postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

22
University of Oregon Postdeconstructive Necrophilia: Grave Spaces in Aristotle, Augustine, and Blanchot and the Question of the Decision Author(s): Floyd Dunphy Reviewed work(s): Source: Comparative Literature, Vol. 56, No. 2 (Spring, 2004), pp. 147-167 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of Oregon Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4125446 . Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:20 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Literature. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: mariane-farias

Post on 27-Jan-2015

111 views

Category:

Education


1 download

DESCRIPTION

 

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

University of Oregon

Postdeconstructive Necrophilia: Grave Spaces in Aristotle, Augustine, and Blanchot and theQuestion of the DecisionAuthor(s): Floyd DunphyReviewed work(s):Source: Comparative Literature, Vol. 56, No. 2 (Spring, 2004), pp. 147-167Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of OregonStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4125446 .Accessed: 23/09/2012 12:20

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to Comparative Literature.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

FLOYD DUNPHY

Postdeconstructive

Necrophilia: Grave Spaces

in Aristotle, Augustine, and Blanchot and the

Question of the Decision

T HIS INQUIRY

SEEKS TO TRACE the sight-line from a critique of existential voluntarism towards a radical analytic of death, where the articulation of the

self is reconfigured in terms of a postdeconstructive subjectivity. Section one notes the failure of Existentialism's radical self-authentication to say anything significant and enduring about human subjectivity and draws upon Iris Murdoch and Martin Heidegger to suggest a place within the following discussion of ethics for the continuous self and private intention. Section two seeks to outline the boundaries of the subject, its ghostly demarcations, and its movement from Dasein to Mitsein. This movement is analyzed in terms of a sustained meditation upon death and leads into notions of phenomenological space. This will help us gain entry into the delicate texture of necrophilia and will function as the conceptual framework that we will use to examine the type of subject Derrida is seeking to establish after Heidegger. Section three applies this conceptual framework to passages in Aristotle, Augustine, and Blanchot that involve subjectivity and friend- ship. Section four then examines the structure and content of the decision that issues from the postdeconstructive subject and follows the decision's migration outward into the political realm. An example of this outward migration will take us into a consideration of the "New International"-Derrida and Critchley's glo- bally deconstructed political community-a consideration that will investigate the complex reciprocity between ethics and politics and subjectivity as a reinvi- sioning of a possible humanism, a neohumanism.

1. The Critique of the Essential Subject: The Problem of Existential Voluntarism

Martin Heidegger and Iris Murdoch offer two challenging critiques to Sartrean Existentialism. In his Letter On Humanism, Heidegger charges Sartre with merely inverting the Platonic order of essence and existence:

Page 3: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 148

By way of contrast, Sartre expresses the basic tenet of existentialism in this way: Existence precedes essence. In this statement he is taking existentia and essentia according to their metaphysical mean- ing, which from Plato's time on has said that essentia precedes existentia. Sartre reverses this state- ment. But the reversal of a metaphysical statement remains a metaphysical statement. With it he stays with metaphysics in oblivion of the truth of Being. (Basic 208)

This is the Existentialists' move, a move that, according to Heidegger, kept Sartre

imprisoned within the history of metaphysics. Heidegger's dasein, on the other hand, as an instantiation of the continuous historical self, suggests a self that is involved in an ongoing process. "Being-there," hereness, consciousness folded into

temporality, becomes Heidegger's account of a postmetaphysical selfhood. Iris Murdoch critiques Sartre's Existentialist move for a different reason-

namely, that it privileges an omnipotent will. In order to resist the Existentialists' reduction of everything to decisionism, Murdoch suggests instead a subjectivity that has the continuous ongoing texture of the metaphor of vision. In his view the Existentialists overemphasize will and action-especially publicly observable action-and so valorize the individual within the public domain, the world of

ordinary facts.

According to the Existentialists, it is the decision to act that actualizes oneself in the public sphere: only public decisions count as politics. This approach pro- hibits the taking up of a contemplative attitude towards an introspective subjec- tivity; it also delimits the possibilities for self-reflexivity and for all of those

interesting moments that come before the decision. For the Existentialist, "self-

knowledge is something which shows overtly" and is seen only once it is too late:

"Morality resides at the point of action," at the brink of haste (Murdoch 311). The self becomes a point of pure will.

For Murdoch, subjectivity (and, following from that, ethics and politics) is not the will breaking free, authenticating itself in a fleeting public instant. Rather, approaching subjectivity in relation to the metaphor of vision helps us to resist utilitarianism and to understand intention as an interior struggle, as an action that can only be performed privately: But if we consider what the work of attention is like, how continuously it goes on, and how imper- ceptibly it builds up structures of value round about us, we shall not be surprised that at crucial moments of choice most of the business of choosing is already over... But it implies that the exer- cise of our freedom is a small piecemeal business which goes on all the time and not a grandiose leaping about unimpeded at important moments. The moral life, on this view, is something that goes on continually, not something that is switched off in between the occurrence of explicit moral choices. (329)

For Murdoch, the "exercise of freedom" is an activity that takes place sometimes

quietly, sometimes violently, but always within the deep caverns of interiority where all of the significant struggles for good and evil take place. This notion of vision, "of a patient, loving regard, directed upon a person, a thing, a situation," en-

gages the will in an act of sustained attention, rather than unimpeded freedom (Murdoch 331).

2. Postdeconstructive Subjectivity: Being-Toward Death from Dasein to Mitsein

Derrida and Simon Critchley, spurred on by the ethical philosophy of Emmanuel

Page 4: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/ 149

Levinas, likewise endeavor to go beyond the Existentialist essentialisms critiqued by Heidegger and Murdoch by offering up a postdeconstructive subjectivity. But in their insistence on the political decision-it is in this totality, or not-their post- deconstructive subjectivity may also finally soften into a postdeconstructive voluntar- ism. Indeed, it is within the nostalgic traces of existentialism that Critchley and Derrida and Levinas emerge with some of their most interesting and provocative insights. It remains to be seen, however, whether the texture of the political deci- sion-new and singular each time-is enough convincingly to suspend the weight of the ethical life that emerges within friendship-political or otherwise.

Derrida weaves his discussion of inter-subjectivity within the historical fibers of the ancient texts on friendship. He begins with the vocative attributed to Aristotle

by Montaigne and others: "O my friends, there are no friends!" It is this haunting maxim that shapes Derrida's thinking on the destablization of "friendship" throughout his Politics of Friendship. This destabilization becomes a porthole for the political, and it is through this that we will be transported to the decision of the political moment.

