engineer, he received the first Ph.D. in Science and Technology Studies (STS) from Viiinia Polytechnic Institute and State University in May, 1999.

289

Page 2: Technological knowledge and technological change

290 G. Parayil

The concepts of technology as knowledge and technological change as essentially a process of knowledge change form the framework for this article. I will present arguments for technological change as essentially a form of knowledge change. Based on this framework, I will provide a complete account of technological change.

Technology as Knowledge

Although scientific change is a thriving research problem in history, phi- losophy, and sociology (the main participating disciplines of STS),l tech- nological change has not yet attracted the same interest. This fact has little to do with the nature of technology itself as a knowledge system. Instead it results from the delayed acceptance of the idea of the intellec- tual and epistemological autonomy of technology as a knowledge system separate from science.

The intellectual autonomy of technology as a knowledge system has been well established.2 The previous prevalent assumption that technol- ogy is only science applied for practical purposes or simply that technolo- gy is applied science3 is being discarded by many analysts of technology. Historians of science writing on the history of technology have created a variety of misconceptions about the fundamental relationship between science and technology, and their interaction with society. Historians of technology have to retrieve the history of technology from the poor histo- riographic scholarship demonstrated by the historians of science.4 Studies in the history, philosophy, and sociology of technology, for exam- ple, have clearly established the autonomy of technology from science.5 We owe more to the community of historians of technology for this devel- opment. The relationship between science and technology is dialectical, or interactive, rather than sequential and hierarchical.6 According to Clark (1987, p. 261, “. . . ‘science’ and ‘technology’ can be regarded as dis- tinct social systems observing different rules of conduct, coming from independent professional traditions and being largely autonomous in the influence one has on the other.” Technology and science benefit immense- ly from each other. The great progress in technology and science, particu- larly in the twentieth century, clearly manifests this process of mutual enrichment. Science and technology are intellectually and epistemologi- tally autonomous entities, but related to each other dialectically

A major outcome of the acceptance of technology as an autonomous enterprise has been the recognition of “technology as knowledge.” This recognition essentially stems from the efforts of modern historians of technology,7 who discarded the old methodology of writing the history of technology, which treated technology as artifacts developed with ideas from science. These modern historians developed a new historiographic method of looking at technology as a body of knowledge with its own

Page 3: Technological knowledge and technological change

!&chnological Knowledge and !tkhrwlogical Change 291

internal dynamics of change and progress. Technology has technological laws, which influence or help to create technological designs and new artifacts.8

The concept of technology as knowledge differs from science as knowl- edge in many respects. Technological knowledge can be often tacit,9 less amenable to the written form, and hence characterized as “papyrophobic”lo in nature. Vincenti (1984) divides technological knowl- edge into three categories: (a) descriptive, (b) prescriptive, and (c> tacit. Descriptive and prescriptive categories denote varieties of explicit tech- nological knowledge, and tacit denotes procedural technological knowl- edge. However, Vincenti argues that there are gradations of prescriptive knowledge, and sometimes this can be categorized as procedural techno- logical knowledge as well, because tacit and prescriptive knowledge are closely related in practice.

Although the fundamental building block of technology is ideas, tech- nology is at the same time both a public and private “good.“ll Compared to other forms of knowledge, technological knowledge is more easily kept private and secret through intellectual property rights. But at the same time, the artifacts generated from such knowledge have to return to the public realm of economic systems mediated largely through the market mechanism for their dissemination, diffusion, and ultimate survival. This paradoxical situation is unique to technological knowledge. Scientific knowledge, on the other hand, has to remain public in order to be accepted as certified knowledge.

Technological knowledge, in a different sense, is tacit to the extent that its transmission is possible without being presented as certified knowl- edge. This transmission is possible through craft traditions, family prac- tices, and shop-floor apprenticeship programs. However, this aspect of technological knowledge transmission is becoming less prominent as large segments of technological knowledge become part of the public domain. Technology also differs from science in that technology is a visu- al activity,12 often with visible and tangible effects.

Ideas form the core of technology. All our artifacts originate in thoughts and ideas. Technology is, in effect, the activities, both intellec- tual and physical, that humans engage in based on ideas and thoughts.13 An anthropological measure of technology reveals that the idea to use a stone or a stick for extending the power of the human hand evolved as a cognitive process, which, in turn, is inextricably linked to human evolu- tionary processes. The externalization of the cognitive responses to the natural world, first with the simple stones and sticks, then with the stone axes and the wooden ploughs, culminating in the sophisticated tools, machines, and instruments of contemporary civilizations results in technological artifacts born out of ideas and thoughts and ultimately of human experiences. The development of technology as a knowledge sys- tem is attributable to the increasing sophistication of human cognitive

Page 4: Technological knowledge and technological change

292 G. Parayil

processes and activities. ‘IUmology constitutes knowledge, and all tech- nologies are embodiments of some form of human knowledge. Levinson (1988) argues that the technological artifacts we have developed aug- ment the functioning of our cognitive faculties. The growth of technologi- cal knowledge is a direct manifestation of its cumulative nature. The pro- cess of technological change is both a cumulative and an evolutionary process.

