reintegrative shaming and restorative justice

84
Reintegrative Shaming: The Essence of Restorative Justice. By Michael E. Marotta E00715351 CRIM 610: Theories of Criminal Behavior Dr. Gregg Barak Eastern Michigan University Winter 2009

Upload: michael-e-marotta

Post on 28-Oct-2014

217 views

Category:

Documents


4 download

DESCRIPTION

Term paper for graduate class in criminology theory.

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Reintegrative Shaming: The Essence of Restorative Justice.

By Michael E. MarottaE00715351CRIM 610: Theories of Criminal Behavior

Dr. Gregg BarakEastern Michigan UniversityWinter 2009

Page 2: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Table of Contents

Abstract.................................................................................................................1The Theory of Reintegrative Shaming...................................................................1Acceptance of the Theory.....................................................................................5Development and Integration of the Theory.......................................................13Practical Applications and Critical Dialectics.......................................................22Appendix A: Convenience Sample of College Textbooks...................................34Appendix B: Search of Academic Journal Articles..............................................36Appendix C: Reviews of Books by John Braithwaite...........................................40References..........................................................................................................46

Page 3: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 1

Reintegrative Shaming: The Essence of Restorative JusticeMichael E. Marotta1

Abstract:

Over the past 20 years, John Braithwaite’s theory of reintegrative shaming has garnered

sufficient attention to be included in many college textbooks. Nonetheless, some

compilers still consider it novel and untested. Perhaps the most compelling aspect of the

theory is that while it can draw on deep traditionalism across a wide range of cultures,

Braithwaite and his colleagues came to the theory by investigating the modern

pharmaceutical industry. Therefore, reintegrative shaming has attraction both for the

community practitioner – from police officer to family counselor – as well as for

corporate security managers and government regulators in the global marketplace.

The Theory of Reintegrative Shaming

“Reintegrative shaming means that expressions of community disapproval, which may

range from mild rebuke to degradation ceremonies, are followed by gestures of

reintegration into the community of law-abiding citizens.” (Braithwaite 1989: 55) That

statement is dense with meaning.

First, the key concept is “reintegration.” It is easy for a community, whether a

family or a nation-state, to hold an offender up to rebuke. Parents may yell or the FBI

can convince a federal prosecutor to bring an indictment. The salient feature of

Braithwaite’s theory is that the offender must be brought back into the community by

means of some ceremony whether the mere nods of a family or the published finding by a

1 Eastern Michigan University. This paper is presented as a requirement of CRIM 610: Theories of Criminal Behavior, taught by Dr. Gregg Barak, Winter 2009.

Page 4: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 2

court. In most times and places, most middle-range problems will be solved with middle-

range techniques.

Second, the expressions of disapproval must be on terms that the offender

understands and agrees with. The community must be the offender’s own. In cases

where the offender is truly a distant stranger, a process of empathetic understanding may

be required. It is not always successful; and yet the failure points underscore the basic

truth.

Third, the offender’s sense of shame is integral to the offender’s sense of guilt.

The essential characteristic of shame is the offender’s understanding, admitting and

agreeing with the rebuke. Braithwaite acknowledges the ambiguity between shame and

guilt. (Braithwaite 1989: 57). While they are differentiable, they are not always

empirically testable by different means. In other words, developmental psychologists

explain that a personal sense of shame comes from assimilating the perceived expressions

of guilt offered by others. We learn this as children. “You did this bad thing and you

should feel bad inside,” comes the message. Indeed, the empathetic child understands

internally the hurt caused to others and feels shame. This much we all know from self-

experience. However, positivism must accept less fine-grained empirical results. When

an offender uses the words guilt, shame and remorse, the distinctions might only be

analogous to words like blue, teal and green. We do not confuse guilt and shame with

pride and honor just as we do not confuse blue and green with red and orange. Beyond

that, Braithwaite asserts that it is unnecessary to seek statistical quantifications. “The

distinction is rather too fine for our theoretical purposes because ‘guilt-induction’ always

implies shaming to the person(s) inducing the guilt and because, as we will argue later, in

Page 5: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 3

broader societal terms guilt is only made possible by cultural processes of shaming.”

(Braithwaite, 1989: 57) This is supported by empirical evidence. Harris and Maruna

(2006) found that feelings of shame and guilt were not differentiated by participants in a

study of community justice programs.

That the intent of reintegrative shaming is the opposite of the goal of retributive

punishment is clear from the semantics of the terms. Another of Braithwaite’s works

(with co-author Philip Petit) is titled, Not Just Deserts.2 That debate bears directly on the

efficacy of shaming. That the punishment should fit the crime was an element of Cesare

Beccaria’s enlightened theory,3 separating the modern era from the medieval. Whether

that was a discrete invention (like the light bulb) or acknowledgement of a general

opinion (like the Declaration of Independence), is a moot point. Moreover, Max Weber

found the trend toward rational law over traditional in the medieval city4. Rational law

became national law when we became nations of bourgeoisie. It may seem intuitively

obvious that lesser crimes require milder punishments and greater crimes call for harsher

consequences. However, Braithwaite strings out 16 citations pointing to studies by

Cohen, Jensen, Paternoster and others showing “but little support for the association

between crime and the severity of punishment.” (Braithwaite, 1989: 69) On the same

page, Braithwaite does acknowledge “reasonable support for an association between the

certainty of criminal punishment and offending.” In short, the degree of pain is not as

important as the fear of getting caught. More to the point, increasingly painful

retributions do not minimize recidivism.

2 Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Justice by John Braithwaite and Philip Petit, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990.3 An Essay on Crimes and Punishments of Cæsar Bonasana, Marquis of Beccaria, 1764, translated from the French by Edward D. Ingraham, second American edition,Philadelphia, Philip H. Nicklin, 1819.4 The City by Max Weber, translated and edited by Dan Martindale and Gertrud Neuwirth, Collier Books, New York, 1958, pp 183-184 within Chapter 4, “The Plebian City.”

Page 6: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 4

Finally, reintegrating the offender with the community requires reconciling the

offender with the victim. This can be difficult. Teenage vandalism is one thing. Assault,

rape and homicide call into question our fundamental beliefs about the righting of

wrongs. Basic as those beliefs are, they remain cultural constructs. We are not born

knowing what to do when an armed robber stabs out your eye (Zehr, 1990: 19 ff.) .

Intense emotions hallmark every encounter between the victim and the offender. No

formula exists. We have no codex to tell us when enough time – or too much time – has

passed. Yet, until and unless this happens, restoration is incomplete and even unbegun.

For informal justice to be restorative justice, it has to be about restoring victims,

restoring offenders, and restoring communities as a result of participation of a

plurality of stakeholders. This means that victim- offender mediation, healing

circles, family group conferences, restorative probation, reparation boards …

whole school antibullying programs, Chinese Bang Jiao programs, and exit

conferences following Western business regulatory inspections can at times all be

restorative justice. Sets of both optimistic propositions and pessimistic claims can

be made about restorative justice by contemplating the global diversity of its

practice. Examination of both the optimistic and the pessimistic propositions

sheds light on prospects for restorative justice. Regulatory theory (a responsive

regulatory pyramid) may be more useful for preventing crime in a normatively

acceptable way than existing criminal law jurisprudence and explanatory theory.

Evidence-based reform must move toward a more productive checking of

restorative justice by liberal legalism, and vice versa. (Braithwaite 1999: 1)

In what may be more than a minor point of semantics, John Braithwaite (writing with

Valerie Braithwaite and Eliza Ahmed), suggested that “shaming” itself is a problematic

label. “Responsibility” and “healing” are more productive. (Henry and Lanier 2007: 289)

The first barrier is always with the offender. If he remains intransigent, reintegration is

impossible. Calling the process a “healing meeting” rather than a “shaming session”

seems more likely to facilitate the desired outcome.

Page 7: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 5

Stigmatizing shaming clearly cannot reintegrate an offender into the community.

Stigmatizing shaming is just another label that assigns as the “master status” or primary

identity of the person the label of “homosexual” or “thief” or “wife beater.” Every

person is more than such a label. (Braithwaite 1989: 55) On this basis, Braithwaite

cogently seeks to avoid the oppressive shaming known to religious communities (evident

under Islamist sharia law) and the “show trials” of totalitarian dictatorships.

Just as restorative justice is the goal of reintegrative shaming, so, too, does

Braithwaite sets dominion as the goal of restorative justice. Braithwaite defines

dominion as the absence of arbitrary power over the individual. “Our idea is that if the

criminal justice system is designed to promote dominion, then it will also promote values

such as people's physical integrity, freedom of movement, secure property rights,

procedural rights, a suitable concern for equity, and so on.” (Braithwaite 1994: 765-766).

In other words, in a society where dominion is the standard of republican justice, an

offender’s irresponsible act has clear consequences that do not involve dropping him into

a criminal justice system whose sine qua non is arbitrary power.

Acceptance of the Theory

“The momentum of restorative justice in the past 20 years has been breathtaking: from a

few small experiments in the mid-1970s, restorative justice has today become ‘the

flavour of the month’ in many justice circles, and is clearly gaining respectability.” (Mika

and Zehr in McEvoy and Newburn 2003: 135).

A convenience sample of 14 contemporary textbooks for criminology and

criminal justice in the library of Eastern Michigan University (Appendix A) reveals that

all but two of them acknowledge the existence of the theory. Depth of presentation

Page 8: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 6

depends on the theoretical expectations of the authors, including apparent advocacy or

demurrage (if any) on this or other issues. These books include those targeted to 100-

level and 200-level occupational training for police officers as well as upper-level

university textbooks for potential supervisors.

Liqun Cao (2004) considered reintegrative shaming only a reformulation of

labeling theory (140) and wrote that there are “relatively few” tests (183). Lilly, Cullen,

and Ball (2007) acknowledged the many qualitative and quantitative studies behind the

theory, but declared, finally: “Studies that employ surveys to measure reintegrative

shaming and then assess its impact on self-reported delinquency – the methodological

approach most used to test criminological theories – are still in short supply.” (140).

Nevertheless, neither of those actually passed judgment on the theory. That lack of

declaration may be an artifact of our relativistic, subjectivist age of cultural context.

Also, absolute statements run the risk of disproof and therefore stigmatizing shaming.5

On the other hand, Lanier and Henry (1998) take a more integrating view. They also

place reintegrative shaming within the field of labeling theory (1997: 173). However,

they do take a broader view and cite others who join them in seeing this as an integrating

theory that draws on differential association, learning, and control (173), as well as

Milovanovic’s “recovering subject” and place the theory within the field of restorative

justice (178). Whereas Cao, Lilly, et al., leave reintegrative shaming as a subset of

labeling theory, Lanier and Henry also recognize, at least implicitly, that this is a rational

choice theory (173). Their summary view, then, is more inclusive and nuanced.

5 Perhaps the iconic example is that William Thompson, Baron Kelvin, for whom absolute temperature is named, declared heavier-than-air flight impossible in 1895. Kelvin also said that radio had no future. In 1943, Thomas Watson, Sr., of IBM predicted a worldwide need for five computers, and 30 years later Digital Equipment’s Ken Olsen saw no need for anyone to have a computer in their home. Etc., etc.

Page 9: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 7

A sample derived from the JSTOR database of journals is presented in Appendix

B. This list of 49 significant publications indicates that the concept of “reintegrative

shaming” has achieved visibility and general acceptance. Appendix C lists 62 reviews of

the books of John Braithwaite and his colleagues. While constructive criticism and fault

finding (and even veiled ad hominem attacks) are accepted and expected in an objective

review, especially of a new idea, the overwhelming response was (and remains) positive

and accepting.

Braithwaite did have a heated exchange with Ernest van den Haag. That The

Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology would host this debate, and that van den Haag

would deign to engage, underscores the esteem that Braithwaite earned. Despite the titles

of the articles and replies, the significant fact is that both scholars abandoned the concept

of just deserts. For van den Haag the primary purpose of punishment was general

deterrence. Fear of punishment clearly does not deter the present practitioner, but must,

in his view, deter some future criminals. For Braithwaite, the problem was that just

deserts offers only internal contradictions rather than standards of action when attempting

to decide whether and to what extent a corporation or an individual should be punished

for white collar crimes. The debate covered a lot of ground that need not be plowed here.