Following the Levinasian subject, a being who empties itself of its Being, Derridian friendship begins with a sense of loss. The conditions of possibility for

friendship are to be found in the idea of a de-distanced, dissymmetrical topol- ogy. Philia begins in survivance. Philia survives to love the inanimate. The beloved survives in the hopes of being loved in life, as well as in death: I do not survive the friend, I cannot and must not survive him, except to the extent to which he

already bears my death and inherits it as the last survivor. He bears my own death and, in a certain way, he is the only one to bear it-this proper death of myself thus expropriated in advance. (Politics 13)

Mourning is the grieved act of possible loving in friendship. It is the mourning before mourning that is the proper death before death. It is only in full view of the grave that friendship may begin. The anguish of loss within friendship is

suspended and becomes the radical possibility for the condition of fraternity. The lover is plunged into anticipated mourning for the beloved: this is the very breath of friendship, that love may presence itself in the absence of death:

Friendship for the deceased thus carries this philia to the limit of its possibility. But at the same time, it uncovers the ultimate spring of this possibility: I could not love friendship without projecting its

impetus towards the horizon of this death. (12)

There are two very important things to notice about this statement: first, that the death is of someone else, and second, that it is a particular death. The death of the Other, like friendship with the deceased, decenters my own subjectivity and calls it outward into radical suspension towards the Other in the grieved act of lov-

ing. This is the meaning of beloved: to love someone even past the point of death:

"loving belongs only to a being gifted with life or with breath ... being loved, on the other hand, always remains possible on the side of the inanimate" (12).

That the extreme delimitations of the possibilities of friendship are to be un- derstood in proximity to the horizon of death in the Other is a fundamental inver- sion of Dasein, the Heideggerian subject who can only experience its own death. For Heidegger, when Dasein experiences death, it experiences the simple move- ment from the state of "being-there" to "no-longer-being-there." However, be- cause Dasein is the subjective consciousness of "being-there," it is incapable of

Page 5: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 150

experiencing death as a transition from the moment it is "no-longer-being-there." The very brilliance of Heidegger's fundamental move-Dasein as consciousness folded into temporality (being there)-delimits Heideggerian subjectivity from

experiencing and understanding what it would mean no longer to be here. It cannot

experience its own death as a transition. This is why the death of others, for

Heidegger, becomes all the more extraordinary, for it is through the analytic of Mitda-sein that Dasein possesses a being-with-one-another that allows it to gain ac- cess to an experience of death. Although the experience of death through Mitda- sein seems, from the outset, a concession that is to some extent commensurable with the view of Derrida, Levinas, and others, Heidegger also introduces a dis- tinction that sets his view apart from that of his descendants-the difference between "being-with" and "being-with-the-dead": In such being-with with the dead, the deceased himself is no longer factically "there." However, be-

ing-with always means being-with-one-another in the same world. The deceased has abandoned our "world" and left it behind. It is in terms of this world that those remaining can still be with him. The more appropriately the no-longer-being-there of the deceased is grasped phenomenally, the more clearly it can be seen that in such being-with with the dead, the real having-come-to-an-end of the deceased is precisely not experienced. Death does reveal itself as a loss, but as a loss experienced by those remaining behind. However, in suffering the loss, the loss of being as such which the dying person "suffers" does not become accessible. We do not experience the dying of others in a genuine sense; we are at best alwaysjust "there" too. (222)

Implicit in this excerpt from Being and Time is the phenomenological difference between absence and presence. In rough language, the dead are not able to be with us the way living people are able to be with us-and yet they are still with us. This is the significance of Heidegger's distinction between Mitda-sein, "being- with," and "being-with-the-dead." It seems as though we cannot experience the death of the Other in the same way that we are able to experience our own deaths. In the death of the Other we do not experience death as a direct loss, but only as those who remain behind, experiencing the death-loss through proxy. Although it would appear that our only access to the experience of death is through our

being together with the dead, our necrophilia, our fraternity with the deceased- or those about to be deceased-does not grant us sufficient purchase on the death experience: we are at best always just "there." We are thus caught in a pecu- liar catch-22 scenario in which Dasein is able to experience neither its own death nor the death of others in such a way that it may register the impress of its own

mortality in a meaningful fashion. But what is Heidegger driving at when he says that "every Da-sein must itself actually take dying upon itself. Insofar as it 'is,' death is always essentially my own?" (Being 223), or that "in dying, it becomes evident that death is ontologically constituted by mineness and existence?" (223). Perhaps his next statement will serve as a clue: "Dying is not an event, but a

phenomenon to be understood existentially" (223). If "being-there" requires the consciousness of a Dasein, a subjective presence,

then "no-longer-being-there" can only be experienced by the one who was first conscious of "being-there." Thus, Heidegger can say that death is always essen- tially my own. Death in this sense finds our subjectivity heavily weighted with our own eventual finitude. Viewed properly, the Heideggerian concept of death is our being-toward this finitude. It is a fundamental posture that we take in the face

Page 6: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/151

of our own mortality knowing that what it means to be human, to be conscious of

being here, will one day end: it is the last and most significant thing that we will do without knowing it.

But does this preoccupation with temporal consciousness- being-there--hint of the leftover traces of the modern subject? Is Heidegger's painting a palimp- sest, the residual image of a Cartesian ego emerging through the thickly tex- tured existential analytic of Heidegger's Dasein? From this perspective, death becomes an ontology, a totality that tries to take in the whole scope and horizon of death. This is the death universal, and Heidegger's analysis becomes a meta- physics of death, albeit abundantly nuanced.

According to Simon Critchley, there has always been a strained idiosyncratic fissure interrupting the flow of Heidegger's (and I hesitate to use the word) logic. "If one were to push this claim a little further, one might say that there is a straightforward incoherence, in Heidegger's Being and Time, between the analy- sis of Mitsein in Division I and the determination of Mitsein as das Volk in Division II" (247). This is the abstruse tension between Dasein and Mitsein. Everything that Heidegger tries to accomplish in disclosure seems to be best served in the middle of the contextual particularities of everydayness, but it seems as though Heidegger still suffers from a modern Cartesian complex: an utter flight from the sensibilities of things, back into ontology and, reluctantly, the pre-imminent cogito.' For Critchley this is the disturbing pathos of Heidegger's authenticity that so desperately needs to be avoided. In his view: the genuine philosophical radicality of Being and Time lies in the existential analytic of inauthenticity. What has to be recovered from the wreckage of Heidegger's political commitment is his phenom- enology of everyday life, the sheer banality of our contact (cotoiment) with the world and with others. (240)

Being and Time must be rewritten from the perspective of the inauthenticity of the Mitsein-analytic and reconfigured as a social ontology. Saying we, the us that we are, is a recognition that the existential analytic of Dasein was too limiting a project. What is needed instead is a broadening of our gaze outward to allow for our social being to emerge, and, having done so, to announce the death of meta- physics as a privileged science.