As Layton (1974) correctly points out, ideas and thoughts were always considered integral in the historical development of technology. But this important aspect of technology was denied temporarily when technology was relegated to the status of applied science. According to him, “the sep- aration of knowledge and technology is both recent and artificial” (p. 35). But analysts of technology, mostly historians of technology who knew better, have stood firm and reversed this ahistorical attribution. The works of several historians 14 of technology established ideas and infor- mation rather than material artifacts as the fundamental constituents of technology.

What Is Technological Change?

Thus it becomes apparent through these recent works that technological change is not a mere concatenation of artifacts, but a change in techno- logical knowledge itself. However, interest in technological change had been shown by many other disciplines, besides history, before it became a major research problem. Nevertheless, this interest was not prompted by theoretical interest in explaining the nature or process of technological change but by the well founded belief that the progressive change in the technological knowledge base of a society directly corresponds to econom- ic and social change. 15 Political economists Hume (19551, Smith (1976/1776), and Marx (1952/1848 and 1967/1867) comprehended the importance of technological change in bringing about economic develop- ment and social change. It was Marx who saw the revolutionary role of technological change in generating economic growth.16 Marx and Engels predicted that the bourgeoisie, whose historic role is to “constantly revo- lutionize the means of production,” would create a modern capitalist eco- nomic system, which in turn would be expropriated by the revolutionary proletariat to create a socialist economic system.17 While they implicitly agreed that the capitalist system would be more efficient not only in terms of creating newer technology, new products, and high profits, they contended that the means of production in a socialist system would be less alienating (to the proletariat) and would be more equitable.18

Although academic interest in technological change declined consider- ably after Marx, it picked up again in the beginning of this century. The first modern economist to show considerable interest in it was Schumpeter

Page 5: Technological knowledge and technological change

!ikchnobgical &owl&e and !&chm&ical Change 293

(1950/1942; 1939). Historian Usher (1954/1929; 1965) and sociologist Gilflllan (1970/1935), among others, followed suit. Although these ana- lysts emphasized different aspects of technological change, particularly their emphasis upon certain idiosyncratic vocabularies,lg their ultimate interests were intimately related to the process of change in technology.

Considerable interest in technological change began to be manifest amongneoclassical economists in the 1950s with the works of Abramovitz (1956) and Solow (1957), followed by the works of Mansfield (19611, Griliches (19601, and Schmookler (19661, among others. Although they were not primarily concerned with the process or the internal dynamics of technological change itself, their interests were predicated upon the assumption that economic growth was primarily caused by technological change rather than the interminable infusion of capital into the economic system, as was widely believed then.20 Their interest in technological change was limited because they were primarily inter- ested in the phenomena responsible for productivity increase. The pre- dominant neoclassical model of technological change was based on a pro- duction function based theory of input/output relationships.

Interest in technology in general, and technological change in particu- lar, on the part of economic historians, historians of technology, and soci- ologists of technology also began to emerge concurrently, but for the most part separately from each other and from mainstream economists.21 Most of these analysts proposed their own interpretations of technologi- cal change and in turn developed models to represent and explain this phenomenon. They worked within their own areas of inquiry or disci- plines. A few among them attempted to transcend the constraints of their disciplines to use perspectives and tools from other disciplines to explain technological change. However, these attempts did not go far enough, for obvious reasons, because in the final analysis they looked at technology through the microscopic eye of their individual disciplines and areas of inquiry. In order to represent the dynamic and multidimen- sional character of technological change one needs to give up disciplinary loyalties and ground one’s arguments in an interdisciplinary framework.

The objective of analyzing technological change tends to vary from dis- cipline to discipline, although most analysts implicitly concede that tech- nological change is essential for economic development and social change. Economists may be primarily interested in the economic impact of technological change. Sociologists and anthropologists may be looking for the changes in the social structures and cultural practices and mores due to this phenomenon. Historians may tend to concentrate on chroni- cling the cumulative nature of technological change in the making of industrial civilizations. Philosophers concentrate on the moral and ethi- cal implications of technological change and progress, and develop methodological tools for technology assessment. Nevertheless, despite these differences, the needs for new technologies to solve human prob-

Page 6: Technological knowledge and technological change

294 G. Parayil

lems and for ways to develop new technologies remain a major factor influencing the thinking of analysts of technological change across disciplines.

It is not necessarily the case that technological change interests only those interested in its effects on progressive social and economic change resulting in the improved well-being of humans. It also has become a topic for intense intellectual debate among some analysts of technology. Some analysts consider technological change a dangerous force which not only produces social and material progress, but which ultimately destroys human freedom and liberty.22 Thus the price for progress, they argue, is less freedom and liberty These analysts argue that technologi- cal change has become an autonomous force beyond human control. This is an important charge, which needs further scrutiny, but which is, how- ever, beyond the scope of this article.