The salient perspective is that Braithwaite’s views on corporate crime and white

collar crime are in accord with his theory of reintegrative shaming. Rather than seeking

to punish – though that may be an outcome – his goal is to bring the errant company or

harmful individual back into the fold. In The Impact of Publicity on Corporate Offenders

(1983), Fisse and Braithwaite assert that shaming works not on the company per se –

though that can happen vicariously – but primarily on its employees, especially its senior

Page 10: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 8

staff and corporate officers who feel a sense of lost social status when bad publicity

plagues their enterprise. In Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation

Debate (1992) Ayres and Braithwaite argue for a close relationship between regulators

and businesses, so that neither is the adversary of the other. Informal discussions lead to

compliance more often and more cheaply than going to court. While it would be easy to

spark a debate with the Cato Institute, no criminologist or sociologist has come forward

to dispute the main points of those books: businesses are entities within communities.

Therefore, the engagements and modalities that bring individuals together after a divisive

conflict are available for the commercial sector as well.

An insightful and friendly criticism comes from Nathan Harris and Shadd

Maruna, writing in Sullivan and Tifft (2006): “Surprisingly, the original formulation of

the theory (Braithwaite, 1989) includes only a cursory discussion of what the emotion of

shame even is.” Perhaps, like art and obscenity, we all know it when we see it, even if

we cannot define it. Nonetheless, a bit of introspection suggests the nuanced distinctions

between shame, guilt, remorse, sorrow, humility, humbleness, and disgrace. The words

“bashful” and “abashed” literally strike at the distinction Braithwaite makes. Being

“bashful” means being full of bashes – beaten into submission. That is not the goal of

republican justice which assures dominion through reintegration of the offender with the

community. That, too, was offered as a counterpoint by Harris and Maruna who said that

“shame and shaming do not belong in restorative justice work.” It is important to bear in

mind that, like Braithwaite, they reject only the counter-productive label, not the

reintegrative purpose.

Page 11: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 9

Andrew von Hirsch specializes in punishments and penal theory.6 Von Hirsh

objected to the pursuit of justice without “just deserts.” Braithwaite, of course, seeks to

do more than merely visit proportionate pain upon the criminal. More subtly, it might

said that reintegration is, indeed, the most just of consequences. Be that as it may, Von

Hirsch asserted that

… desert theory … is a key concept-that of blaming; it directs policymakers to

judge specifics in terms of whether, and how much, blame is due. … The goal

for white- collar cases would then be to administer proportionate, deserved

punishment to the maximum extent feasible, taking into account problems of

successfully prosecuting such crimes. Thus, priority would be given to

imprisoning those offenders whose crimes were the most reprehensible. The

thalidomide executives, and not some smaller- fry who might make useful

examples to their industry, would become the prime targets for the tougher

sanctions. Would this mean that all such malefactors will receive their full,

merited penalty? In a system having limited resources, of course not. Serious

offenders would, however, be at higher risk of receiving substantial punishment:

it is they who would be more likely than other white-collar criminals to go to

prison and to receive terms approaching (even if not always equalling) those

received by violent street criminals. The more one disregards desert, as Dr.

Braithwaite proposes, the less likely such a state of affairs becomes. … There is

no alchemy by which one can become more “just” through ignoring

considerations of justice. .Braithwaite has, in my judgment, failed to make his

case. (Von Hirsh 1982: 1164-1165; 1174-1175)

Yet, all is not lost. Von Hirsch closes that passage with a bon mot, as how could he not?

A criminologist whose goal is to see the guilty go free would not be a professor, but

would, instead, hang out a shingle as a defense attorney, soliciting the wealthiest and

guiltiest of clients. Apparently not in that camp, Von Hirsch doffs his hat. “[Braithwaite] 6 “Professor of Penal Theory and Penal Law at Cambridge University. He is also the Honorary Fellow at Wolfson College, Cambridge. Andrew von Hirsch has also been Adjunct Professor of Penology in the Law Faculty of the University of Uppsala, Sweden.” Andrew von Hirsch -- From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Andrew_von_Hirsch

Page 12: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 10

has, however, performed an important service by raising the question of desert and white-

collar criminality.” (1175)

If the most egregious of white collar crimes challenges the assumptions of

reintegrative shaming, how then, do we view crimes against humanity? The Holocaust

has a name. The suffering in Bosnia and Rwanda do not. We say that we cannot live

with such evil. Yet, we do. After the Holocaust, the slogan touted was “Never again!”

But genocides played out again and again. Therefore, criminologist Charles Villa-

Vicencio (1999) wrote: “The sheer weight of such evil, that no atonement, compensation

or any other form of human balm can appease, lends credence and understanding to our

ingrained human desire for revenge. … By institutionalizing feelings of anger,

resentment and even hatred, the state exercises procedural controls over individual and

group anarchy. … These arguments on behalf of revenge bring into sharp relief two

seemingly contradictory models for responding to radical evil. … I will argue that

models of restorative and retributive justice, properly conceived, belong together.” (165-

166).

The extent to which community-based restorative justice operated differently than

retributive international law is nowhere more evident than in South Aftica. Nonetheless,

the experience was not easy or unambiguous. In Villa-Vicencio’s opinion: “The response

of President Thabo Mbeki in questioning the appropriateness of individual reparations

recommended by the TRC [Truth and Reconciliation Commission] in its Report has

further complicated the discussion.” Villa-Vicencio’s theory is that “righteous anger” of

the victim can “immediately transform the perpetrator.”(183) Villa-Vicencio is eloquent

in support of righteous anger, but at one point closes his thought on a problematic note.

Page 13: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 11

It affirms the dignity of the victim and sometimes survivors. It requires the

perpetrator to take responsibility as a moral agent. At the same time, it creates

space for the possibility of mercy and forgiveness-recognising that its telos is

restoration, not punishment per se. This movement toward a reconciliation of

retributive and restorative justice engenders three final observations: First, the

angry spirit that justifies the demand for radical repentance, a willingness to pay

back all that has been unfairly acquired and a commitment to live a radically

transformed life, does make good moral sense. Sometimes, however, it takes time

for the perpetrator to be brought to this point-not least in ideologically laden

situations where the most hideous deeds are done in the name of all that is said to

be decent and worth dying for. (185)

Whether anything is “worth dying for” is another discussion entirely. I point out

that in the archaic and ancient world, the Greeks of Samos, Miletus, Agrigentum, and

other towns slipped into their ships and rowed away in the night, rather than to face

overwhelming odds. The Romans stood their ground as the loins of Italy produced sons

by the tens of thousands to die what the Senate apparently found “decent.” Villa-

Vicencio’s point, however, still remains: ideology provides the words that allow the

offenders to remain unshamed. The matter is complicated. As will be shown, the

overwhelming assumption, even in restorative and reintegrative conclaves, is that the

accused is guilty. In most cases, the offender has been so labeled by a court of law. The

theoretical point may be fundamentally unsolvable; and it may be that the initiative for

restoration and reintegration always resides with the accused.

For others the moral high ground is always the property of the accuser.

“Restorative justice seeks to recover dimensions of justice often lost within the

institutional retributive justice process. It does not necessarily reject all punitive

measures associated with retributive justice.” (Villa-Vicencio in “Transitional justice,

Page 14: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 12

restoration, and prosecutition,” in The Handbooks of Restorative Justice: A Global

Perspective by Dennis Sullivan, Larry Tifft, Routledge, 2006.)

Ideas take on a life of their own. Richard Dawkins called them “memes”

analogous to genes in that they find carriers to reproduce their message. Therefore, it is

interesting to read ideas very similar to Braithwaite’s in works that do not cite him in the

bibliography or index. Merry and Milner’s The Possibility of Popular Justice: A Case

Study of Community Mediation in the United States (1993) is replete with examples.

Although each of the contemporary programs addresses the emotional

dimensions of conflict resolution in slightly different ways, all believe the

expression of emotions is appropriate in mediation. In HNJC [Honolulu

Neighborhood Justice Center] the expression of feelings is understood as a

necessary prelude to the main objective – negotiating agreements. Whereas some

expression of emotions is expected and encouraged, exploration of this

dimension is seen as inappropriate for mediation and is labeled as a “counseling

issue.” … The MCS [Mennonite Conciliation Service] training manual is not

very explicit about the role of emotion in the mediation process, but in a recent

issue of their newsletter devoted to “reconciliation,” emotional expression was

related to forgiveness, emotional healing, and restoring relationships. (255)

As will be shown their reference to the Mennonite Conciliation Service is cogent. While

restorative justice has a long and deep tradition across many cultures, that inheritance is

often discontinuous – as is the habit of authoritative retribution. We call harsh laws

“draconian” after Drakon of Athens (c. 500 BCE), the tyrant who made murder a capital

offense. Previously, such disputes were family matters. While Roman law was state

law7, once the Roman Empire receded in the West, Germanic tribal customs became the

norm for centuries and Roman law had to be rediscovered. Similarly, European colonists

7 The Romans knew the difference between private law and civil law. In the sixth century CE, the Code of Justinian recognized private international law, even though commercial law as we understand it was still 500 years in the future.

Page 15: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 13

in the Americas had Native customs in front of their eyes for 250 years before the present

generation discovered the power and utility of community justice and restorative justice.

Once Braithwaite’s theory was publicized, it was easy to find antecedent support.

COPS, the Community Oriented Policing Services program of the U.S.

Department of Justice (www.usdoj.gov/cops/), supports restorative justice programs

(Umbreit and Coates 2000a; Umbreit and Coates 2000b; Nicholl 2000). The program

does acknowledge that it is important to separate the offense from the offender in order

not to separate the perpetrator from those who can help him avoid further trouble. The

offender must be given the opportunity to develop empathy. “Addressing the offender’s

needs and obligations–with support from the community–is likely to enable the offender

to see that he is someone who is connected to people who care about him.” (Nicholl

2000: 13). In all, there are at least 500 such programs in Europe and 300 in the United

States (Umbreit and Coates 2000b, 5).

Development and Integration of the Theory

Braithwaite came to the theory of reintegrative shaming during his study of the

pharmaceutrical industry in Australia and the United States. He said:

Brent Fisse and I had been doing some writing together for years on The Impact

of Adverse Publicity on Corporate Offenders. That’s where the interest in shame

started. In the business regulation work, we could see counterproductive effects

of stigmatizing forms of shaming. But also we could see that the big problem

was that so many business people did not see corporate crime as anything to be

very ashamed about. So for years we puzzled over how might productive forms

of shame be managed and harnessed. So it was very much from thinking about

the corporate crime literature. And then moving to an attempt at more general

theory that encompassed street offenders. (Braithwaite 2009)

Page 16: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 14

That businesses were amenable to reintegrative and restorative processes should not be

surprising. Business at a distance, where valuables are delivered and paid for by agents,

depends on deeply embedded habits of trust and responsibility. (Greif 2006). As Deirdre

McCloskey has shown in her long series of essays (and now a book) on “Bourgeois

Virtues”8 reputational gossip the true currency of commerce. As will be shown, the value

in the forms and formats of restorative justice can be measured to two decimal places in

dollars and cents.

In a sophisticated and literate expression recognizable to us, this goes back at least

to the great fairs of the High Middle Ages, but has roots as deep as the first caravans of

the Neolithic era. When problems arise in commerce, traders seek only restoration, not

retribution; and the offender must find reintegration or else suffer isolation – and trade is

as metaphysically impossible in social isolation as is breathing in a vacuum. In seeking

rebalance through the lawe marchaunt (lex mercator), traders of the Middle Ages were,

in fact, attempting to hang on to traditions.