But this realization does not mean that we need abandon Heidegger altogether. Heidegger remains ready-at-hand, armed with all of the conceptual tools to suffi- ciently rearticulate this new position. There is no going beyond Heidegger un- less we go forward with him. To overcome him will mean that he will always be our companion.2

' "The senses do not enable us to know any being in its being; they merely make known the usefulness and harmfulness of 'external' inner worldly things for human beings encumbered with bodies..,. they tell us nothing at all about beings in their being" (Heidegger, Being 90). Heidegger's commentary on his analysis of Descartes' contempt for sensibility is ironic, however, because subjec- tivity, for Heidegger, is a matter to be thought within the structure of Dasein. This is the very thing that Levinas and Derrida will define themselves against. For them, subjectivity (or more to the point: ethics as first philosophy) begins with the sensation in the face of the Other. Against Heidegger, theface is not a matter to be thought at all; it is not an object of our understanding. Rather, we apprehend the Other in proximity.

2 "My view, broadly stated, is that the ambiguity of thinking the subject after Heidegger must be governed by the double bind of a double affirmation: firstly, by the need-ethically, politically,

Page 7: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 152

For Heidegger, Dasein always encounters others and other things (things ex-

tended)3 from within the given world, things that are "at hand." Being in is always a being with (Being 112). As Dasein surfaces to its own awareness through Mitsein -worldness-it does so through the phenomenology of care, that is, "in terms of a totality of the interconnected places of the context of useful things at hand in the surrounding world" (Being 95). Heideggerian subjectivity goes from "being there" to "being with" to belonging there. The positional belonging of beings and things is gathered into the nearness of a region. This is what constitutes Heidegger's notion of aroundness, which is "the being around us of beings encountered ini-

tially in the surrounding world," "the spatiality of what is at hand" (Being 96). These everyday associations, the spatiality of what is at hand, are not "catalogued by the observational measurement of space"; rather, they are apprehended in their giveness through a taking care of things (Being 96). It is through this mode of

discovery that Dasein, by being-in-the-world, encounters the regional spatiality of

things-at-hand. This, in turn, could be said to describe the primordial nature of disclosure:

Space, which is discovered in circumspect being-in-the-world as the spatiality of a totality of useful

things, belongs to beings themselves as their place ... But this spatiality has its own unity by virtue of the worldlike totality of relevance of what is spatially at hand. The "surrounding world" does not

arrange itself in a previously given space, but rather its specific worldliness articulates in its signifi- cance the relevant context of an actual totality of places circumspectly referred to each other. The actual world discovers the spatiality of space belonging to it. The fact that what is at hand can be encountered in its space of the surrounding world is ontically possible only because Da-sein itself is

"spatial" with regard to its being-in-the-world. (Being96-97)

Implicit within this notion of spatiality is the concept of de-distancing, which removes the alienation of space and time that exists between corporeal beings and objects: De-distancing means making distance disappear, making the being at a distance of something dis-

appear, bringing it near. Dasein is essentially de-distancing. As the being that it is, it lets beings be encountered in nearness ... De-distancing ... must be kept in mind as an existential. (Being 97)

This de-distancing is, for the most part, a bringing near, and it is the essential ten- dencies of Mitsein that gather things together in the overcoming of distance. Remoteness or nearness should not be understood in terms of objective distance, but as powers and capabilities of human subjectivity. That is why the presence of an absent lover can seem closer to us than the very object that we hold in our own hand: On those paths Dasein does not traverse, like an objectively present corporeal thing, a stretch of

space, it does not "eat up kilometres"; nearing and de-distancing are always a heedful being toward what is approached and de-distanced. An "objectively" long path can be shorter than an "objec-

metaphysically---to leave the climate of Heidegger's thinking; and secondly, by the conviction that we cannot leave it for a philosophy that would be pre-Heideggerian. That is, there is no going back behind Heidegger and no going forward without him; the break or paradigm shift occasioned by Sein und Zeit is, in my view, philosophically decisive" (Critchley 62). Critchley will likewise divide L~vinas's Zionism from his ethical thought, thereby removing the primary thrust from Levinas's writings.

3 In one sense, we have never left behind Descartes, who articulated the ontological difference between self and world that led to epistemology, the logic of positivism, the linguistic turn, herme- neutics, and, most recently, the ethical turn. Whatever new reconfigurations of subjectivity we artic- ulate, we will always feel the ebbs and flows of consonance and dissonance between self and world.

Page 8: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/153

tively" much shorter path which is perhaps an "onerous one" and strikes one as infinitely long ... The objective distances of objectively present things do not co-incide with the remoteness and nearness of what is at hand in the world. (Being 99)

On Heidegger's account it is clear that de-distancing operates as a principle of

phenomenology,4 and in order for it to be understood in meaningful ways it must be approached existentially through the phenomenon of care. For Heidegger care is the only "logic" (or "anti-logic") that can account for the relational ontology of Mitsein, and it will prove to be indispensable in our coming to an understanding of life together. The circumspect de-distancing of everyday Da-sein discovers the

being-in-itself of the "true" world, of beings with which Da-sein as existing is al-

ways already together (Being 99, italics mine). Taking care, then, creates the conditions of possibilities for an encounter with

the Other. "The other is encountered in his Mitda-Sein in the world" (Being 113). Moreover, the ongoing texture of care contours the subjectivity of Dasein to the

point where "being-with-others belongs to the being of Dasein" (Being 115). In this, we are beginning to see the first traces of a (post) deconstructive subjectiv- ity, although one would be hard pressed to prove that Heidegger understood the full import of all of the nuances of his own thinking. In words Levinas would later use, this is the inaugural appearance of the conception of the demand of the Other residing in me. In Heidegger's own words, "As being-with, Dasein 'is'

essentially for the sake of others" (Being 116). Butjust as we seem to have touched the hem of a postdeconstructive subjectiv-

ity in Heidegger, the whole thing begins to unravel-and unravel quickly. The

unraveling starts with a disturbing comment that Heidegger makes after having just established that Dasein is "essentially for the other": "But when actual, factical Dasein does not turn to others and thinks that it does not need them, or misses them, it is in the mode of being-with" (Being 112, italics mine). The fibrous con- nection with the Other proves threadbare. What previously appeared to be the continuous ongoing texture of world is coming apart at the seams: This phenomenon, which is none too happily designated as "empathy," is then supposed, as it were, to provide the first ontological bridge from one's own subject, initially given by itself, to the other subject, which is initially quite inaccessible... it remains puzzling how the relation of Dasein to itself is to disclose the other as other. (Being 117)