Interest in technological change is not only intense in the developed world but in the developing countries as well. The spectacular rise in the standard of living of the peoples in industrialized nations is attributed to the technological change that has been going on at an intense pace for the past 200 to 300 years. The increased pace of technological change in countries affected by the Industrial Revolution was responsible for this. The importance of technological change in enhancing the economic well- being of humans is well understood. 23 Because of these precedents, developing countries are also interested in fostering technological change for improving the standard of living of their peoples through measures like technology transfer.

Given that interest in technological change varies according to the dis- ciplinary and individual objectives of the analysts, it should come as no surprise that there is no consensus yet on a consistent theoretical expla- nation of technological change. Likewise, it is an epistemologically risky exercise to look for a simple and consistent definition of technological change. This risk is primarily due to the lack of a consistent definition for technology itself. Most scholarly works on the subject circumvent the need for providing a definition of technological change.24 Most analysts, unable to quite articulate it, skip this part and go on to explain the impact of technological change on human society or explain what its con- stituent components are or offer models based on case studies of techno- logical change. This is not to say that definitions of technological change are never found in the literature. In neoclassical economic literature we fmd the usage of capital-labor ratios to define biased or neutral techno- logical change.25

Technological change may be defined as a temporal and cumulative process which increases the ability of a people or society to solve their social, economic, and other everyday existential problems. Technological change is, then, essentially a process of knowledge change - a cognitive process involving changes in the structure and content, and in the con-

Page 7: Technological knowledge and technological change

Technological Knowledge and !lkchnol&al Change 295

text of production of technological knowledge. Although the manifesta- tion of the change is tangible and apparent in material (a&factual) forms, the integral part of this process is cognitive in nature.

A more rigorous definition of technological change is that it is the out- come of the activities that humans engage in through their collective or individual organizational structures, such as firms, households, or any other institutional agents or social units to optimize their resources sub- ject to constraints imposed by their own limitations in tandem with that of their environment.2s The problems generated by technological imbal- ances, bottle-necks, technological disequilibria, and other technological puzzles act as focusing devices to find solutions. Technological change, therefore, may be analyzed or looked at as essentially the outcome of a problem-solving activity.27

The manifestations of technological change may be the development of new products and machines and better and easier ways of solving soci- ety’s problems. The nature, process, and outcome of technological change may vary from countries, regions, and cultures based upon their particu- lar social, political, and economic systems, despite the fact that technolo- gy is increasingly transcultural. 28 The development of new technologies and the relative improvement in the standard of living in the market-ori- ented Western nations where efficiency is stressed more than equity have been far greater than in the socialist, centrally-planned nations where equity is stressed more than efficiency29 On the other hand, in much of the Third World, where both free market and centrally-planned economic systems prevail, technological change is less rapid than in either the East or the West.30

One of the significant aspects of technological change, as mentioned earlier, is transfer of technology between nations and cultures, an activi- ty that has been going on since antiquity Although the present trend is the transfer of technology from the West to the East, before the onset of the Industrial Revolution in Europe, much of technology transfer was in the opposite direction. 31 The borrowing and importation of technological artifacts and know-how speed up the process of change in the technologi- cal knowledge base of the recipients.32 The transferred technology often acts as a catalyst for further change by encouraging new inventions and innovations on the newly acquired technology. Technological change may be generally characterized as the combined effect of several technologi- cally-related activities, such as invention, innovation, development, transfer, and diffusion.33 It is not necessary that these components have to follow the same sequence in every case involving technological change, nor for that matter is it necessary to have all these forces present in every case of technological change. Although these individual compo- nents are conceptually distinct, it is empirically often difficult to tell when one ends and the other begins. Bryant (1976) argues that the best approach to studying technological changes would be to treat them not

Page 8: Technological knowledge and technological change

296 G. Parayil

as chronological sequences, but instead, as forces operating in an interac- tive-dialectical manner following an evolutionary course.34

Like Bryant, most analysts emphasize different aspects of technologi- cal change, depending upon their areas of specialization or disciplinary areas in which they have been trained. Thus they tend to see the whole process (of technological change) just in terms of invention, innovation, transfer, or diffusion. Schumpeter (19391, for example, considers innova- tion as the key force that brings about technological change, and neglects or deemphasizes other forces, like invention and transfer. Usher (19541, on the.other hand, treats technological change as a “cumulative synthe- sis” ‘ofinventive activities. However, a careful analysis of Usher’s model reveal& that the constituents of the cumulative synthesis concept include othenaspects of technological change, like innovation and diffusion.

GilfWm’s (1970/1935) 38 “social principles of invention” include refer- ence&to other aspects of technological change like transfer, development, and!dWu&on.of technology, although he conflates all these into inven- tion. .I%oclassical economists generally emphasize innovation and inven- tion.= Institutional economists, on the other hand, consider all aspects of technological change important, but emphasize diffusion and transfer of technology more. 36 Historians of technology who pay more attention to the internal history of technology seem to emphasize invention and transfer of technology. 37 Analysts of technological change who approach technological change using systems theory emphasize innovation and dif- fusion processes more than the others.38 Also, there are several analysts of technological change who consider technological change to be similar to or epistemologically akin to scientific change.39

The divergence of views, grouped as they are by discipline, helps to frame the following question: Do disciplinary biases influence models of technological change in providing a complete and clear picture of this process? To answer this ..question it should be ascertained whether the frequent characterization of technological change in the literature as one of the component forces of this dynamic process is only a semantic prob- lem, or whether it goes deeper, in turn hampering a clear and complete conceptualization of technological change. Since there are no competent theories of technological change developed from an interdisciplinary stand-point or for that matter from a disciplinary perspective, it is important in technology studies to take a unified approach to studying this phenomenon without being constrained by disciplinary loyalties.