“Restorative justice has been the dominant model of criminal justice throughout

most of human history for all the world's peoples. A decisive move away from it

came with the Norman Conquest of much of Europe at the end of the Dark Ages

… Transforming crime into a matter of fealty to and felony against the king,

instead of a wrong done to another person, was a central part of the monarch's

program of domination of his people.” (Braithwaite 1999, page 2)

The commercial paradigm indicates that every dollar misspent is two dollars lost. This

lesson from Benjamin Franklin’s Poor Richard is cited in Max Weber’s The Protestant

8 Among many:McCloskey, Donald N. “Bourgeois Virtue” (The American Scholar 63 (2, Spring 1994): 177-191.“Bourgeois Virtues?” by Deirdre McCloskey, May 18, 2006, Cato Institute Online http://www.cato.org/research/articles/cpr28n3-1.htmlMcCloskey, Deirdre N., The bourgeois virtues : ethics for an age of commerce University of Chicago Press, 2006.

Page 17: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 15

Ethic and the Rise of Capitalism. It is more than a trick of bookkeeping: entropy exists.

Therefore, it is not surprising that advocates of restorative justice are able to find

inevitable monetary loss and fundamental injustice in the prison system.

Imprisonment is enormously expensive. This means that a double burden is

placed on the innocent who must suffer the crime and, in addition, pay through

taxation for the support of the offender and his family if they are forced onto

welfare. Also, any benefit of imprisonment is temporary; eventually, most

offenders will be released. If their outlook has not improved-and especially if it

has worsened-the benefits of incarceration are obviously limited. Finally, when

disablement is permanent, as with capital punishment or psychosurgery, it is this

very permanence, in light of the possibility of error, which is frightening.

(Barnett 1977: 281)

Barnett is not alone in cataloging the failure of punishments, either to reform the offender

or to dissuade others, or to restore the victim. (281-283) Yet, restoration in particular and

the process of reintegration in general may be explained as a better form of punishment.

That, at least, is the assertion of philosophy professor Richard K. Dagger in “Restitution,

Punishment, and Debts to Society.”

What Barnett is urging, in short, is a radical departure from the theory of

restitution as well as a radical transformation of our system of criminal justice.

Neither of these moved is warranted. In what follows, I shall argue that

restitution is quite properly regarded as a form of punishment and that criminals

do indeed incur debts to society when they commit their crimes… (Dagger in

Hudson and Galaway 1980: 3)

In that same volume, Sveinn Thorvaldon’s contribution, “Toward the Definition of the

Reparative Aim” (15-27) devotes but a single paragraph to “Reparation as a

Rehabilitative Technique.” Reparation can be viewed as punishment and rehabilitation.

Braithwaite brought both sides of the equation together. The goal of reintegrative

Page 18: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 16

shaming – which can include restitution to whatever extent possible – is to heal the

victim and the offender, specifically and consciously, not accidentally or tangentially.

The historical development of the modern restorative justice regimen bears this out.

Success has many fathers, but the present tradition of bringing restoration to criminal

proceedings is accepted as beginning with Mark Yantzi and Dave Worth of the

Mennonite Central Committee in Kitchener, Ontario. Their subject perpetrator was a

troubled youth named Russell Kelly.

Russell Kelly is now a restorative justice practitioner in Kitchener, Ontario. In

1974 he was a teenager who, with a friend, both under the influence of alcohol,

committed a number of acts of vandalism one night in Elmira, Ontario. After

being apprehended, they were turned over to Mark Yantzi, a probation officer

and volunteer with the Mennonite Central Committee in Kitchener, and to Dave

Worth, another volunteer. Yantzi and Worth, in coordination with the courts,

arranged for the teenagers to meet with their victims to apologize, to hear their

victims’ statements, to ask forgiveness of their victims, and to determine

restitution. Thus arose the Victim-Offender Reconciliation Program in Kitchener

and an oft-repeated story of the emergence of modern day victim-offender

mediation. http://www.restorativejustice.org/

Years after the encounter, Kelly went to work as an industrial laborer. Following an

accident and (physical) rehabilitation, he chose criminal justice as a new career, bringing

with him his highly personalized insight.

Meeting our victims was one of the hardest things I had ever done in my entire

life. Accompanied by Mark Yantzi (our probation officer) and Dave Worth (a

volunteer), we walked up to the victims front door to apologize, hear what the

victims had to say, determine the amount of restitution, ask for forgiveness and

assure the victims that they were not targeted. It was a random act of vandalism.

Some victims offered forgiveness while others wanted to give us a good

whipping. Nonetheless, we survived meeting the victims of our crime spree and

returned a couple of months later with certified cheques to restore the amount of

Page 19: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 17

out-of-pocket expenses not covered by insurance. The total damage was around

$2,200; my accomplice and myself each had to pay $550 restitution and each

paid a $200 fine. As well, we were placed on 18 months probation. I thought that

was the end of that shameful part of my life. Little did I know what would

become of this judicial experiment. Unknowingly to me the Victim Offender

Reconciliation Program was born. (Kelly http://www.sfu.ca/crj/kelly.html)

The involvement of the Mennonite community proved at once to derive from their own

values, as well to deliver a value to the wider world, perhaps the best proof of the

efficacy of faith-based restoration. That tradition is not isolated. It is known across the

globe, among the Eskimos, Cheyenne, Trobriand Islanders, and Ifugao of Luzon.

(Hoebel 1967) Studying the Cheyenne in particular was somewhat easier as they are still

among us. Delving into their experiences by listening to their oral traditions opened the

door to asking the basic questions of criminology: What is law? What is an offense?

It is easy to identify with the instinctive family-based community rules of the

tribe. The man known as Pawnee was an old and respected member of the tribe who

counseled young boys and looked out closely after their moral behavior. He tells his own

story. When he lived among the southern Cheyenne, he was a wild and hurtful youth,

stealing other people’s horses and other people’s meat. If he stole a horse, he would not

even return it, but would just let it loose. The Bowstring Soldiers caught up with him,

beat him senseless, broke his goods and took his horse. They left him where he lay.

When he recovered sufficiently, he started back. After three days, he was in a bad way.

But he was found by High Backed Wolf, later a great chief, but then a young man. High

Backed Wolf broke into tears when he saw Pawnee, the latter’s condition, bruised, naked,

hungry, was so pitiful. High Backed Wolf gave him food, clothes and tobacco, and

restored him. He also called the Bowstring chiefs to witness. Pawnee confessed his

Page 20: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 18

wrongfulness. On the word of High Backed Wolf, Pawnee was accepted back into the

tribe, but his shame was such that he did not remain. He went instead to the Fox Soldiers

of the northern Cheyenne. So, he tells the young boys now to be good, lest they suffer

his fate. “You may run away, but your people will always remember. You just obey the

rules of the camp and you’ll be all right.” (Llewellyn and Hoebel 1941: 6-9)

The story is nice. We find in it the simple, effective restorative and reintegrative

justice that we seek.

We must not gloss over the fact that the Bowstring Soldiers caught up with this

young hooligan, beat him senseless, destroyed the tools he would need for survival and

then left him naked on the plains. In short, the community had its fill, and was content to

be rid of the offender – forever. Period.

It may be helpful to place this story in its anthropological context. The Cheyenne

live with a relatively complex constitutional law. Forty-four appointed chiefs serve for

ten years. Only half of them are replaced at one time. Sons rarely succeed fathers. In

addition, as separate councils, each warrior society9 has its own leaders. Their word

counted for much within the tribal councils because these men bore the brunt of action

not only in war but simply in policing the move of a tribe from one place to another

across great distances. (99-101) Yet, all of this served for a people numbering perhaps

never more than 7,000. Therefore, justice, guidance, rule and responsibility were always

personal and close.10

According to their own legends, this “traditional” arrangement was given to them

by a captive girl from the Assinboine tribe. Anthropologists figure that this dates to 9 Accepted as five in number (Fox Soldiers, Bowstring Soldiers, Elk Soldiers, Dog Men and Northern Crazy Dogs), their names changed over time for reasons not clearly understood by ethnographers.10 The Cheyenne split into many small groups for the autumn, winter and spring, coming together in the summer. The great camp would have a ceremonial open space in the center about a mile across.

Page 21: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 19

about 1750 (68). Therefore, as the case of Pawnee demonstrates, it is important not to

romanticize them simply for being “the other.” These institutions were recent

developments to the Cheyenne, only slightly older than the Federal Constitution of the

Whites when the two groups met.

So, too, does it lie with the ancient Visigoths and Vikings. Among the Visigoths

– who readily adopted and adapted to Roman Christian ways – remediation, restoration

and reparation were woven into the fabric of social life. So were amputation, flogging,

blinding and enslavement. (King 1972: 90-91)

Citing Njal’s Saga, Miller (1984: 114) writes:

Despite the shortcomings of arbitrated settlements, they were perceived by a

substantial segment of the community to be more likely than either self-help or

legal judgments to lead to peace, even if that peace were only temporary. Indeed,

so pervasive was the feeling that cases were better concluded in agreement than

judgment or dismissal that we see litigants refusing to put forward absolute

defenses, using them instead as leverage to induce the other side to enter into

some kind of arbitrated settlement. Njal, again acting on Gunnar's behalf, obtains

a favorable clearing verdict from the panel of neighbors and “he said he would

submit the verdict unless the plaintiffs agreed to put the case to arbitration.”

By “self-help” Miller means vengeance. Whether and to what extent blood feuds were

more or less common than other outcomes may be not quantifiable. Qualitatively, there

is no doubt. Miller (1983) even finds echoes of the Viking blood feud in Shakespeare’s

Hamlet. It might be argued that our highly abstracted legal system is only vengeance in

another form, a social structure to meet same sociologic function. (Tarifa 2008: 99-102)

While reintegrative shaming can be found in a wide range of cultural traditions, so

can other modes of conflict resolution.

Also, it is important to guard against the self-satisfying opinion that these peoples

held a higher moral ground merely because they are not us. Marginalized people create

Page 22: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 20

societies that meet the needs of their physical environment first. Failing that, they do not

survive to have a society. Among the Yup’ik Eskimo of Alaska, community justice was

an import, brought by Americans.11

One of the more promising fields of thought for alternatives to

retributivism, spearheaded by people like John Braithwaite and Howard Zehr,

involves community based systems of justice. … The introduction of village

councils, organized with the support of government and church officials, did

however, grant Yup'iks an outlet for traditional legal practices. Although Eskimo

groups like Yup'iks found it difficult to take individual roles as judges and

bosses, the councils nevertheless espoused non-coercive problem solving.

Council records indicate their function was to remind wrongdoers that although

mitigating circumstances were understood, actions had reached an intolerable

level. The council would oftentimes offer the offender the option to renew his

social contract with his society. The council, for many years, was the dominant

form of Yup'ik social control. On rare occasions, the council had to rely on the

outside world to reinforce its authority. (Ptacin, et al. 2005: 133; 140)

The central problem was that their society previously had no need for the

centralist authority that a court requires. Hoebel (1967) tells of how some Eskimos dealt

with one murderer. Three homicides in your vicinity is bad news for everyone else. So,

the men nearest the events got together on their own and decided that it would be all right

just to shoot the perpetrator in the back at the next opportunity. Less stressful to the

offender is the Navajo court. When two people have a problem, their relatives get

together. Even in modern times, court is “the place where they talk about you.” That

echoes the Yup’ik view that court is “where you are made to speak.” (Hoebel 1967:

passim.)

11 As shown above in the example from the Cheyenne, native cultures overwhelmingly had modes that were recognizable against, cognate to, or congruent with European forms. The human species being what it is, this was required. For more detail see “U.S. Colonization of Indian Justice Systems: A Brief History,” by Carol Chiago Lujan and Gordon Adams in Wicazo Sa Review, Vol. 19, No. 2, Colonization/Decolonization, I (Autumn, 2004), pp. 9-23

Page 23: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 21

Humans are social creatures. It is to be expected that widely separated societies

will develop some similar customs, folkways and institutions to meet similar needs. Not

speaking about oneself is common to many peoples, modern as well as traditional.

Conversely, other people accept and ignore passing and ritualized displays of anger. All

of this can make restorative justice programs difficult, even – or especially – in a modern

industrial urban society where African Americans, Native Americans, Hispanics, Asians

and Causcasians come together. Shaming can be deeply consequential. Japanese parents

are known to have committed suicide when their children’s actions shamed them.