What we are witnessing is a Cartesian flight from the world into the security of the cogito. For Heidegger, everydayness loses traction and fades away into the publicness of the they. This is a form of forgetfulness and, as such, qualifies as a form of inauthenticity. The impending trauma of intersubjectivity proved to be too great for Heidegger, and, rather than embrace the decentering that needed to take place in order for subjectivity to be released from the insular constric- tions of Dasein, Heidegger collapsed back into the familiar isolation of Dasein, and with this decisive move remains within a history of subjectivity that is closer to Descartes than it is to L~vinas.5

4 Let us remember Heidegger's definition of phenomenon: "Phenomenon-the self-showing in it- self-means a distinctive way something can be encountered" (Being 27).

SI am being deliberately provocative here in order to establish the view that Levinas needs to be seen as making a significant break from Heidegger, and, as such, does not define his task as solving the problem of self and world.

Page 9: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 154

There remains, however, one possible opening onto the infinite in Heidegger's thought that will smooth our transmigration into Derrida's thinking, a statement that creates the preconditions for a togetherness-a togetherness that can reach into the beyond-a togetherness that embraces the impending finitude of the grave and yet is still a denial of death: "Being-with existentially determines Da-sein even when an other is not factically present and perceived... This being-with and the facticity of being-with-one-another are not based on the fact that several

'subjects' are physically there together" (Being 113). To access the richness of this statement, we must read it in the inverse. My being-with-one-another is not in terms of this world, but it is in terms of another world, a world where the dead live on to be loved by us-an us who still occupy this world, the world of Heidegger's everydayness. There is an absence that exhibits such density that, like a black hole, it sucks us into a death-world where the deceased may once again com- mune with us and be-loved. What Heidegger condemned as inauthentic, Derrida celebrates in luxurious morbid jubilation. Derrida's togetherness, unlike Heideg- ger's, is a necro-philia, a friendship with the dead, a vital synergy with the grave that demands a new estimation of subjectivity that will go beyond Heidegger's Dasein. The space in which friendship issues is a presencing, an ecstasy, that

collapses the vast geography of space and time into this other world-into the

space of memory. The infusion of space and time into memory creates a world-

space for an intersubjective opening onto the infinite. The breach between the world of the living and of the dead is held, through the dialect of memory, in tension. Until we are willing to linger in this middle space, we are not yet ready to understand what Heidegger should have meant by Mitsein or what Derrida is now seeking in his new determination of the subject.

3. Necrophilia: Aristotle, Augustine, and Blanchot

Friendship stretches out toward the future-and the past. Friendship begins by one friend recalling another in proximity, temporality, and memory-even from beyond the grave: "Friendship begins by surviving ... it is because of Friend-

ship that the dead live ... the condition of possibility for friendship is memory. The dead live because they are recalled by friends, they survive after death be- cause they are not forgotten. In this sense, philia, is necro-philia" (Critchley 257-

58). This precondition of memoria will now reorient our thinking towards a certain

fraternal conjuration: an invocation of the dead. For Derrida, this fraternalization is

constructed, not only spatially (from different places), but also temporally (from different times). Derrida characterizes this summoning of the dead in terms of the responsibility of the other residing in us:

But this responsibility can be called for only by first of all summoning the dead. They are, after a fashion, made to be born again; they are convoked in an invocation, once again, of their birth. The oath of this co-engagement thus resembles of fraternal conjuration. (Politics 94)

Here, I will summon across time and place three friends, who will provide us with a meditation on death and friendship. I will begin with Aristotle, who must traverse the greatest distance to presence himself with us: "In the development devoted to

Page 10: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/155

this inequality Aristotle evokes friendship with the dead, [even though now he him- self is dead-the dead invoking the dead through memory?] a friendship which knows without being known... Hence one must not ask to be loved in return ... or to be loved in like measure to one's own love" (Derrida, Politics 206-207). Loving the dead in friendship, for Aristotle, occurs in an incongruous fashion. This incongruous dissymmetry first takes place in the vocative attributed to Aristotle, O my friends, there are nofriends!-a vocative that presupposes a "saying" and an "unsaying." Aristotle utters a vocative to be heard by friends, even as he laments there are no friends. Because of this, Derrida assigns Aristotle to a herme- neutics of suspicion, one that destabilizes understanding into misunderstanding: Aristotle-let us call him by that name-at least asked the other to hear him, understand him, to be

enough of a friend to do so, and therefore to, consider him-Aristotle-as a friend, qua the friend of a promise of friendship? And even at the very moment of saying "no friend"? This request for

friendship, this offer of friendship, this call to coming together in friendship, at least to hear, the time it takes to hear, at least to finally agree, the time it takes to agree on the meaning of the sentence, even if it were still saying, in the saying of its said, the worst in dialectics, is this, this saying of the said, not, then, the "I love you listen" of the "I love you; do you hear me?" (Politics 217, italics mine)

Derrida's view is that the text before him is fraught with fissures that, if agitated, will begin to deconstruct text and meaning through the process of contradic- tion. With Derrida, a more delicate approach is always in order, one that appreci- ates the delicate tensions of irony: But we cannot, and we must not, exclude the fact that when someone is speaking, in private or in

public, when someone teaches, publishes, preaches, orders, promises, prophesies, informs or com- municates, some force in him or her is also striving not to be understood, approved, accepted in consensus-not immediately, not fully, and therefore not in the immediacy and plenitude of tomor- row. (Politics 218)

Hidden somewhere in the echoes of Aristotle's vocative is the desire for misun- derstanding: Aristotle is striving not to be understood even as he pleads with us to listen. With great deconstructive energy, Aristotle's vocative displays a textual incongruence that is provocative and that demands that we remain with its dia- lectical tensions for awhile in the hopes of understanding (a virtue usually con- nected with the hermeneutics of trust); by doing so, we have ventured into a friendship with the one who has uttered that there are no friends.