Technological change is essentially a qualitative phenomenon. This is a Cmdamental premise in conceptualizing technological change as knowl- edge change. Mathematical and econometric models of technological change may not represent this phenomenon correctly or completely. For example, counting patent statistics in an industry as a representative trend of technological change in fact tells us very little about technologi- cal change.40 There are some analysts of technological change who use

Page 9: Technological knowledge and technological change

!lkchn&gical Knowledge and llxhn&gical Change 297

econometric models to explain diffusion of new technologies.41 Although these exercises might explain the rate of diffusion of a new technology, they do not tell us the underlying extant factors responsible for the adop- tion of new technologies.

!&chn.&gical Change as Knowledge Change

I have already argued the case for technology as knowledge following the lead provided by Layton (1974). Technological change involves a heuristic in which a technological algorithm helps in deciding how the new knowl- edge can be transformed into material outputs and artifacts. The techno- logical algorithm is nothing but a simplified means for transforming complex knowledge created by technologists and scientists into a simpli- fied form that workers, farmers, and artisans could absorb in order to produce the desired outputs. The process of change is clearly a conceptu- al-cum-cognitive one, whether it is complex biotecbnological knowledge being told in simple language to farmers by extension agents,. or the translation of a large design into bridges, machines, and automated -pro- duction systems, or the diagnostic results available for ordinary medical workers from an elaborate diagnostic expert system.

Technological change here involves not just the introduction of a few artifacts, but essentially the change in the actors’ knowledge related to agriculture, production, and medical diagnosis. In many instances, these actors provide important feedback to the so-called experts who were ostensibly responsible for the creation of the new knowledge. Farmers give important suggestions to extension agents to improve seeds and mechanical implements; important innovations evolve from shopfloors; and improved diagnostic techniques may emerge from the users of the

expert system.42 It is obvious that because the actors who make the decisionsregarding

technological selection are particular groups of people in the society, and they are motivated by political, economic, and cultural concerns, techno- logical change is both socially constructed and political-economic in nature. The former may appear to be a tautology because, being mem- bers of a society, all our actions, beliefs, and decisions are social construc- tions. Because of the self-referencing of our actions, social construction arguments for developing models of technological change turn up explanatory rather than analytical. Political-economic arguments, on the contrary, turn out to be powerful analytical categories. We know that great technological developments were the direct results of governmental actions.

The latter argument becomes quite clear if we take a look at the histo- ry of technological change. It used to be widely believed that technologi- cal change was caused largely by the works of individual inventors who

Page 10: Technological knowledge and technological change

298 G. Parayil

tinker with artifacts, and that the rest of the society accepted new tech- nologies whenever they were offered to the public. The rise of organized production based on the factory system in the nineteenth century forced the capitalists to improve the technology for increasing productivity, to reduce the power of workers who could strike for better pay and working conditions, to substitute materials and methods of production, to stifle competition, and to reduce production costs. The decline of feudalism and the rise of industrial production marked this change in social labor and social production first in Western Europe. The search for improved tech- nology became a profession now of the technologists and scientists employed by the firms. Thus the creation of new technological develop- ment moved from the realm of individual inventors to the hands of orga- nized R&D efforts of both government and industry. Governmental regu- lations, market forces, consumer preferences, and environmental factors also influence the course of technological change and development. With governments actively involving themselves through science and technolo- gy policy instruments, the course of technological change began to take a different form since the World War I. This process began to take on a fre- netic pace during the World War II and after because of massive govern- mental investments in scientific and technological development activities.

While the political-economic and social interests set the stage for tech- nological change and determine its trajectory, the actual process of learn- ing and the cognitive processes required for that change are dictated by cultural and cognitive attributes of the members of the particular social groups involved. Through premeditated and consciously thought-out actions, humans try to change nature to satisfy their needs. While the social, political, economic, and other factors set the stage for change, the internal dynamics of the actual change are determined by the functional attributes of the technology: the requirements for energy substitution, the possibilities for diminishing human intervention, the possibilities of automation for avoiding hazardous actions and for increasing productivi- ty, the ability for invariant reproduction of products and services based on the same ideas and design concepts, the sustainability of action through methods of communication and control, and finally the decision- rules humans establish to decide between alternative courses of actions.43

Conclusion

Technological change should be conceptualized as essentially a form of knowledge change. Instead of putting primary emphasis on the change in the physical artifacts, models and theories of this phenomenon should take into consideration how the knowledge content of technology itself

Page 11: Technological knowledge and technological change

Technological Knowledge and lkchnological Change 299

changes, and hence primary emphasis should be placed on the actors involved with each category of technology and its institutional struc- tures. The appearance of newer artifacts should be interpreted as the manifestations of the phenomenon and not the phenomenon itself. Technological change should be modeled within the framework of an evo- lutionary epistemology of technological knowledge.