The theory of reintegrative shaming serves the broader goal of restorative justice.

The purpose of shaming is not to punish in the perpetrator by humiliating him – though

some criminal court judges use it that way. Following expressions of contrition and

sorrow (which may include other consequences such as reparations to the victim), the

offender is welcomed back into the community. This, too, works within a broader

context that Braithwaite calls “dominion,” a central concept to his call for “republican

justice.”

[Dominion is not ] the absence of interference- however broadly interference is

understood-which is hailed in classical 19th-century liberal thought; it is not

negative liberty in the established sense of that term… But neither does dominion

involve the presence of self-mastery, the presence of power over self-however

that power is articulated-[as] positive liberty. Dominion is something in between.

… Dominion is negative to the extent that it requires the absence of an evil

perpetrated by others-the absence of an arbitrary power of interference.

Dominion is positive to the extent that it requires not just that others not actually

interfere but that they do not have-and be seen not to have-the arbitrary power of

interfering… One important feature of this comprehensiveness is that the theory

requires us always to think not just about the effects of crime in diminishing the

dominion that people enjoy but also about the effects on people's dominion of

Page 24: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 22

investing authorities like the police, the courts, and the prison officers with high

levels of power. (Braithwaite and Petit 1994: 765-767)

Practical Applications and Critical Dialectics

Like all justice systems, this one operates on the past. It seeks to redress grievances, to

restore losses, to reintegrate offenders. Except as it prevents re-offending and recividism,

it does nothing for the causes of crime (Lin 2007a; Lin 2007b). This is an essential

distinguishing characteristic differentiating modes of power from modes of market.

Governments exist to change the past, at the very least by correcting injustices

and repelling invaders. Even new laws are made in response to a perceived inequity of

some kind that has already occurred at least once. Businesses, on the other hand, survive

and thrive by predicting and planning for the future: tomorrow’s sales; next quarter’s

inventory; next year’s research and development. Moreover, government traditionally

assumes that everyone is equal – even a class-based society accords rights and privileges

on the theory that all member of the same class are interchangeable. Despite the illusion

of “mass marketing” businesses, on the other hand, assume and accept the validity of

subjective values. No court has carved over its doors: “The customer is always right.”

For all of those reasons, as an action of government, any viable theory of criminal

behavior is predictive only on a statistical basis. No sociological theory predicts

individual choices. Accepting this premise, the situation is far from hopeless. It is

certainly better to fix a problem than not. Reintegrative shaming and restorative justice

remain socially powerful modes of community cohesion.

That said, not all progressive or critical theorists are pre-sold. While evidence

does come from a wide range of initiatives across the landscape of cultures and peoples

Page 25: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 23

of our own times and places, from the Eskimo to the Germans, the fact is that in America

today, much of this effort is directed at middle class suburbs and minor offenses in any

community.

Restorative justice is based on values that promote repairing harm, healing, and

rebuilding relations among victims, the offenders, and the communities.

Community justice views crime as a social problem that affects life in

communities and suggests that prevention is an essential part of all criminal

justice agencies' work. … Without a systemwide shift, restorative programs will

probably continue to handle mostly minor offenses. … Experience with

community policing has shown that benefits tend to go to white and middle-class

communities. Community policing in Houston favored the interests of whites and

homeowners, while African Americans, Hispanics, and renters were excluded. …

In Chicago, neighborhood groups that represented white and middle- class

constituencies were much more likely to use opportunities for involvement than

groups representing lower-class minorities ... ((Kurki 2000: 235; 288-290)

Just as reintegration and restoration have been perceived as barriers against, rather

than paths to, justice in human rights tribunals, so, too, do they seem wan to some

advocates for the victims of sexual violence and racial violence. Given that we have a

harshly penalized society, “to forego penalization in a punitive society would look like

tolerance of intolerable behaviour.” (Hudson 1998: 254)

Whilst it is correct to argue that racial and sexual violence will only be

diminished by reducing the economic, racial, and sexual inequalities in power

that exist in present societies, we cannot ask women, children, and victims of

racial violence and abuse to wait for protection and compensation until the

achievement of wholesale social transformation. We cannot, furthermore,

reasonably expect them to give up such protection, remedy, and condemnation of

violence as is afforded by criminal law, in present society with its systems of

criminal rather than restorative justice. (254)

Page 26: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 24

As Lisa Rieger points out in “Applying Urban Models to Rural Alaska” in McEvoy and

Newburn (2003), the only way to know whether and to what extent these outcomes have

validity in a positivist sense is to create control groups and experimental groups. The

experimental groups would get the best-known treatment and the controls would get “just

deserts” or whatever it is that the courts mete out. Clearly, this creates ethical dilemmas.

It is one thing to pay people $10 to take a placebo that might not curb their appetite. It is

quite another to randomly select one person for perdition and another for salvation.

Widely applicable and widely founded as Braithwaites’s theory may be, the fact

remains that he and his colleagues came to it by considering government regulation of

complex corporations. If the advantages of reintegrative shaming and restorative justice

are clear in the case of the juvenile delinquent, do they make sense for a multinational

corporation? Indications are that they do. Independent of Braithwaite’s own arguments,

indications of clear economic incentives exist. It is far cheaper to set out ahead of

problems, to engage forums for settling disputes without going to court. In particular,

Shavell (1995) offers the (hypothetical) case of a neighborhood concerned that the

increased traffic from a factory will increase traffic accidents. The model has several

problems. How wide is the community? How responsible is the plant for the actions of

its visitors? Nonetheless, Shavell argues on strictly economic terms – via arithmetic and

algebra – that the monetary advantage for the corporation is to be found in establishing

procedures for alternative dispute resolution ahead of any problem, rather than going to

court later, as the outcomes of trials are uncertain and not predicted by prior arbitration.

(Shavell 1995: 1-28)

Page 27: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 25

Rosenberg and Folberg (1994) found strong statistical evidence of satisfaction

among attorneys and their clients with “early neutral evaluator” (ENE) alternative dispute

resolution in federal courts for the Northern District of California.

During the 4-year period studied, the district used an ADR process called early

neutral evaluation (ENE), to which half of the cases in certain types of suits were

assigned. Two- thirds of those assigned to ENE were satisfied with the process

and believed it was worth the resources devoted to it; half of those assigned to

ENE saved money, with average savings exceeding ten times the cost of an ENE

session… (1487)

[The] vast majority of all participants (90 percent of attorneys and 80

percent of parties) reported that the evaluator listened carefully to them. This

willing- ness to listen bore a strong relationship to attorney satisfaction (r=.44,

p=.01). Fortunately, nearly all of those who thought the evaluator listened

carefully also thought she understood their perspectives, such that 80 percent of

the attorneys and 73 percent of the parties reported that the evaluator understood

their perspectives. Not surprisingly, the correlation between attorneys'

impressions that the evaluator understood their perspectives and their satisfaction

with the process was also relatively high (r=.47, p=.01). Another important

attribute for an evaluator is her ability to facilitate communication between the

sides (75 percent of the attorneys and 78 percent of the parties found this skill

important). The evaluator's ability to facilitate bore a stronger relationship to

attorney satisfaction than did any other measurable factor (r=.55, p=.01).97 Even

evaluators who sought primarily to ensure a shared understanding of the parties'

perspectives also often offered their opinions on both the substance of the case

and procedure, and most ENE participants believed that the evaluator's judgment

was reliable. Eighty percent of the attorneys and 79 percent of the parties said the

evaluator accurately analyzed the legal issues, and this skill was an important

factor in ensuring attorney satisfaction (r=.55, p=.01). In addition, 71 percent of

the attorneys and 77 percent of the parties believed the evaluator was an expert in

the subject matter of their case, and this perceived expertise also corresponded to

attorney satisfaction (r=.41, p=.01). Although the judges and the ENE program.

(1532)

Page 28: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 26

It is radically important to understand that nothing about that necessarily involved

“reintegrative shaming.” As Hudson’s criticism underscores, these litigants were

relatively privileged. They were engaged in property squabbles far less consequential

than domestic battering and marital rape or even burglary. Furthermore, their feelings of

“satisfaction” are easy to explain via Festinger’s theory cognitive dissonance. Perhaps all

that can be said is that we know to two decimal places that almost anything is preferable

to going to court – even for those who nominally own the courts.

A more optimistic appraisal comes from considering alternative dispute

resolution, including restorative justice programs, to be a voluntary engagement. As

such, it validates Braithwaite’s expectations for “republican justice” that grants

“dominion” to all parties rather than leaving them as isolated objects in the mechanized

production of legalistic routines.

In a 27-page monograph that can do little more than describe the tip of the

iceberg, Umbreit and Coates (2000) caution the mediator on the “pitfalls and dangers”

working with individuals from diverse cultural groups. African-Americans, Asians,

Native Americans, … The gross descriptions do not even differentiate the suburbanite

from the city-dweller. In a society that is accustomed to mechanisms, the highly

personalized atmosphere of reintegration and restoration can only be admittedly

unpredictable. As Olson (2004) argues, the need for professionals is real and important.

Restorative justice theory largely ignores the role of professionals in the criminal

justice process, and yet professionals have played a dominant part in initiating

many restorative justice programs. Several theoretical traditions recognize

professionals as being important intermediaries between citizens and the state.

The theory of democratic professionalism argues that professionals can play

crucial roles in increasing. (Olson 2004:139)

Page 29: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 27

A restorative justice “true believer” may agree that such involvement is

needed at the outset of restorative justice programs, but once that stage has

passed, the community will take back what is deservedly theirs. We see it

differently. Generating sufficient citizen involvement in most communities is

something that may involve considerable long-term social change to accomplish,

even with the concerted efforts of democratic professionals. At a time when it is

hard for even the most devoted local party activist to get 50% of a neighborhood

to turn out to vote in a presidential election year-even given a stable party

system, with established political networks at the national, state, and local levels-

we wonder whether "giving back" the criminal justice system is as easy as it

sounds. Another questionable assumption is that all the tasks to be done can be

done by volunteers. Even beyond a possible transition stage to restorative justice,

we see evidence that restorative justice programs usher in new tasks and new

burdens for some particular group to master. Because tasks such as mediation

and facilitation of community involvement are different but no less complex and

burdensome than traditional criminal justice tasks, it seems sociologically sound

to suppose that some professional involvement will likely be a long-term and not

temporary phenomenon. The role of facilitator also includes finding political

support for community involvement in hitherto professionally dominated

institutions. (170)

As noted, the case of South Africa is a paradigmatic challenge to notions of restoration

and reintegration. “The danger is that gestures toward healing will be confused with

moral consensus, or that history will be told mainly in a way that reflects and legitimates

political compromises.” (Leebaw 2003: 51) South Africa is not alone. Admission of

guilt is more than an essential component of reintegrative shaming. One can be said to be

identical to the other. This can be impossible in a context where the perpetrator has

strong beliefs. The case of Israel and Palestine is an easy example. This brings us back

to the highly personalized reintegrative shaming and restorative justice meetings of

families and neighbors. These sessions assume that the offender has accepted the status

given to him.

Page 30: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 28

As cited above, Harris and Maruna (2006) accept the premise of restorative

justice, but question its mode of application. The distinctions between grossly

humiliating shaming – wearing a sign, for example – and reintgrative shaming in a family

structure may be clear to us. They may be lost on the offender.

Forcing offenders to publicly humiliate themselves by means such as holding

placards which announce their crimes is directly opposite to what RST

[Reintegrative Shaming Theory] advocates. While completely rejecting the use of

this type of shaming, RST suggests that disapproval which is reintegrative is

constructive in reducing re-offending.

While it is easy to see the difference between these overtly stigmatizing

forms of shaming and what Braithwaite proposes … direct expressions of

disapproval are not a common feature of family group conferences, which focus

more clearly on emphasizing the consequences that an offence had on its victims.