In his Nichomachean Ethics Aristotle likewise discloses the abiding commitments that he holds with regard to the notion of subjectivity within friendship by problematizing the notion of wishing the greatest good for one's friend: This raises the question whether or not we wish our friends the greatest of all goods, namely, to be

gods. For (if that wish were fulfilled,) they would no longer be our friends, and, since friends are

something good, we would have lost this good. Accordingly, if our assertion is correct that a man wishes his friend's good for his friend's sake, the friend would have to remain the man he was. Consequently, one will wish the greatest good for his friend as a human being, but perhaps not all the greatest goods, for each man wishes for his own good most of all. (1 159a 5-10)

Here, Aristotle, with philosophical precision, identifies a core difference within friendship: the demarcation between human and divine good. Because he is in- tensely interested in what it would mean to be human within the category of friendship, Aristotle leaves behind all fascination with the divine. Furthermore, because all thinking on friendship must stay within the realm of the possible, we must also remain within the domain of biology, and it is here that Derrida, pick-

Page 11: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 156

ing up on Aristotle's ironic lyric, locates the central tension within this passage: Perfect friendship destroys itself. It is contradictory in its very essence. On the one hand, in effect, one must want the greatest good for the friend-hence one wants him to become a god. But one cannot want that, one cannot want what would then be wanted for at least three reasons. (Politics 222)

First, friendship with a god would not be possible due to a remoteness that would exhaust the possibilities for friendship: The energy offriendship draws its force from presence or from proximity. If absence and remoteness do not destroy friendship, they attenuate or exhaust it, they enervate it. The proverb on this subject quoted by Aristotle indeed makes the point that for him, absence or remoteness is synonymous with silence: friends are separated when they cannot speak to one another. (Politics 222)

It is at this point that we are able to diagnose a cardinal distinction between Aristotle and Derrida, between more classical configurations of friendship and Derrida's necrophilia. Aristotle stays with the more conventional configurations of

friendship, while Derrida, not bound by such overt constraints of the sentient, moves into the poetic mysteries of necrophilia. For Aristotle, "friendship can still remain even when much is taken away, but when one partner is quite separated from the other, as in the case of divinity, it can remain no longer" (1 159a 25). For Derrida, the physical absence of a friend-in another place, or even in death- does not stop the beloved from presencing himself in a type of de-distanced

proximity: the miracle of memory that raises the dead (or gods) to life. Second, in Derrida's reading of Aristotle we are prohibited from violating the

natural order; namely, we must love the Other as they naturally are in their hu- man nature. Friendship is a distinctive feature of human finitude, and, as such, the deification of a man lies outside the purview of this kind of relationship.

Third, the gods have no need of friendship. The self-sufficiency of a deity- albeit in terms of absolute being or knowledge-has no need to go outside of itself. In contrast, philia demands that thought go outside of itself: this is why human friendship, as a finite fraternity, is friendship par excellence. The gaze of

friendship is continually directed towards the finitude of the Other. Thus, Aristotle confirms the following: Friendship is present to the extent that men share something in common, for that is also the extent to which they share a view of what is just. And the proverb "friends hold in common what they have" is correct, for friendship consists in community. (1159a 25)

Indeed, philia, in its originary Greek construction, was thought to constitute a bond that held the members of any association together, whether that associa- tion be natural or conventional: it was primarily inter-subjective. This idea of philia, the idea of having something in common, approaches the conception of concord. The proximity of these two notions likely underlies the Homeric adage when two

go together, or, more alluringly, Derrida's fragmented saying, "He who accompa- nies me" (see, especially, Politics 171-93).

This deconstructed fraternity-this inspirited philia-is characterized by a soli- darity that is achieved in soul-sharing. In keeping with ghosts and their texts, Derrida, in an obscure footnote, quotes a passage from the Eudemian Ethics (7.1240b 2-15), a ghostlike text whose authorship has often been questioned: Further, we say about friendship such things as that friendship is equality, and true friends have but a single soul. All such phrases point back to the single individual; for a man wishes good to himself in this fashion. [. . .] And wishing the existence above all of the friend, living with him, sharing his

Page 12: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/ 157

joy and his grief, unity of soul with the friend, the impossibility of even living without one another, and the dying together are characteristic of a single individual. (Politics n 5 190)

This speaks to us of a life together that, through phenomenology, witnesses the

compression of two souls into the space of one. True friends, then, have but a single soul, and it is by dwelling in this intersubjective space that the shared dynamics of joy, grief, and a life together become possible. But this inevitably leads to the problem of locating the exact place of subjectivity. In Derrida's words, "But how is this topology of habitat in friendship to be thought? 'What is a friend?'

Response: 'one soul in twin bodies"' (Politics 177). If we agree with Derrida and Aristotle on this provisional, if not historical, definition of intersubjectivity, then we find that the dispossession that surfaces to consciousness within this configu- ration of intersubjectivity succumbs to an uncanny unhomeliness: A friend, having more than one place [twin bodies], would never have a place of his own. He could never count on the sleep or nourishment of the economic intimacy of some "home." The body of the friend, his body proper, could always become the body of the other. This other body could live in his body proper like a guest, a visitor, a traveler, a temporary occupant, Friendship would be unheimlich. How would unheimlich, uncanny, translate into Greek? Why not translate it by atopos: outside of all place or placeless, without family or familiarity, outside of self, expatriate, extra[-] ordinary, extravagant, absurd or mad, weird, unsuitable, strange, but also "a stranger to." (Politics 178)

With this unhomeliness comes the demand that the subject reside outside of itself. Outside of allplace. Unsuitable. We are always in the place of the Other, and, as such, feel the impending demand that we must always move within a dialectics of hos- pitality. I am outside of myself We are always a guest, or we are always encountering a guest. This is the fundamental posturing that will contour Derrida's postdecon- structive (inter) subjectivity. We host, and we are hosted-our place is always the place of the Other. We never feel at home when we are at home-like coming home as an adult after many years away. This is likewise the meaning of Levinas's being that empties itself of its Being.