Insights from all the disciplines and areas of inquiry on technology should be integrated without disciplinary loyalties to develop a compre- hensive theoretical account of technological change. Technological change is a continuous, cumulative, and, largely, an irreversible process.44 By cumulative it is meant that often ideas, practices, laws, and theories from the past do pass on to the development of newer technologies. The reasons why this aspect tends to be neglected or does not seem apparent is due to the tacit nature of technological knowledge.

Notes

1. Besides these three disciplines, economics, political science, and anthropology are some other disciplines that are involved with STS. These disciplines are more involved in technology than in science, because technology is more overtly related to economic growth and development, political-economy, and cultural issues that we face.

2. For a pioneering work in this regard, see Layton (1974). 3. Wise (19851, Price (19651, and Beer (1965) explore this ahistorical assumption exceedingly well.

They argue that this misconception was popularized by some science historians and science policy-makers.

4. Price (1974, p. 46) makes this point explicit by admitting that: “We historians of technology should bow our heads in even greater shame that so many administrators of science should derive such knowledge as they have of the science-and-technology interactions from cooked-up investigations like Project Hindsight and Traces instead of from any conventional wisdom of our own making.”

5. The formation in 1958 of the Society for the History of Technology (SHOT) and its journal Zlxhrwlogy and Culture, along with numerous books and papers, are testimonials to this claim from the perspectives of history. The formation in 1975 of the Society for Philosophy of Technology and the numerous volumes of books published under its sponsorship credit the interest of philosophy in technology. In sociology, the movement to develop a sociology of technology is exemplified by the publication of a volume edited by Bijker et al. (1987). This movement may be better identified as social studies of technology.

6. The relationship between science and technology is described with various metaphors, for example, “mirror-image twins” (Layton, 19711; science and technology as two autonomous spheres of knowledge, the former about the “natural world” and the latter about the ‘man-made world” (Wise, 1985); science and technology as a “pair of dancers” dancing to the “music of instrumentalities” (Price, 1984; 1965); and science and technology relate to each other “interactively” (Barnes, 1982). As an aside, Price attributes to Arnold lbynbee the dancing pair metaphor for science and technology. ‘Ihynbee in his Introduction: The Geneses of Civilizations, Vol. I, no. l(1962, p. 3), conceives of “Physical Science and Industrialism” as “a pair of dancers.”

7. Besides Layton other pioneers in the field are Walter Vincenti, Lynn White, Carl Condit, Ladislao Reti, Eugene Ferguson, de Solla Price, Hunter Dupree, Robert Multhauf, Melvin Rranzberg, and Carroll Pursell, among others.

8. For more on this see Layton (1974). 9. The otten “tacit” nature of knowledge generating processes was first recognized by Michael

Polanyi (1958, p. 491.

Page 12: Technological knowledge and technological change

300 G. Parayil

10. This differentiation was made explicit by de Solla Price (1974, p. 37). This distinction may be less prominent now than it was before because of the increasing prominence of research and development activities geared toward technological development, and of the proliferation of published work along with efforts intended for integrating and codifying technological knowledge.

11. For a pioneering work on this facet of technology, see Nelson (1989). 12. For more on this facet of technology, see Ferguson (1977). 13. Florman (1976, p. 58) argues that technology is not a thing, but merely “one of the activities”

humans engage in by choice or by force. Pitt (1988, p. 448) argues that technology is “humanity at work.” According to Huning (1985, p. 111, the pioneering work on the “anthropology of technology” was first done by Ernst Rapp in his Grundlnien einer Phdosophie der !&chnik (1877) [“Foundations of a Philosophy of Technology.“] Rapp uses the term Grganprojektion or “organ projection” to refer to technology.

14. A few examples, besides Layton’s work are, White (19691, Kranzberg and Purse11 (19671, Ferguson (19741, and de Solla Price (1965).

15. One major manifestation of these changes was the dramatic improvement in the standard of living of the people (mostly in the West) who experienced the most rapid technological change during the past 100 years.

16. Marx, in both A Manifesto ofthe Communist Party (1952/1848) and in Capital, Vol. I (1967/1867), clearly emphasized the role that technological change (changes in the means of production) plays in the dynamics of capitalist economic systems.

17. See Marx and Engels (19520848). 18. Rosenberg (1988) argues that the relatively poor performance of socialist economies in

generating new technologies through rapid technological change compared to the market- oriented capitalist economies was due to the former’s neglect of efficiency and its emphasis only on equity

19. Schumpeter called this process “technological innovation,” but excluded invention from the locus of technological change. Usher called this process “invention,n which was an umbrella for all the phases of technological change. Gilfillan developed his theories of technological change based on the premise of a “sociology of invention.”

20. Solow’s (1957) empirically-based study of the United States economy for the period from 1909 to 1949 shows that technological change was responsible for 87.5% of increase in output per worker hour, while only 12.5% of increase in output per worker hour was due to increased use of capital.