[E]ven if direct disapproval is intended to reintegrate it may not be interpreted as

such by the offender. The degree to which disapproval can be expressed directly

and yet also be perceived as reintegrative (or nonstigmatizing) is an empirical

question that is yet to be fully explored. … Braithwaite argues that shaming

includes all social processes which express disapproval. Simply convening a

family group conference expresses the communities concern or disapproval of an

offence, as does discussion of the consequences of an offence. Indeed

Braithwaite and Braithwaite (2002, 33) argue that it is these indirect forms of

shaming that are most likely to be reintegrative. … Braithwaite and Braithwaite

(2001) acknowledge that additional shaming in contexts that are already highly

shaming is unnecessary and may even be interpreted as stigmatizing.

http://demgov.anu.edu.au/papers/HarrisMaruna2006rjhandbook.pdf

On that broad reservation, it is important to note that Braithwaite himself (1989: 60) cites

the instances of pubs in Queensland forced to display signs that they were guilty of

selling watered beer. How that is not stigmatizing, especially as such businesses are

family-owned and neighborhood-based, is hard to understand.

Page 31: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 29

“Reintegration into what?” ask Sullivan and Tifft (2001: 85-87) “Dave: a Case

Study” tells of a boy who is reintegrated into “physically and structurally violent

circumstances.” Dave says, “Nothing’s going to change when I go home except me.”

Sullivan and Tifft ask: “Can we expect a meeting of perhaps an hour’s duration to

counteract or neutralize in any long-lasting way the harmful structural conditions and

moral values that young people have been exposed to, perhaps since birth?” (88)

The nicest thing about the ivory tower of academe is that you can stay far away

from the hurt and pain even while you study it. This paper has not bathed in the sorrow

of loss. We call them “perpetrators” and “offenders.” Even if you call them rapists or

killers, no word is strong enough. We refer to “victims.” Legalism and criminalistics

have no specific words for the robbed, the raped, the beaten … cheated, deprived, looted,

denied, stripped.

Howard Zehr is Professor of Restorative Justice and Co-Director of the Center for

Justice and Peacebuilding, Eastern Mennonite University, Harrisonburg, Virginia. He is

also a photographer. Transcending: Reflections of Crime Victims provides verbal and

visual images of loss. You can read the book, and see their faces, and experience some

fraction of their actual loss. But you can never get inside and you can never take it away.

Zehr offers these cases of people who found at least partial (sometimes nearly complete; I

will claim never truly complete) peace and restoration, in many cases through religion.

Some did not. One cold case (Mary Baratta-Lorton) remains open, the putative killer, her

husband, still profiting from their join work and her four life insurance policies. In some

cases, the perpetrators, the killers, the rapists express the deep sorrow that was born in

their own victimization. In other cases, that is not true: no remorse … no perpetrator…

Page 32: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 30

What we want from justice is a mechanistic response, like starting a car, every time. And

if the car does not start, you replace the coil or the battery or the car. Often, that does not

happen. These cases were selected by the author. Other criteria could have produced a

book of unsolved crimes, senseless acts of random violence. It might not make much

difference. As it is impossible to undo the past, every harm remains a harm. Forever.

David R. Karp and Todd R. Clear (2002) find happier outcomes in six community

justice programs serving Ventura County, Maricopa County, Bend, Oregon, Tallahassee,

Boston, and the state of Vermont. The cases sited involve reparable harms to property

and surprisingly little attention is given to the victims. Central to their thesis is the

position of “the community” as one of three “parties” to a mediation, along with the

victim and the offender. One of the Vermont cases involved a simple DWI. After being

stopped, and during the initial interview, the offender let his car roll into a utility pole.

The authors make no mention of reparation to the power company, though the offender

pays reparation to “the community.” Basically, it is just another kind of fine, court costs

to cover the expense of holding court.

Braithwaite points out that often when the government becomes involved in

restorative justice, the outcome is different than that intended by the theorists. “The

suspending of the two- year custodial sentence was quashed in favor of a sentence of four

years and a $5,000 compensation order (which had already been lodged with the court);

the community service and payment of the remaining compensation were also quashed.

The victim got neither his act of grace nor the money for the cosmetic surgery.”

(Braithwaite 1999: 88) If nothing else, authoritative shaming is less effective than

community shaming (Braithwaite 1989: 84 and 96).

Page 33: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 31

Braitwaite acknowledges early on (1989: 12) that done wrongly, shaming can lead

to thought-control. Yet, Ayres and Braithwaite (1992: 158-162) propose private

guardians to monitor businesses. Obviously, the cost of government regulation is high.

You can’t have a cop on every corner and when it comes to complex corporations, the

problem assumes manifold complexity. As private “watchdog” groups exist, Ayres and

Braithwaite suggest empowering them to monitor businesses. The problem with that is

known from the McCarthy Era. Red Channels, published by American Business

Consultants and Counterattack published by Aware, Inc. were blacklisting newsletters

answerable to no one. The American Security Council12 and the Church League of

America, both from Chicago, began as information clearinghouses for the security

departments of businesses seeking to avoid unionization by their employees. The open

exchange of information for whatever motive is one price of an open society. However,

when such groups receive a mandate from the state without a concomitant constitutional

responsibility, the very dangers that Braithwaite fears become very real.

The underlying problem is that communitarian apologies slide past the limitations

of the common mind. In the Muslim Middle East women are flogged for talking to

strangers – and for being raped. Homosexuals are hanged in Iran. In China, the People’s

Courts of the Cultural Revolution ultimately served no objective purpose whatsoever as

the Culture Revolution spun out of control and consumed itself, leaving behind the shards

of person, personhood and personal life.

Is government regulation always to be accepted as the social standard? How do

we not see the government as the violator? What is the distinction between government

12 Now known as the American Security Council Foundation. http://www.ascfusa.org/

Page 34: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 32

regulation and a shakedown? Who sets the community standards? And who defines the

community? Braithwaite has company when he thinks that it is wrong for businesses to

resist regulation. Here in America, many others are in good company for resisting

government intrusion. The theory of reintegrative shaming and restorative justice

assumes that those questions have been answered – and that their own answer is the

correct one.

Braithwaite’s theory of reintegrative shaming is powerful. The vagaries of social

history being as they may, the fact remains that for many peoples – including ourselves –

this was the way that offenders were handled, certainly at best.

That still leaves the rambling litany of rhetorical questions in the paragraph

above. In The Impact of Publicity on Corporate Offenders Fisse and Braithwaite offer a

chapter on “Antitrust at IBM.” IBM’s competitors complained to the Federal Trade

Commission and the Justice Department that the giant was engaged in predatory pricing

and other unfair tactics. I can personally attest that this was common knowledge. I

learned to program computers in 1976 and 1977 on IBM 360 and 370 mainframes. I also

gained experience on the first Hewlett Packard 8-bit desktop computers. At this time, the

computer industry was called “IBM and the Seven Dwarves.” All of that was about to

change. Tracy Kidder’s book, The Soul of a New Machine tells of how Data General

created the first 32-bit supermini computer to compete against IBM’s mainframes. When

the anti-trust agitations began, Data General did not even exist. DG’s real competitor

was never IBM, but DEC: the Digital Equipment Corporation of Ken Olsen from which

DG chief Edson de Castro had come to found his own company. Meanwhile, a little mail

order electronics firm in Albuquerque, MITS, was selling kits to build a home computer,

Page 35: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 33

the Altair. Steven Levy’s Hackers: Heroes of the Computer Revolution provides many of

the details for that side of the story. Two decades after IBM fended off anti-trust charges,

Microsoft survived similar attempts. In both cases, innovation made the matter moot.

Reintegrative shaming and restorative justice are means for redressing wrongs.

Wrongs are the result of violated rights. A right is something for which you do not need

to ask permission. Those are axiomatic. As we move farther from them, we need to

exercise greater care and restraint, lest hubris bring unintended consequences.

Page 36: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 34

Appendix A: Convenience Sample of College Textbooks

This list was compiled by taking in alphabetical order by author the general survey

textbooks suitable for an introductory class in criminology, published after 1990.

The purpose was to establish the extent to which John Braithwaite’s theory of

reintegrative shaming has been incorporated into the body of knowledge that the average

college-eductated police patrol officer (public or private) would be expected to know.

The process began with an examination of the index for the keyword “reintegrative

shaming.” Failing that, “shaming” was sought, then “Braithwaite” in both the general

index and name index. Producing the Index is not necessarily the job of the author.

Those who do this work may not know the subject matter from the viewpoint of a

practitioner.

Outcomes: RS= “Reintegrative Shaming” listed in the Index.Author Publisher Edition/Year Outcome

1 Beirne, Piers.Messerschmidt, James

Boulder, Colo. Westview Press

3rd ed. 2000 RS

2 Brown, Stephen EugeneEsbensen, Finn-Aage. Geis, Gilbert.

Cincinnati, OH Anderson Pub. Co

1st. 1998 No listings.No mention.

3 Conklin, John E. Boston, MA : Allyn and Bacon .

8th ed. 2004 RS

4 DeKeseredy, Walter S., Schwartz, Martin D.

Belmont, Calif. : Wadsworth Pub.,

1st 1996 “Shaming” in index. Proper discussion in text.

5 Ellis, LeeWalsh, Anthony

Boston : Allyn and Bacon,

1st 2000 RS

6 Hirschi, Travis.Laub, John H.

New Brunswick, U.S.A. : Transaction Publishers,

1st 2003 No listings in topic index. No discussions.Braithwaite listed in Bibliography

Page 37: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 35

7 Maguire, Brendan, Radosh, Polly F.

Belmont, CA : West/Wadsworth

Instructor's ed. 1999

RS

8 Reid, Sue Titus. Madison, WI Brown & Benchmark

8th ed. 1997 Braithwaite mentioned under Labeling Theory. Braithwaite cited in six end of chapter notes. No listings

9 Schmalleger, Frank. Upper Saddle River, N.J. : Prentice Hall

2nd ed 1999. RS

10 Shelley, Louise I. Carbondale : Southern Illinois University Press

1st 1981 Braithwaite listed in Index, but not key concepts.

11 Siegel, Larry J.(“The Core”)

Australia ; Belmont, CA : Wadsworth/Thomson Learning,

1st 2002 RS

12 Siegel, Larry J.(“Theories, Patterns, and Types”)

Australia ; Belmont, CA : Wadsworth/Thomson Learning,

7th 2001 RS

13 Siegel, Larry J. Australia ; Belmont, CA : Wadsworth/Thomson Learning,

7th 2000 RS

14 Williams, Katherine S. Oxford ; New York : Oxford University Press

5th ed. No index listings for key words. 12 citations to Braithwaite in the Name Index

Page 38: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 36

Appendix B: Search of Academic Journal Articles

Full articles – not reviews or letters, but including exchanges Full text citations of the full phrase “Reintegrative shaming” but not “restorative

justice” (a related but different term not specifically identified with John Braithwaite; unless appearing with the previous)

Eliminating John Braithwaite and his primary co-researchers, Valerie Braithwaite, Eliza Ahmed , Ian Ayres, Brent Fisse, and Philip Petit.