With Derrida, then, singularity is displaced into duplicity. the one soul half- twinned into two bodies. This absolute intercommunity of souls problematizes the impending separation that death will enact. The promise of finitude is the promise of a tear, of one soul being ripped in half, resulting in a death trauma, the act of death, for both lover and beloved.

Augustine knew something of the trauma of this half-souled separation, and it is here that we will pause to consider a meditation of Book 4 of the Confessions. Augustine crosses the folds of history to presence himself, inviting us into his economy of tears for a departed friend. Augustine is seized by what Derrida glosses as a double horror, That of surviving and not surviving, of surviving with half his soul amputated-the ineluctable arithmetical consequence of the Aristotelian axiom-but also that of not surviving, that is, of perhaps (forte) not keeping within himself, in what is left of self, at least a little of the beloved. (Politics 186)

This double terror leads Augustine to a haunting question: Do we survive for ourselves or for the Other in us? The union of friendship, especially after death, is a necro-magnetism that pulls us into the still warm grave of the friend: it pulls us towards the other half of ourselves. We enter a fraternity with the grave, and we covenant with the inevitable destiny of rejoining our friend, and ourselves. Augus- tine, steeped in the deep interiority of a half-souled suspension, pauses and re-

Page 13: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 158

calls (re-members) for us his act of mourning: But there had sprung up in me some kind of feeling, too, contrary to this, for both exceedingly wearisome was it to me to live and dreadful to die. I suppose, the more I loved him, so much the more did I hate and fear, as a most cruel enemy, that death which had robbed me of him ... For I was astonished that other mortals lived, since he whom I loved, as if he would never die, was dead; and I wondered still more that I, who was to him a second self, could live when he was dead. Well did one say of his friend, "Thou half of my soul," for I felt that my soul and his soul were but one soul in two bodies; and, consequently, my life was a horror to me, because I would not live in half. And therefore, perchance, was I afraid to die, lest he should die wholly whom I had so greatly loved. (4.6.11)

I would not live in half Torn asunder. Divided. Augustine enters into an abyssal calculation: does he survive for himself or for the one for whom he is in mourn-

ing. The asymmetrical density of this decision weighs heavily upon Augustine: "for self or for the other, for the other in self, in a narcissism which is never related to itself except in the mourning of the other.., the other's survival in self" (Derrida, Politics 187). The Other survives in me through an absence. This is the unalterable asymmetry that calls me into a continual stream of questioning. This, for Augustine, is the "relation of friendship to originary finitude and the

question of sur-vivance" (Critchley 270). Perhaps this is what Augustine is trying to articulate a little later when he says that "sweetness turned into bitterness, and

upon the loss of the life of the dying, the death of the living" (4.9.14), or, in Derrida's words, "This is why we mourn their death ... and life becomes a living death because a friend is lost" (Politics 187).

But in the midst of this loss, there is an advent; there is a coming of the Other. It

begins in a speaking to the one who is no longer here. This address, this speaking -a hospitality for the dead-welcomes the Other to be present for me. Derrida continues: I presuppose his presence, if only at the end of my sentence, on the other end of the line, .... at the intentional pole of my allocution ... But in another respect, my very sentence simultaneously puts him at a distance or retards his arrival, since it must always ask or presuppose the question "are you there?" (Politics 173)

In this instance, although the address objectifies the Other, the appeal to a presence nonetheless invokes his advent. The Other is made to come, to be welcomed, so that his orphan soul may rejoin, if only for an instant, the living part of him in whom he survives. But this appeal to the Other, this hospitality of the dead, is a

gesture yet to come, in an ad-vent, an appearing. Consistent with Derrida's herme- neutic of suspicion is the conception that within every advent is a deference, which clears a space for Derrida's secularized eschaton of a democracy always yet to come. This is the fundamental undoing that accompanies every facet of Derrida's

thought (see Politics 174). With this move, Derrida takes flight from the particu- lar intimacies of a necro-memoria into the abstract fascinations of deconstruction. In one fell swoop, we have moved from the highly personalized localities of the dead Other to a globally deconstructed eschatological politics, from the messi- ness of finding intersubjectivity in the death of the Other to a metaphysics of the political eschaton. It is in this vein that Derrida still appeals to a Nietzschean futurity-indeed, perhaps to a syncretism between Neitszche and a deconstructed Judaic eschatology-of a democratization to come in a series of eternal returns.

Page 14: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/159

We will more fully entertain the possible connections between a Nietzschean nihilism and a deconstructedJudaic repossession of the land, after the death of God, when we consider the particularities of the decision, and of the decision's migration outward into the public realm in terms of the "New International." But we must first turn from Derrida's metaphysic to The Instant of My Death, Blanchot's three-page meditation, which inspired a short philosophical novella on the part of Derrida. There is a mirroring effect that occurs between Blanchot's short meditation on death and the passivity of the decision that Levinas, Derrida, and Critchley want more fully to articulate. The texture of the decision, and this is the quandary that Augustine faced, will take us into the hiatus of a delayed contingency: "One thus finds oneself in a fatal and double impossibility: the im-

possibility of deciding, but the impossibility of remaining [demeurer] in the unde- cidable" (Derrida, Demeure 16). For Augustine, it is the decision as to Who is to survive, for Blanchot it is the question Why Me? There remained, however, at the moment when the shooting was no longer but to come, the feeling of lightness that I would not know how to translate: freed from life? The infinite opening up? Nei- ther happiness, nor unhappiness. Nor the absence of fear and perhaps already the step beyond. I know, I imagine that this unanalyzable feeling changed what there remained for him of existence. As if the death outside of him could only hence forth collide with the death in him. "I am alive." "No, you are dead." (9)

For Blanchot the step beyond betrays to us the ultimate texture of the instant of death: an instant that is always coming and yet never comes. This can be artic- ulated as a posturing before our finitude, and even greater than that, before our impending graveside. To dwell in the instant of death is to escape from the vul- gar conception of time that Heidegger spurned. The measure of time fades away and is reabsorbed into the phenomenology of the moment. 'All that remains is the feeling of lightness that is death itself or, to put it more precisely, the instant of my death henceforth always in abeyance" (Blanchot 11). Derrida glosses thus: I am dead, or I will be dead in an instant, or an instant ago I was going to be dead. Someone intends to speak, to speak to us, not only of his death, but of his death in the sense of the Latin, de, in the sense of from his death ... from my death, from the place and from the taking place, better yet, from the having-taken-place, already of my death. (Demeure 45)

We must not think of the instant in terms of the measurement of time. The instant, rather, is a way of being before a trauma, a tragedy, or even more profoundly, death. The instant possesses an immemorial elasticity that defies quantitative diagnosis.