21. A few of these analysts are Rosenberg (1976, 1982), David (1975), Hanieski (1973), and Habakkuk (1962) from economic history; White (19621, Hughes (19831, Constant (19801, and Susskind (19731 from the history of technology; Bijker, Hughes, and Pinch (19871, and Law (1987) from the sociology of technology; and Dosi (1982). Nelson and Winter (1977), Sahal (1981), and DeGregori (1985) from an evolutionary perspective.

22. Some analysts of technological change warn that it is becoming a force beyond human and societal control that destroys freedom and liberty Some analysts who hold these views are Ellul (1964), Mumford (19671, and Winner (1977).

23. Analysts like Adam Smith (1976/1776) and Marx (1952/1848) pointed out this fact way before empirical studies by modern economists like Solow (1957), Abramovitz (19561, and others demonstrated it in their works. Works by Coombs et al. (19871, DeGregori (1985), Solo and Rogers (1972). Fransman (1986), and Binswanger and Ruttan (1978) also have demonstrated this conclusively.

24. For example, in De Bresson’s (1987a) Understanding !&chn&gical Change, there is no definition for technological change, and he does not even explain clearly what this means.

25. In the biased technological change categories there are technologies that would be capital-saving or labor-saving. In the neutral category the capital-labor ratio is always one and the technology favors neither labor nor capital. See Hicks (1932) for more on these.

26. This definition is conceptually closer to the idea of clearing out “bottlenecks,” solving “technological imbalances,” and ‘technological disequilibrium.” See Hanieski (1973) and Rosenberg (1969, 1976) for more on this. The puzzles thrown out by these situations are solved by any number of methods, such as investing in R&D efforts, innovations on shop floors and in the fields and farms, new inventions, etc.

27. The assumption that technological change may be examined as a problem-solving activity was used by Rosenberg and Vmcenti (1978) in their work on the history of the Britannia Bridge.

Page 13: Technological knowledge and technological change

l%chnokgical Knowledge and lkchmbgical Chunge 301

28. For an excellent treatment of the transcultural nature of technology, see DeGregori (1985) and Lower (1988).

29. See Rosenberg (1988) for more on this. 30. It is beyond the scope of this article to go into the details of why this is so. Lingering effects of

neocolonialism, unequal exchange prices between primary commodities (of the Third World) and the finished products and machinery (of the developed nations), simmering internal problems due to semi-feudal social relations, ethnic and linguistic tensions, etc., might be a few reasons, apart from differing value-systems and beliefs regarding social progress and economic development.

31. Lynn White (1962) and Joseph Needham (1954) have chronicled the massive transfer of technologies from India and China to Europe before the Industrial Revolution. According to DeGregori (1985, p. 291, ‘The vast mejority of the technology of any people was developed by others. We are all or have been borrowers of technology. Technology transfer is a constant facet of human history.” Susskind (1973) also makes a similar claim.

32. A thorough theoretical grounding in the process of technological change is thus essential for formulating technology policies geared toward succes&~l technology transfer.

33. This may be taken as a third definition of technological change, although it refers to the temporal and cumulative, and the structural characteristics of this phenomenon.

34. Bryant identifies only invention, innovation, and development as these forces. Bryant explains the process of technological change in the case of the diesel engine between the period 1890-1908.

35. See, for example, Schmookler (1966) [invention] and Mansfield (1961) [innovation]. 36. See, for example, Ruttan and Hayami (19731, Ruttan and Binswanger (19781, and DeGregori

(19851, among others. 37. See, for example, White (1962) and David (1975). Hughes’ (1983) systems model of technological

change emphasixes the crucial role of inventor-entrepreneurs. 38. While Sahal(1981) emphasizes both, Saviotti (1983) emphasizes only innovation. 39. While Constant (1980) and Dosi (1982) argue that technological paradigms characterize

technological change h 24 Kuhn (1970, scientific paradigms), Nelson and Winter (1977) chart the path of technological change along a technological trajectory.

40. It may reflect the rats of invention in a industry, but does not tell us how inventions are carried out. Schmookler’s (1966) methodology of studying the trend of technological change using patent statistics suffers from such an inadequacy.

41. This practice is popular among economists. See Sahal(1981) and MansfIeld (1966). 42. See Biggs (1980). Gamser (19881, and Von Hippel(1988) for how ordinary technology users like

farmers and customers were instmmental in developing new products and technologies. 43. Daniel Bell (1975) cogently analyzes how a few of these dimensions of technology transform

culture and social structures. 44. De Bresson argues that these facets of technological change embolden us to quip that “One

needn’t reinvent the wheel” (1987b, p. 752). As part of his 35 social principles of invention, Giltlllan (1970) postulated that few inventions are ever lost.

Bibliography

Abramovite, M. (1956), ‘Resource and Output Trends in the United States Since 1870,” in Rosenberg, fed.), (1971) pp. 320-343.

Barnes, B., ‘The science-technology relationship: A model and a query,” Social Studies of science, Vol. 12 (1982) pp. X6-172.