In journals of Economics, Finance, Health Policy, Law, Political Science and Sociology

Sorted by date (Oldest to Newest)

1. Shame, Culture, and American Criminal Law Shame, Culture, and American Criminal Law Toni M. Massaro Michigan Law Review, Vol. 89, No. 7 (Jun., 1991), pp. 1880-1944

2. Legal Cultures and Punishment Repertoires in Japan, Russia, and the United States, Joseph Sanders, V. Lee Hamilton Law & Society Review, Vol. 26, No. 1 (1992), pp. 117-138

3. The Benevolent Paternalism of Japanese Criminal Justice, Daniel H. Foote California Law Review, Vol. 80, No. 2 (Mar., 1992), pp. 317-390

4. Criminality, Social Control, and the Early Modern State: Evidence and Interpretations in Scandinavian Historiography, Eva Österberg Social Science History, Vol. 16, No. 1 (Spring, 1992), pp. 67-98

5. Beyond Calvin and Hobbes: Rationality and Exchange in a Theory of Moralizing Shaming: [Rejoinder] Christopher Uggen Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 18, No. 3 (Summer, 1993), pp. 513-516

6. Sexual Violence, Victim Advocacy, and Republican Criminology: Washington State's Community Protection Act, Stuart A. Scheingold, Toska Olson, Jana Pershing Law & Society Review, Vol. 28, No. 4 (1994), pp. 729-763

7. Urban Poverty and the Family Context of Delinquency: A New Look at Structure and Process in a Classic Study, Robert J. Sampson, John H. Laub Child Development, Vol. 65, No. 2, Children and Poverty (Apr., 1994), pp. 523-540

8. The Labeling Perspective Is Far from Abandoned in Modern Criminology: Comment on Wright, Hugh D. Barlow Teaching Sociology, Vol. 23, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 55-57

9. State Crimes of Previous Regimes: Knowledge, Accountability, and the Policing of the Past, Stanley Cohen Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Winter, 1995), pp. 7-50

10. One Story, Two Readings: A Response to Harold Tanner: [Response], Michael Dutton Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Winter, 1995), pp. 305-316

11. The Empirical Limitation of Theoretical Insight: [Rejoinder], Harold Tanner Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Winter, 1995), pp. 317-324

12. Interdependence and Reintegrative Social Control: Labeling and Reforming "Inappropriate" Parents in Neonatal Intensive Care Units, Carol A. Heimer, Lisa

Page 39: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 37

R. Staffen American Sociological Review, Vol. 60, No. 5 (Oct., 1995), pp. 635-654

13. Penal Communications: Recent Work in the Philosophy of Punishment, R. A. Duff Crime and Justice, Vol. 20, (1996), pp. 1-97

14. Theoretical Integration in Criminology, Thomas J. Bernard, Jeffrey B. Snipes Crime and Justice, Vol. 20, (1996), pp. 301-348

15. What Do Alternative Sanctions Mean? Dan M. Kahan The University of Chicago Law Review, Vol. 63, No. 2 (Spring, 1996), pp. 591-653

16. Risk Preferences and Patriarchy: Extending Power-Control Theory, Harold G. Grasmick, John Hagan, Brenda Sims Blackwell, Bruce J. Arneklev Social Forces, Vol. 75, No. 1 (Sep., 1996), pp. 177-199

17. Labeling Mental Illness: The Effects of Received Services and Perceived Stigma on Life Satisfaction, Sarah Rosenfield American Sociological Review, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Aug., 1997), pp. 660-672

18. Developments in the Law: Alternatives to Incarceration, Harvard Law Review, Vol. 111, No. 7 (May, 1998), pp. 1863-1990

19. Restorative Justice: The Challenge of Sexual and Racial Violence, Barbara Hudson Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 25, No. 2 (Jun., 1998), pp. 237-256

20. Rush to Closure: Lessons of the Tadić Judgment, Jose E. Alvarez Michigan Law Review, Vol. 96, No. 7 (Jun., 1998), pp. 2031-2112

21. Can Shaming Punishments Educate? Stephen P. Garvey The University of Chicago Law Review, Vol. 65, No. 3 (Summer, 1998), pp. 733-794

22. Informal Social Control and Crime Management in Belfast, John D. Brewer, Bill Lockhart, Paula Rodgers The British Journal of Sociology, Vol. 49, No. 4 (Dec., 1998), pp. 570-585

23. Collateral Consequences of Imprisonment for Children, Communities, and Prisoners, John Hagan, Ronit Dinovitzer Crime and Justice, Vol. 26, Prisons (1999), pp. 121-162

24. Institutions for Restorative Justice: The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Jennifer J. Llewellyn, Robert Howse The University of Toronto Law Journal, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer, 1999), pp. 355-388

25. Volunteerism and Arrest in the Transition to Adulthood, Christopher Uggen, Jennifer Janikula Social Forces, Vol. 78, No. 1 (Sep., 1999), pp. 331-362

26. Employee Discharge and Reinstatement: Moral Hazards and the Mixed Consequences of Last Chance Agreements, Peter A. Bamberger, Linda H. Donahue Industrial and Labor Relations Review, Vol. 53, No. 1 (Oct., 1999), pp. 3-20

27. Public Opinion about Punishment and Corrections, Francis T. Cullen, Bonnie S. Fisher, Brandon K. Applegate Crime and Justice, Vol. 27, (2000), pp. 1-79

28. Juvenile Offenders in the Adult Criminal Justice System, Donna M. Bishop Crime and Justice, Vol. 27, (2000), pp. 81-167

29. Restorative and Community Justice in the United States, Leena Kurki Crime and Justice, Vol. 27, (2000), pp. 235-303

30. Organizational Approaches to Shame: Avowal, Management, and Contestationm Daniel D. Martin The Sociological Quarterly, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Winter, 2000), pp. 125-150

Page 40: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 38

31. The Conditional Effect of Peer Groups on the Relationship between Parental Labeling and Youth Delinquency, Xiaoru Liu Sociological Perspectives, Vol. 43, No. 3 (Autumn, 2000), pp. 499-514

32. Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms Robert Cooter Virginia Law Review, Vol. 86, No. 8, Symposium: The Legal Construction of Norms (Nov., 2000), pp. 1577-1601

33. Does the Diplomacy of Shame Promote Human Rights in China? Alan M. Wachman Third World Quarterly, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Apr., 2001), pp. 257-281

34. Shaming in Corporate Law David A. Skeel, Jr. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 149, No. 6 (Jun., 2001), pp. 1811-1868

35. States Monitoring States: The United States, Australia, and China's Human Rights, 1990-2001 Ann Kent Human Rights Quarterly, Vol. 23, No. 3 (Aug., 2001), pp. 583-624

36. Reducing School Violence: Strengthening Student Programs and Addressing the Role of School Organizations R. Matthew Gladden Review of Research in Education, Vol. 26, (2002), pp. 263-299

37. Community Prosecutors Anthony V. Alfieri California Law Review, Vol. 90, No. 5 (Oct., 2002), pp. 1465-1511

38. Shame, Stigma, and Crime: Evaluating the Efficacy of Shaming Sanctions in Criminal Law Harvard Law Review, Vol. 116, No. 7 (May, 2003), pp. 2186-2207

39. The Role of Procedural Justice and Legitimacy in Shaping Public Support for Policing Jason Sunshine, Tom R. Tyler Law & Society Review, Vol. 37, No. 3 (Sep., 2003), pp. 513-548

40. Confessions and Criminal Case Disposition in China Hong Lu, Terance D. Miethe Law & Society Review, Vol. 37, No. 3 (Sep., 2003), pp. 549-578

41. Double Jeopardy: The Modern Dilemma for Juvenile Justice Christina L. Anderson University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 152, No. 3 (Jan., 2004), pp. 1181-1219

42. Revisiting Informal Justice: Restorative Justice and Democratic Professionalism Susan M. Olson, Albert W. Dzur Law & Society Review, Vol. 38, No. 1 (Mar., 2004), pp. 139-176

43. Enhancing Police Legitimacy Tom R. Tyler Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 593, To Better Serve and Protect: Improving Police Practices (May, 2004), pp. 84-99

44. Integrating Remorse and Apology into Criminal Procedure Stephanos Bibas, Richard A. Bierschbach The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 114, No. 1 (Oct., 2004), pp. 85-148

45. Criminal Law. Federal Sentencing Guidelines. Ninth Circuit Holds That Shaming Punishment Does Not Violate the Sentencing Reform Act. United States v. Gementera, 379 F.3d 596 (9th Cir. 2004) Harvard Law Review, Vol. 118, No. 2 (Dec., 2004), pp. 825-832

46. The Bethel Therapeutic Court: A Study of How Therapeutic Courts Align with Yup'ik and Community Based Notions of Justice John M. Ptacin, Jeremy Worley, Keith Richotte American Indian Law Review , Vol. 30, No. 1 (2005/2006), pp. 133-150

Page 41: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 39

47. Applying the Death Penalty to Crimes of Genocide Jens David Ohlin The American Journal of International Law, Vol. 99, No. 4 (Oct., 2005), pp. 747-777

48. The Banality of Good: Aligning Incentives against Mass Atrocity Mark Osiel Columbia Law Review, Vol. 105, No. 6 (Oct., 2005), pp. 1751-1862

49. Structural Influences on Activism and Crime: Identifying the Social Structure of Discontent Rory McVeigh The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 112, No. 2 (Sep., 2006), pp. 510-566

Page 42: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 40

Appendix C: Reviews of Books by John Braithwaite

1. Review: Playing the Opposites Game: On Mirjan Damaška's "The Faces of Justice and State Authority" Review: Playing the Opposites Game: On Mirjan Damaška's "The Faces of Justice and State Authority" Inga Markovits Reviewed work(s): The Faces of Justice and State Authority: A Comparative Approach to the Legal Process by Mirjan R. Damaška Stanford Law Review, Vol. 41, No. 5 (May, 1989), pp. 1313-1341

2. Review: [untitled] Joel Best Reviewed work(s): Crime, Shame and Reintegration. by John Braithwaite Social Forces, Vol. 69, No. 1 (Sep., 1990), pp. 318-319

3. Review: Reintegrative Shaming: A New General Theory of Crime? Review: Reintegrative Shaming: A New General Theory of Crime? Ronald L. Akers Reviewed work(s): Crime, Shame, and Reintegration. by John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 19, No. 5 (Sep., 1990), pp. 722-723

4. Review: A New Durkheim Review: A New Durkheim Thomas J. Scheff Reviewed work(s): Crime, Shame, and Reintegration. by John Braithwaite The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 96, No. 3 (Nov., 1990), pp. 741-746

5. Review: [untitled] Wojciech Sadurski Reviewed work(s): Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice by John Braithwaite; Philip Pettit Law and Philosophy, Vol. 10, No. 2 (May, 1991), pp. 221-234

6. Review: [untitled] Robert J. Bursik, Jr. Reviewed work(s): Advances in Criminological Theory: Vol. 2. by William S. Laufer; Freda Adler Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 20, No. 4 (Jul., 1991), pp. 594-596

7. Review: Not Not Just Deserts: A Response to Braithwaite and Pettit Review: Not Not Just Deserts: A Response to Braithwaite and Pettit Andrew Von Hirsch, Andrew Ashworth Reviewed work(s): Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice by John Braithwaite; Phillip Pettit Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 12, No. 1 (Spring, 1992), pp. 83-98

8. Review: [untitled] Suzanne Retzinger Reviewed work(s): Mea Culpa: A Sociology of Apology and Reconciliation. by Nicholas Tavuchis The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 97, No. 6 (May, 1992), pp. 1754-1756

9. Review: White Collar Crime and the Poverty of the Criminal Law Review: White Collar Crime and the Poverty of the Criminal Law Kenneth Mann Reviewed work(s): Regulating Fraud: White-Collar Crime and the Criminal Process by Michael Levi Just Deserts for Corporate Criminals by Kip Schlegel Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 17, No. 3 (Summer, 1992), pp. 561-571

10. Review: The Yale White-Collar Crime Project: A Review and Critique Review: The Yale White-Collar Crime Project: A Review and Critique David T. Johnson, Richard A. Leo Reviewed work(s): Wayward Capitalists: Target of the Securities and Exchange Commission by Susan Shapiro Defending White-Collar Crime: A Portrait of Attorneys at Work by Kenneth Mann Sitting in Judgment: The Sentencing of White-Collar Criminals by Stanton Wheeler; Kenneth Mann; Austin Sarat Crimes of the Middle Classes: White-Collar Offenders in the Federal Courts by David Weisburd; Stanton Wheeler; Elin Waring; Nancy Bode Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 18, No. 1 (Winter, 1993), pp. 63-99

Page 43: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 41

11. Review: Crime and the Average American Review: Crime and the Average American John Braithwaite Reviewed work(s): Crimes of the Middle Classes: White-Collar Offenders in the Federal Courts by David Weisburd; Stanton Wheeler; Elin Waring; Nancy Bode Law & Society Review, Vol. 27, No. 1 (1993), pp. 215-231