With Blanchot, there is a remembering-of a young man perhaps-and the infinite density of a moment. The Germans (vanquished Visigoths) were retreat- ing homeward away from the pursuing Allies. A knock ushers in an instant, an indescribable duration, which would warp time and place into a spinning vortex. One man, in a family of women, proceeds, almost priest-like, to take his place before the firing squad. His pace, increments of half-lives, a denial of his execu- tion, is a vindication of his innocence. Men are shouting (in French, German, Russian?). In the midst of this immeasurable density, he experiences "a light- ness, a sort of beatitude" (5): the death of death? I am already dead, therefore I am immortal. Hence, he is bound to death in an inescapable friendship. Butjust "at that instant, an abrupt return to the world" (5): comrades appear on the

Page 15: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 160

horizon-on the horizon of death-to deliver the young man. The firing squad stands, frozen in formation, "prepared to remain, thus in an immobility that arrested time" (5). Next, in a fleeting moment the young man was dismissed and released from his covenant with death. He moved, with a sense of lightness, and fled to a distant forest where he regained a sense of the real. He moved within the space of a surreal imaging, a movement extended, as he sat, absorbing the

magnitude of what had just taken place. He lingers now, in death, before death, indeed, on the other side of death.

A substitution has occurred, but not the one that the young man has thought: "Three young men, sons of farmers ... had been slaughtered" (7). The termina- tion of the instant is followed by an impenetrable question: Why me? Released from death only to embrace death more fully. Why me? The illogic of tragedy: "Strangers to all combat whose only fault was their youth" (7). And now the recon- ciliation-life on the other side of the instant. Some instants can last a whole life- time: Why me? What follows is the torment of a mis-placed injustice: "There remained, however, at the moment when the shooting was no longer to come, the feeling of lightness that I would not know how to translate: freedom from life? The infinite opening up?" (7).

This is the other side, the infinite opening up, freed from life to embrace death. His confession, like his existence, is mixed, confused. "I am alive. No, you are dead" (9). He is living a borrowed life, a haunted life, a life no longer his- he lingers in a debt he could never pay. The demand of the Other in me. He relin-

quishes his right to subjectivity and enters an infinite deference: The Other in me. He now lives to find himself in others-dwelling in an intersubjectivity: "All that remains is the feeling of lightness that is death itself, or, to put it more precisely, the instant of my death, always in abeyance" (11).

All of the most fundamental insights of this narrative are imploded into the moment of the decision that experiences an eternal deference. To understand this more vividly, we must enter the central labyrinthine confusion of the instant

whereby a great exchange takes place: three young men's lives for Blanchot's. "I am alive, No you are dead." The unexpected substitution fractures our subjectiv- ity.6 I am living a borrowed life. This is the theater of the decision. Dreamlike and surreal, the infinity of the Other comes upon us and we enter into play, always deferred, infinitely perfectible. The decision does not originate within us, but rather circumvents our own subjectivity. It apprehends us in utter astonishment, takes us hostage, and invites us into an eternal hospitality that contours all of the

significant structures of our subjectivity. There is no surviving on the other side of the instant: modern subjectivity expires. The decision is an indescribable mag- nitude: it almost requires everything of us and then lets us off the hook to live in

6 Our subjectivity becomes a split infinitive, a divided subjectivity. I am two witnesses. I am only half myself and my subjectivity is delayed: "One of the two says to the other, 'I am alive,' and would thus be the one who has survived. But it is the other, the one who has survived, who responds to him: 'No you are dead.' And this is the colloquium, this is the dialogue between two witnesses, who are, moreover [au demeurant], the same, alive and dead, living-dead, and both of whom in abidance [en demourance] claim or allege that one is alive, the other dead, as if life went only to an I and death to a you" (Derrida, Politics 97). We experience our being-toward-death as a fissure that opens us up onto the infinity of the Other.

Page 16: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/161

the vacuum of an insatiable hospitality. We now look for ourselves in others and others within ourselves. But this decision is also accompanied with an impend- ing sense of injustice that obligates us to the alterity within us: The decision is not something taken by a subject, but rather the subject (insofar as one can still

employ this word post-deconstructively) is taken by the decision that is made without its volition. In this sense, the moment of the decision is the subject's relation to an alterity within itself, something which corresponds to the structure of the Lbvinasian subject. (Critchley 263)

4. The Nature of the Decision and the New International

In an unpublished lecture delivered at Green College in Vancouver, British Columbia, on 11 April, 2000, Simon Critchley suggested that the way ahead for

conceiving of an ethical self was a postdeconstructive subjectivity, echoing Levinas's formulation of substitution as the phenomenological thrust "to found ethical sub-

jectivity in sensibility and to describe sensibility as a proximity to the other, a

proximity whose basis is found in what Levinas calls substitution." In Ethics, Poli- tics, Subjectivity, Critchley describes substitution as "the deep structure of subjec- tive experience... structured in a relation of responsibility or responsivity to the other" (64). Ethics, in this way, is a moment of self-negation, borne out of a desire for the other that can in no way be reduced to a recovery of the self (65).

Speaking more specifically to the question of a postdeconstructive subjectivity, Critchley cites Jacques Derrida as the first to use the term "postdeconstructive" to describe new determinations of subjectivity that must come only after feelings of duty. Critchley's thesis in his book thus becomes clear: "My claim here is that the Levinasian account of subjectivity as responsibility to the other provides the framework for the kind of new determination of the 'subject' by Derrida" (71). Thus, a postdeconstructive subjectivity moves beyond the self's autonomous

grounding as a self to Levinas's formulation of the self as a substitution towards the responsibility of the Other.