Basalla, G., The Evolution of !&chtw@y, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). Beer, J J., ‘The Historical Relations of Science and Technology,,” 7hchnology and Cultwe, Vol. 6, no.

4, pp. 547-532. Bell, D., ‘%chnology, Nature, and Society,” in The Frontiers of Knowledge, (Garden City, NV.:

Doubleday, 19751, pp. 27-78. Biggs, S.D., “Informal R&D,” Gems, Vol. 13, no. 4 (19801, pp. 23-26. Bijker, W.E., Hughes, TX, and Pinch, T. (eds.), The Social Conetruction of lb&nolo&al Systems:

New Directiona in the Sociology and Hietory of lkchnokgy (Cambridge, MA.: The MIT Press,

Page 14: Technological knowledge and technological change

302 G. Parayil

Binswanger, H. and Ruttan, V.W. teds.), Induced Innovation: Technology, Institutions and Deuelopment (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978).

Bryant, L., “The Development of the Diesel Engine,” %hnoZogy and CuZture, Vol. 17, no. 3, pp. 432-446.

Clark, N., “Similarities and Differences Between Scientific and Technological Paradigms,” Futures, Vol. 19, no. 1, pp. 26-42.

Constant, E.W., The Origins ofthe Z’brbojet Revolution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1980). Coombs, R., Saviotti, P., and Walsh, V, Economics and !&chnoZogical Change (lbtowa, N.J.: Rowman

& Littlefield, 1987). David, P., lbzhnical Choice, Innovation and Economic Growth (New York: Cambridge University

Press, 1975). DeBresson, C., Understanding Technological Change (Montreal-New York: Black Rose Books,

1987a). DeBresson, C., “The Evolutionary Paradigm and the Economics of Technological Change,” Journal

of Economic Issues Vol. 21, no. 2 (1987b) pp. 751-762. DeGregori, T.R., A Theory of !&chnology: Continuity and Change in Human Development (Ames,

Iowa: Iowa State University Press, 1985). Dosi, G., “Technological paradigms and technological trajectories,” Research Policy, Vol. ll(1982) pp.

147-162. Ellul, J., The !&chnoZogical Society (New York: Knopf, 1964). Ferguson, E.S., ‘The Mind’s Eye: Nonverbal Thought in Technology,” Science, Vol. 197, no. 4306, (26

August, 1977), pp. 827-836. Ferguson, E.S., “lbward a Discipline of the History of Technology,” !&chndogy and Culture, Vol. 15,

No. l(1974) pp. 13-30. Florman, S.C., The Existential Pleasures of Engineering (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1976). Fransman, M., lbchnology and Economic Development (Boulder, CO.: Westview Press, 1986). Gamser, M.S., “Innovation, Technical Assistance, and Development: The Importance of Technology

Users,” World Development, Vol. 16, no. 8 (1988) pp. 711-720. Gilfillan, S.G., The Sociology of Invention (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1970/1935). Griliches, Z. (19601, “Hybrid Corn and the Economics of Innovation,” reprinted in Rosenberg, N.

(ed.), The Economics of l’bchnological Change (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971) pp. 212-228. Habakkuk, H.J., American and British Technology in the Nineteenth Century: The Search for

Labour-Saving Incentives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962). Hanieski, J.F., “The Airplane as an Economic Variable: Aspects of Technological Change in

Aeronautics, 1903-1955,” l&hnology and Culture, Vol. 14, no. 4 (1973) 535-552. Hicks, JR., The Theory of Wages (New York: Macmillan, 1932). Hughes, T.P., Networks of Power: Electrif~ation in Western Society, 188&1930 (Baltimore: Johns

Hopkins, 1983). Hume, D., Writings on Economics, E. Rotwein, ed. (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1955). Huning, A. (1985), ‘Homo Mensura: Human Beings Are Their Technology - Technology Is Human,”

in PT. Durbin (ed.), Research in Philosophy & !Z&hnology, Vol. 8 (Greenwich, CT: JAI Press) pp. 9-16.

Kranzberg, M. and Pursell, C.W., Technology in Western Ciuilixation, 2 Vols. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1967).

Kuhn, T.S.. The Structure of ScientifK Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). Laudan, R., (ed.1 The Nature of !Zbchnalogical Knowledge. Are MaEels of Scientifw Change Relevant?

(Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1984). Law, J., “On the Social explanation of Technical Change: The Case of the Portuguese Maritime

Expansion,” !Zbchnalogy and Culture, Vol. 28, no. 2 (1987). pp. 227-252. Layton, E.T., “lbchnology as Knowledge,” !&chnaZogy and Culture, Vo1.15, no. 1, (1974) pp. 31-41. Layton, E.T., “Mirror-Image Twins: The Communities of Science and Technology in 19thCentury

America,” Technology and Culture, Vol. 12 (1971) pp. 562-580. Levinson, P., Mind at Large: Knowing in the Technological Age (Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press, 1988). Lower, M., “The Concept of Technology Within the Institutionalist Perspective,” in Tool, M.R. (ed.),

Evolutionary Economics, Volume I (New York: M.E. Sharpe, 1988). Mansfield, E. (19611, “Technical Change and the Rate of Imitation,” in N. Rosenberg, (ed.), The

Economics of Tkchnological Change, (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1971)pp. 284-315.