12. Review: [untitled] Anne M. Khademian Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate. by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 98, No. 5 (Mar., 1993), pp. 1187-1189

13. Review: [untitled] Joel Rogers Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate. by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 22, No. 3 (May, 1993), pp. 338-339

14. Review: The Bureaucrats of Rules and Standards Review: The Bureaucrats of Rules and Standards Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite Harvard Law Review, Vol. 106, No. 7 (May, 1993), pp. 1685-1690

15. Review: Reintegrating Braithwaite: Shame and Consensus in Criminological Theory Review: Reintegrating Braithwaite: Shame and Consensus in Criminological Theory Christopher Uggen Reviewed work(s): Crime, Shame and Reintegration by John Braithwaite Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 18, No. 3 (Summer, 1993), pp. 481-499

16. Review: [untitled] Frank Gallo Reviewed work(s): Self Employment: A Labor Market Perspective by Robert L. Aronson The Japanese Labor Market in a Comparative Labor Market Perspective with the United States by Masanori Hashimoto Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 528, Citizens, Protest, and Democracy (Jul., 1993), pp. 202-203

17. Review: [untitled] Floyd B. McFarland Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 528, Citizens, Protest, and Democracy (Jul., 1993), pp. 203-204

18. Review: [untitled] Kenneth Nowotny Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 27, No. 3 (Sep., 1993), pp. 974-976

19. Review: [untitled] Lyle A. Downing Reviewed work(s): What's the Matter with Liberalism? by Ronald Beiner True Tolerance: Liberalism and the Necessity of Judgment by J. Budziszewski The American Political Science Review, Vol. 87, No. 3 (Sep., 1993), pp. 753-760

20. Review: [untitled] John T. Scholz Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite The American Political Science Review, Vol. 87, No. 3 (Sep., 1993), pp. 782-783

21. Review: Overcoming Barriers to Better Regulation Review: Overcoming Barriers to Better Regulation John Mendeloff Reviewed work(s): Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate by Ian Ayres; John Braithwaite Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 18, No. 4 (Autumn, 1993), pp. 711-729

22. Review: Two Faces of Justice: A Milestone in Quantitative Cross-Cultural Research Review: Two Faces of Justice: A Milestone in Quantitative Cross-

Page 44: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 42

Cultural Research David T. Johnson, Setsuo Miyazawa Reviewed work(s): Everyday Justice: Responsibility and the Individual in Japan and the United States by V. Lee Hamilton; Joseph Sanders Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 19, No. 3 (Summer, 1994), pp. 667-685

23. Review: [untitled] Robert Eli Rosen Reviewed work(s): Corporations, Crime and Accountability. by Brent Fisse; John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 24, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 93-94

24. Review: Putting Women First Review: Putting Women First Mary Coombs Reviewed work(s): Gender, Crime, and Punishment by Kathleen Daly Michigan Law Review, Vol. 93, No. 6, 1995 Survey of Books Relating to the Law (May, 1995), pp. 1686-1712

25. Review: [untitled] Katherine M. Jamieson Reviewed work(s): Beyond the Law: Crime in Complex Organizations. by Michael Tonry; Albert J. Reiss, Jr. Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 24, No. 3 (May, 1995), pp. 377-378

26. Review: Donald Black's Positivism in Law and Social Control Review: Donald Black's Positivism in Law and Social Control David Sciulli Reviewed work(s): The Social Structure of Right and Wrong by Donald Black Law & Social Inquiry, Vol. 20, No. 3 (Summer, 1995), pp. 805-828

27. Review: The Future of Criminologies Review: The Future of Criminologies David Downes Reviewed work(s): The Futures of Criminology by David Nelken The British Journal of Sociology, Vol. 47, No. 2 (Jun., 1996), pp. 360-365

28. Review: What's Criminology Got to Do with It? Review: What's Criminology Got to Do with It? David Cole Reviewed work(s): Malign Neglect: Race, Crime and Punishment in America by Michael Tonry Crime and Inequality by John Hagan; Ruth D. Peterson Stanford Law Review, Vol. 48, No. 6 (Jul., 1996), pp. 1605-1624

29. Review: [untitled] Darnell F. Hawkins Reviewed work(s): Crime and Inequality. by John Hagan; Ruth Peterson Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 25, No. 4 (Jul., 1996), pp. 537-538

30. Review: [untitled] Daniel Krislov Reviewed work(s): Crime and Public Policy: Putting Theory to Work. by Hugh D. Barlow Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 26, No. 1 (Jan., 1997), pp. 89-90

31. Review: [untitled] Frank Henry Reviewed work(s): Corporate Crime: Contemporary Debates by Frank Pearce; Laureen Snider Canadian Journal of Sociology / Cahiers canadiens de sociologie, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Spring, 1997), pp. 274-277

32. Review: Why Do Nations Obey International Law? Review: Why Do Nations Obey International Law? Harold Hongju Koh Reviewed work(s): The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements by Abram Chayes; Antonia Handler Chayes Fairness in International Law and Institutions by Thomas M. Franck The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 106, No. 8, Symposium: Group Conflict and the Constitution: Race, Sexuality, and Religion (Jun., 1997), pp. 2599-2659

33. Review: Discrediting the Free Market Review: Discrediting the Free Market Ian Ayres Reviewed work(s): The Progressive Assault on Laissez Faire: Robert Hale

Page 45: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 43

and the First Law and Economics Movement by Barbara Fried The University of Chicago Law Review, Vol. 66, No. 1 (Winter, 1999), pp. 273-296

34. Review: Putting the Regulated Back into Regulation Review: Putting the Regulated Back into Regulation Richard Johnstone Reviewed work(s): Corporate Regulation: Beyond 'Punish or Persuade' by Fiona Haines Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 26, No. 3 (Sep., 1999), pp. 378-390

35. Review: [untitled] Samantha Luks Reviewed work(s): Trust and Governance by Valerie Braithwaite; Margaret Levi The Journal of Politics, Vol. 61, No. 4 (Nov., 1999), pp. 1207-1208

36. Review: [untitled] Christopher T. Marsden Reviewed work(s): Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace by Lawrence Lessig The Modern Law Review, Vol. 63, No. 4 (Jul., 2000), pp. 624-628

37. Review: [untitled] Ronald Weitzer Reviewed work(s): The Handbook of Crime and Punishment by Michael Tonry Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 29, No. 4 (Jul., 2000), pp. 665-666

38. Review: [untitled] Lance Davis Reviewed work(s): The London Stock Exchange: A History by Ranald C. Michie The Journal of Economic History, Vol. 60, No. 4 (Dec., 2000), pp. 1141-1142

39. Review: [untitled] Ngaire Naffine Reviewed work(s): Criminology at the Crossroads: Feminist Readings in Crime and Justice by Kathleen Daly; Lisa Maher Crime Control and Women: Feminist Implications of Criminal Justice Policy by Susan L. Miller Nothing Bad Happens to Good Girls: Fear of Crime in Women's Lives by Esther Madriz Policing Women: The Sexual Politics of Law Enforcement and the LAPD by Janis Appier Signs, Vol. 26, No. 2 (Winter, 2001), pp. 572-577

40. Review: [untitled] Kathryn J. Fox Reviewed work(s): Doing Time: An Introduction to the Sociology of Imprisonment by Roger Matthews Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 30, No. 3 (May, 2001), pp. 292-294

41. Review: [untitled] John F. Camobreco Reviewed work(s): American Business and Political Power: Public Opinion, Elections, and Democracy by Mark A. Smith The American Political Science Review, Vol. 95, No. 3 (Sep., 2001), pp. 740-741

42. Review: [untitled] Thomas W. Church Reviewed work(s): The Regulatory Craft: Controlling Risks, Solving Problems, and Managing Compliance by Malcolm K. Sparrow The American Political Science Review, Vol. 95, No. 3 (Sep., 2001), pp. 741-742

43. Review: [untitled] Michael Woolcock Reviewed work(s): Global Business Regulation by John Braithwaite; Peter Drahos Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 30, No. 6 (Nov., 2001), pp. 626-627

44. Review: [untitled] Sidney A. Shapiro Reviewed work(s): Regulatory Encounters: Multinational Corporations and American Legal Adversarialism by Robert A. Kagan; Lee Axelrad The American Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 50, No. 1 (Winter, 2002), pp. 229-240

45. Review: Casting New Light on an Old Subject: Death Penalty Abolitionism for a New Millennium Review: Casting New Light on an Old Subject: Death Penalty Abolitionism for a New Millennium Wayne A. Logan Reviewed work(s): When the State Kills: Capital Punishment and the American Condition by Austin Sarat

Page 46: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 44

Michigan Law Review, Vol. 100, No. 6, 2002 Survey of Books Relating to the Law (May, 2002), pp. 1336-1379

46. Review: Is Republican Regulatory Law the Answer to Globalization? Review: Is Republican Regulatory Law the Answer to Globalization? William E. Scheuerman Reviewed work(s): Global Business Regulation by John Braithwaite; Peter Drahos The University of Toronto Law Journal, Vol. 52, No. 3 (Summer, 2002), pp. 301-311

47. Review: Dangers of Dystopias in Penal Theory Review: Dangers of Dystopias in Penal Theory Lucia Zedner Reviewed work(s): The Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in Contemporary Society by D. Garland Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Summer, 2002), pp. 341-366

48. Review: [untitled] Roger Brownsword Reviewed work(s): Genetic Privacy: A Challenge to Medico-Legal Norms by Graeme Laurie The Modern Law Review, Vol. 66, No. 1 (Jan., 2003), pp. 156-160

49. Review: [untitled] Andrew Sanders Reviewed work(s): Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation by John Braithwaite Regulation, Crime, Freedom by John Braithwaite The Modern Law Review, Vol. 66, No. 1 (Jan., 2003), pp. 160-167

50. Review: [untitled] Kathleen E. Hull Reviewed work(s): Regulating Intimacy: A New Legal Paradigm by Jean L. Cohen Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 5 (Sep., 2003), pp. 637-638

51. Review: [untitled] Mary C. Ingram Reviewed work(s): Information Feudalism: Who Owns the Knowledge Economy? by Peter Drahos; John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 5 (Sep., 2003), pp. 638-639

52. Review: [untitled] Anne M. Nurse Reviewed work(s): Convicted Survivors: The Imprisonment of Battered Women Who Kill by Elizabeth Dermody Leonard Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 6 (Nov., 2003), pp. 762-763

53. Review: [untitled] M. R. Bodapati, Paul Knepper Reviewed work(s): Shame Management through Reintegration by Eliza Ahmed; Nathan Harris; John Braithwaite; Valerie Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 6 (Nov., 2003), pp. 763-765

54. Review: [untitled] Jerry Van Hoy Reviewed work(s): Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Vol. 26 by Austin Sarat; Patricia Ewick Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 33, No. 1 (Jan., 2004), pp. 95-96

55. Review: [untitled] Michael P. Johnson Reviewed work(s): Restorative Justice and Family Violence by Heather Strang; John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 33, No. 1 (Jan., 2004), pp. 96-98

56. Review: [untitled] Giuseppe Eusepi Reviewed work(s): Australia Reshaped. 200 Years of Institutional Transformation by Geoffrey Brennan; Francis G. Castles Public Choice, Vol. 121, No. 3/4 (Oct., 2004), pp. 517-520

57. Review: The Rise of the British Regulatory State: Transcending the Privatization Debate Review: The Rise of the British Regulatory State: Transcending the Privatization Debate David Levi-Faur, Sharon Gilad Reviewed work(s): Regulation inside Government: Waste-Watchers, Quality Police and Sleaze-Busters by Christopher Hood; Colin Scott; Oliver James; George Jones; Tony Travers. The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification by Michael Power The

Page 47: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 45

British Regulatory State: High Modernism and Hyper-Innovation by Michael Moran Comparative Politics, Vol. 37, No. 1 (Oct., 2004), pp. 105-124

58. Review: Globalizing Regulatory Capitalism Review: Globalizing Regulatory Capitalism Jacint Jordana Reviewed work(s): A New World Order by Anne-Marie Slaughter Learning from Foreign Models in Latin American Policy Reform by Kurt Weyland Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 598, The Rise of Regulatory Capitalism: The Global Diffusion of a New Order (Mar., 2005), pp. 184-190

59. Review: Is There a Future for Leniency in the U.S. Criminal Justice System? Review: Is There a Future for Leniency in the U.S. Criminal Justice System? Nora V. Demleitner Reviewed work(s): Harsh Justice: Criminal Punishment and the Widening Divide between America and Europe by James Q. Whitman Michigan Law Review, Vol. 103, No. 6, 2005 Survey of Books Relating to the Law (May, 2005), pp. 1231-1272

60. Review: Making Happy Punishers Review: Making Happy Punishers James Q. Whitman Reviewed work(s): Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law by Martha C. Nussbaum Harvard Law Review, Vol. 118, No. 8 (Jun., 2005), pp. 2698-2724

61. Review: [untitled] Bill Martin Reviewed work(s): Markets in Vice, Markets in Virtue by John Braithwaite Contemporary Sociology, Vol. 35, No. 6 (Nov., 2006), pp. 614-615

62. Review: [untitled] Michacl E. Bucrger Reviewed work(s): Third Party Policing by Lorraine Mazerolle; Janet Ransley The American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 113, No. 2 (Sep., 2007), pp. 593-595

Page 48: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 46

References

Ayres, Ian and John Braithwaite. 1992. Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate. New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Barnett, Randy. 1977. “Restitution: A New Paradigm of Criminal Justice,” Ethics, Vol. 87, No. 4 (Jul., 1977), pp. 279-301

Beale, Joseph H., “Social Justice and Business Costs: A Study in the Legal History of Today,” Harvard Law Review, Vol. 49, No. 4 (Feb., 1936), pp. 593-609.

Braithwaite, John. 1982. “Challenging Just Deserts: Punishing White-Collar Criminals,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982), pp. 723-763.

Braithwaite, John. 1982. “Comment on "The Criminal Law as a Threat System,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982),pp. 786-789.

Braithwaite, John. 1982. “Reply to Dr. Ernest van den Haag,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973-), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982),pp. 790-793

Braithwaite, John. 1984. Corporate Crime in the Pharmaceutical Industry. London, Boston, Melbourne, and Henly: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Braithwaite, John. 1989. Crime, Shame and Reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Braithwaite, John. 1999. “Restorative Justice: Assessing Optimistic and Pessimistic Accounts,” Crime and Justice, Vol. 25 (1999), pp. 1-127.

Braithwaite, John. 2001. “Crime in a Convict Republic,” The Modern Law Review, Vol. 64, No. 1 (Jan., 2001), pp. 11-50.

Braitwaite, John. 2009. Private communication to the author. Subject: Re: Genesis of Reintegrative Shaming? Sent By: john <[email protected]> On: March 31, 2009 1:29 AM To: [email protected]

Braitwaite, John and Philip Petit. 1990. Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Braithwaite, John and Philip Petit. 1994. “Republican Criminology and Victim Advocacy: Comment,” Law & Society Review, Vol. 28, No. 4 (1994), pp. 765-776.

Braithwaite, John and Valerie Braithwaite and Eliza Ahmed, “Reintegrative Shaming,” in Lanier, Mark M. and Stuart Henry, Editors.2006. The Essential Criminology Reader. Boulder: Westview Press.

Braithwaite, Valerie. 2004. “The Hope Process and Social Inclusion,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 592. pp. 128-151.

Cao, Liqun. 2004. Major Criminological Theories: Concepts and Measurements. Belmont, California: Wadsworth Group.

Cochran, Robert F., Jr. 2000. “The Criminal Defense Attorney: Roadblock or Bridge to Restorative Justice,” Journal of Law and Religion, Vol. 14, No. 1 (1999 - 2000), pp. 211-228.

Delgado Richard. 2000. “Goodbye to Hammurabi: Analyzing the Atavistic Appeal of Restorative Justice,” Stanford Law Review, Vol. 52, No. 4 (Apr., 2000), pp. 751-775.

Page 49: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 47

Dietz, Jorg and Sandra L. Robinson, Robert Folger, Robert A. Baron, Martin Schulz. 2003. “The Impact of Community Violence and an Organization's Procedural Justice Climate onWorkplace Aggression,” The Academy of Management Journal, Vol. 46, No. 3 (Jun., 2003), pp. 317-326.

Dzur, Albert, 2003. “Civic Implications of Restorative Justice Theory: Citizen Participation and Criminal Justice,” Policy Sciences, Vol. 36, No. 3/4 (Dec., 2003), pp. 279-306.

Fisse, Brent and John Braithwaite. 1983. The Impact of Publicity on Corporate Offenders. Albany: State University of New York Press.

Greif, Avner. 2006. “History Lessons: The Birth of Impersonal Exchange: The Community Responsibility System and Impartial Justice,” The Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 20, No. 2 (Spring, 2006), pp. 221-236

Harris, Nathan and Shadd Maruna. “Shame, Shaming and Restorative justice: A critical appraisal,” Published in: Sullivan, D. &Tiff, L. (2006). Handbook of Restorative Justice. New York: Routledge.

Hoebel, E. Adamson. 1967. The Law of Primitive Man: A Study in Comparative Legal Dynamics. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

Hudson, Barbara. “Restorative Justice: The Challenge of Sexual and Racial Violence,” Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 25, No. 2 (Jun., 1998), pp. 237-256.

Hudson, Joe and Burt Galaway. 1980. Victims, Offenders, and Alternative Sanctions. Lexington: Lexington Books D. C. Heath.

Karp, David R. and Todd R. Clear, Editors. 2002. What is Community Justice? Case Studies of Restorative Justice and Community Supervision. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publishers.

Kelly, Russell (2003). Victim-Offender Reconciliation Program – In the Beginning. Included in “Restorative Justice Week 2004: Engaging Us All in the Dialogue.” Ottawa: Correctional Service of Canada. http://www.restorativejustice.org/

King, P. D. 1972. Law and Society in the Visigothic Kingdom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kurki, Leena. 2000. “Restorative and Community Justice in the United States,” Crime and Justice, Vol. 27 (2000), pp. 235-303.

Lanier, Mark M. and Stuart Henry. 1998. Essential Criminology. Boulder: Westview Press.

Leebaw, Bronwyn. 2003. “Legitimation or Judgment? South Africa's Restorative Approach to Transitional Justice,” Polity, Vol. 36, No. 1 (Oct., 2003), pp. 23-51.

Lilly, J. Robert and Francis T. Cullen and Richard Ball. 2007. Criminological Theory: Context and Consequences. Thousand Oaks. Sage Publications.

Lin, Ming-Jen. 2007a. “Does democracy increase crime? The evidence from international data.” National Taiwan University, No. 21, Hsu-Chow Road, Taipei, Taiwan. Received 17 January 2007; revised 12 June 2007.

Lin, Ming-Jen. 2007b. “Does Unemployment Increase Crime? Evidence from U.S. Data 1974–2000. Submitted May 2006; accepted June 2007.

Llewellyn, Jennifer J. and Robert Howse. 1999. Institutions for Restorative Justice: The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission,” The University of Toronto Law Journal, Vol. 49, No. 3 (Summer, 1999), pp. 355-388.

Page 50: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 48

Llewellyn, Jennifer J. 2002. “Dealing with the Legacy of Native Residential School Abuse in Canada: Litigation, ADR, and Restorative Justice,” The University of Toronto Law Journal, Vol. 52, No. 3 (Summer, 2002), pp. 253-300.

Llewellyn, K. N. and E. Adamson Hoebel. 1941. The Cheyenne Way: Conflict and Case Law in Primitive Jurisprudence. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.

Lujan, Carol Chiago and Gordon Adams. “U.S. Colonization of Indian Justice Systems: A Brief History,” Wicazo Sa Review, Vol. 19, No. 2, Colonization / Decolonization, I (Autumn, 2004), pp. 9-23.

McEvoy, Kieran and Tim Newburn, editors. 2003. Criminology, Conflict Resolution and Restorative Justice. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

Merry, Sally Engle and Neal Milner. 1993. The Possibility of Popular Justice: A Case Study of Community Mediation in the United States. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

Miller, William Ian. 1983. “ Choosing the Avenger: Some Aspects of the Bloodfeud in Medieval Iceland and England,” Law and History Review, Vol. 1, No. 2 (Autumn, 1983), pp. 159-204.

Miller, William Ian. 1984. “Avoiding Legal Judgment: The Submission of Disputes to Arbitration in Medieval Iceland,” The American Journal of Legal History, Vol. 28, No. 2 (Apr., 1984), pp. 95-134.

Nicholl, Caroline G. 2000. Toolbox of Implementing Restorative Justice and Advancing Community Policing: A Guidebook Prepared for the Office of Community Oriented Policing Services (COPS), U.S. Department of Justice. Washington D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice.

Olsen, Susan M. and Albert W. Dzur. 2004. “Revisiting Informal Justice: Restorative Justice and Democratic Professionalism,” Law & Society Review, Vol. 38, No. 1 (Mar., 2004), pp. 139-176.

Ptacin, John M. and Jeremy Worley and Keith Richotte. 2005. “The Bethel Therapeutic Court: A Study of How Therapeutic Courts Align with Yup'ik and Community Based Notions of Justice,” American Indian Law Review , Vol. 30, No. 1 (2005/2006), pp. 133-150.

Rosenberg, Joshua D. and H. Jay Folberg. “Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Empirical Analysis,” Stanford Law Review, Vol. 46, No. 6 (Jul., 1994), pp. 1487-1551.

Shevell, Steven. 1995. “Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis,” The Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 24, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 1-28.

Sullivan, Dennis and Larry Tifft. 2001. Restorative Justice: Healing the Foundations of Our Everyday Lives. Monsey, New York: Willow Tree Press.

Sullivan, Dennis and Larry Tifft. 2006. The Handbooks of Restorative Justice: A Global Perspective. New York. Routledge.

Tarifa, Fatos. 2008. Vengeance is Mine: Justice Albanian Style. Chapel Hill: Globic Press.

Umbreit, Mark S. and Robert B. Coates. 2000. Multicultural Implications of Restorative Justice: Potential Pitfalls and Dangers. Washington D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice; Office of Justice Programs; Office for Victims of Crime.

Umbreit, Mark S. and Jean Greenwood. 2000. Guidelines for Victim-Sensitive Victim-Offender Mediation: Restorative Justice Through Dialogue. Washington D.C.:

Page 51: Reintegrative Shaming and Restorative Justice

Marotta Restorative Shaming Page 49

U.S. Department of Justice; Office of Justice Programs; Office for Victims of Crime.

Van den Haag, Ernest. 1982a. “Reply to Dr. John Braithwaite,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982), pp. 794-796.

Van den Haag. Ernest. 1982b. “Comment on "Challenging Just Deserts: Punishing White-Collar Criminals,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982), pp. 764-768.

Van den Haag, Ernest. 1982c. “The Criminal Law as a Threat System,.” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982), pp. 769 785.

Van den Haag, Ernest. 1982d. “Reply to Dr. John Braithwaite.” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology (1973), Vol. 73, No. 2 (Summer, 1982), pp. 794-796.

Villa-Vicencio, Charles. “The Reek of Cruelty and the Quest for Healing: Where Retributive and Restorative Justice Meet,” Journal of Law and Religion, Vol. 14, No. 1 (1999 - 2000), pp. 165-187.

Von Hirsh, Andrew. “Desert and White-Collar Criminality: A Response to Dr. Braithwaite,” The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology Vol. 73, No. 3 (Autumn, 1982), pp. 1164-1175.

Zehr, Howard. 1990. A New Focus for Crime and Justice: Changing Lenses. Waterloo, Ontario: Herald Press.

Zehr, Howard. 2001. Transcending: Reflections of Crime Victims. Intercourse, Pennsylvania: Good Books.

------. Student Handbook and Catalog 2008-2009. International Institute for Restorative Practices. REV. 3/3/09, Bethlehem, Pennsylvania.