Page 15: Technological knowledge and technological change

!&chnological Knowledge and lkchdogieal Change 303

Marx, IL, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vol. I (New York: International Publishers, 1967/1867).

Marx, If. and Engels, F., Manifeeto of the Communist Party (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 19520848).

Mumford, L., !&chnics and Civilization (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovitcb, 1963). Needham, J., Science and Ciuilizatian in China (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954). Nelson, RR., “What Is Private and What Is Public About Technology?” Science, Technology, &

Human Values, Vol. 14, no. 3 (1989) pp. 229-241. Nelson, RR. and Winter, S.G., An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change (Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press, 1982). Nelson, RR. and Winter, S.G. (1977), “In Search of Useful Theories of Innovation,“Research Policy,

Vol. 6 (1977) pp. 36-76. Pavitt, R., “The objectives of science policy,” Science and Public Policy Vol. 14, no. 4 (1987) pp.

182-188. Pinch, T. and Bijker, W.E. (1987), ‘l’be Social Construction of Facts and Artifacts,” in Bijker et al.,

op. cit. Pitt, J.C., “Style” and Technology,” !lkchnology in Society, Vol. 10 (1988) pp. 447456. Polanyi, M., Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (Chicago: University of

Chicago Press, 1958). Price, de Solla D.J., ‘Notes Towards A Philosophy of the Scienc&chnology Interaction,” in R.

Laudan, (ed.), op. cit., (1984) pp. 105-114. Price, de Solla D.J., “On the Historiographic Revolution in the History of Technology: Comments on

the Papers by Multhauf, Ferguson, and Layton,’ Txhnology and Culture, Vol. 15, no. 10974) pp. 42-48.

Price, de Solla D.J., “Is Technology Historically Independent of Science? A Study in Statistical Historiography,” !#chnology and Culture Vol. 6, no. 4 (1965) pp. 553-568.

Rosenberg, N., ‘lbchnological Change Under Capitalism and Socialism,” in Anderson, A and Bark, D.L. (eds.) Thinking About America: The United States in the 1999s (Stanford: Hoover Institution, 19881, pp. 191-202.

Rosenberg, N., Zn&!e the Blackbar: %hnology and Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).

Rosenberg, N., Perspectives on !lkhnohgy &monk, NY: M.E. Sharpe. Inc., 1976). Rosenberg, N. (1971), (ed.) The Economics of Technological Change (Harmondsworth: Penguin,

1971). Rosenberg, N., “The Direction of Technological Change: Inducement Mechanisms and Focusing

Devices,” Economic Development and Cultural Change, Vol. 18, no. 10969) pp. l-24. Rosenberg, N. and Vincenti, W.G., The Britannia Bridge: The Generation and Diffusion of

!Bxhnological KnowMge (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1978). Ruttan, VW. and Binswanger, H., “Induced Innovation and the Green Revolution,” in Binswanger

and Ruttan, op. cit. (1978) pp. 358-408. Ruttan, VW. and Hayami, Y. (1973), “Technology Transfer and Agriculture Development,”

lechnology and Culture, Vol. 14, no. 2 pp. 119-151. Sahal, D., Patterns of Technological Innovation (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1981). Saviotti, PP. (19831, “Systems Theory and Technological Change,” Futures, Vol. 18, no. 6 (1983) pp.

773-786. Schmookler, J., Znuention and Economic Growth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1966). Schumpeter, J.A. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper & Row, 1950/1942X Schumpeter, J.A, Business Cycles, Vol. I (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1939). Smith, A, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Chicago: University of

Chicago Press, 1976/1776). Solo, RA and Rogers, E.M., Inducing Technological Change for Economic Growth and Development

(East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 1972). Solow, R., “Technical Change and the Aggregate Production Function,” in Rosenberg, op. cit.

(1971/1957) pp. 344-362. Susskind, C., Understanding Technology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1973). Usher, AP., ‘lbchnical Change and Capital Formation,” in Rosenberg, op. cit. (1971/1955) pp. 43-72. Usher, A.P., A History of Mechanical Inventions (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,

1954/1929x

Page 16: Technological knowledge and technological change

304 G. Parayil

Vincenti, W.G., “Technological Knowledge without Science: The Invention of Flush Riveting in American Airplanes, ea. 193O-ca. 1950,” !khnology and Culture, Vol. 26 (1984) pp. 640-676.

Von Hippel, E., The Sowces ofZnnovation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988). White, L., Machinu ex Deo: Essays in the Dynumism of Western Culture (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard

University Press, 1969). White, L., Medieval !lkchnology and Social Change (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962). Winner, L., Autonomous Ipchnology: Technics-out-of-Control as a Theme in Political Thought

(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1977). Wise, G., ‘Science and Technology,” OSIRIS, 2nd series, Vol. l(1985) pp. 229-246.