On Levinas's account, it is the theological notion of expiation that provides possibilities for thinking about this new determination of subjectivity. Levinas de- theologizes the origin and content of expiation while allowing the general im- port of the word to remain and inform the richness of his thought. Speaking of the origins of this word expiation, Levinas problematizes the two streams of confluence that flow together to provide this word with its robust magnitude: On the one hand, the problem of the Man-God includes the idea of a self-inflicted humiliation on the part of the Supreme Being, of a descent of the Creator to the level of the Creature; that is to say, an absorption of the most active activity into the most passive passivity. On the other hand the

problem includes, as if brought about by this passivity pushed to its ultimate degree in the Passion, the idea of expiation for others, that is, of a substitution. The identical par excellence, the noninterchangeable, the unique par excellence, would be substitution itself. (EntreNous53-54)

More than a new determination of the subject, this construal of substitution emerges as almost a complete denial of the subject by suggesting that the self is perpetually suspended toward the Other in an ongoing self-negation. The sense that we have of ourselves, and this is the lie of the Enlightenment, is really the demand of the Other residing within us, calling us outside of ourselves:

Page 17: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 162

The passive decision, condition of the event, is always in me, structurally, an other decision, a ren- dering decision as the decision of the other. Of the absolutely other in me, of the other as the absolute who decides of me in me. (Critchley 263)

The only possible critique of this position, following Iris Murdoch, is that

Critchley's point is truer than he (or Derrida) could ever have imagined: when the "crisis" finally arrives the business of deciding is mostly over. Why is this? Because the texture of the ethical life features an ongoing registry, almost unnoticeable, where smaller, insignificant decisions build up into the higher emergences of the ethical life; the moral life is a web of existential affirmations that are spun together to form a nonintentional consciousness. Murdoch's private intention is

really a Levinasian non-intention. But if this designation of self seems to annihilate subjectivity completely, L 6vinas

reminds us that it was the anti-essentialism of modernism that cleared a space for the self-emptying subject: Modern antihumanism, denying the primacy of the person, an end in itself, in being, consequently seeking that meaning in a pure and simple configuration of elements, may have left a place for subjectivity as substitution. It is not that the self is just a being endowed with certain qualities called moral, which it would bear as attributes. It is the infinite passivity or passion or patience of the me- its self-the exceptional uniqueness to which it is reduced that is that incessant event of substitu- tion, the fact for being of emptying itself of its being. (Entre Nous 59)

It is within this vacuum that Levinas suggests a reconstruction of subjectivity that resides in the demand of the Other. Thus, when considering Heidegger's notion of Dasein, Levinas asks whether "the Da of my Dasein is not already the usurpa- tion of someone's place?" (Entre Nous 148). We are not even at home in our own

place, our own being; the Da of our Dasein may prove to be, on Levinas's account, the high-jacked subjectivity of someone else. And so the inevitable question: what

justifies my occupying my place, this place, as a self? Why Me?

Just as Heidegger turned Descartes' fundamental maxim against him,7 so Levinas turns Heidegger's Dasein into a question, indeed, a questioning. "Dasein in Heidegger is never hungry" (Totality 134), Levinas argues, because Dasein is not human enough to feel its own impinging presence in the place of the Other, and the Heideggerian subject dis-places (usurps) the position of the Other. For

L6vinas, our relation to the Other, like our relation to the world, is not ontologi- cal: "Position, absolutely without transcendence, does not resemble the compre- hension of the world by the Heideggerian Da. It is not a care for Being, nor a relation with existents, nor even a negation of the world, but its accessibility in

enjoyment" (Totality 138). "Enjoyment":' for L6vinas, is another word for what occurs within the space of proximity to the Other, that is, when one encounters the face of the Other.

In his Vancouver lecture, Simon Critchley attempts to imagine what it would

mean for this kind of subject to "get on" in the real world by talking about the hyper-contingency of the decision. He posits that each decision is elicited as a singularity via the relentless demand of the Other. That is to say, the decision is

7 Descartes' fundamental fascination concerned [the] thinking [the cogito of the subject],whereas Heidegger, in antithesis, emphasizes being [the sum of the subject]. Levinas, in one ironic stroke that paralyzes Heidegger, questions whether the being-there of Heidegger's Dasein isn't really the expropriation of someone else's locale.

Page 18: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/ 163

conjured by the demand that the Other places upon me, or, in other words, the material particularity of each decision, as a spontaneous ethical enactment, hinges upon the ineffable universal ephiphany of the revelation of the Other within me. This revelation is not imparted from outside the subject, nor from another world, but its demand is universal inasmuch as one human can begin to recognize an- other human being's presence, and possibly, suffering. Thus, for Critchley, true ethical decisions can only occur when brought face-to-face within the proximity of the Other. The situational contingency of this kind of decisionism deconstructs

any modernist notions of what it would mean to be political, or even how one would legislate such ethical activity.

On the basis of this account of the decision, Critchley argues for a non-state based democratization, or, to put it differently, a globally deconstructed politics. The rearticulation of the decision-in its deconstuctionist algorithm-becomes the link between Derrida's conception of friendship and Critchley's political de- cision. This decision, to be rethought outside of the old orthodoxy ofvoluntarism, springs from a new formulation of subjectivity: "This concept of friendship ... cuts across the public-private distinction, or the division between friendship and camaraderie, whilst informing both dimensions" (Critchley, Ethics 267).

For Critchley (as it is for Derrida), the political finds its originary genesis in the hypercontingency of the moment of the decision; in this way, the political is an emergent property springing from the energy of deciding. But Derrida's view of the political does not concern itself with the political subject of Western liber- alism. His is a fascination with the human yet to come, indeed, a neohumanism or, more radically, an unconditional hospitality. Hospitality can be thought of as

being put into the place of a radical reversal where the "Da" of my Dasein comes under questioning: the hospitality-to come-suspends itself toward the Other -the Other in me-in utter subjective dis-place-ment. Thus the imagined link be- tween the decision and hospitality is made apparent in the moment when I must decide to give myself up, must decide to become a hostage to the Other, realizing that my place, my being here, has already become the site of disenfranchisment of an Other. I must decide against myself andfor the one for whom my being is always already a dislocation. This is the act of granting asylum to the accused, relief to the afflicted, homeland to the foreigner. This is how the revelation of the de- mand of the Other comes to me in the form of a decision, in the form of a face and of a hospitality yet to come.

We remember with Critchley that the responsibility of ethical involvement un-

dergoes continual renovation; that is, the risk of making decisions is taken in the absence of normativity. In other words, politics is found in the face of the Other and in the unanticipated apprehension of such a face. Ethics is always a surprise. Owing to the constant performance of the decision, Critchley holds that his ap- plied Levinasian ethic does not collapse into a "vapid formalism" or an "empty universalism" (275). Rather, it is the indeterminacy of the passage from ethics to politics that insures that the political decision is inherently destabilized and there- fore always a singular response made over against the manifold difference of the context in which one finds oneself. In this way politics, and the ethics from which it issues, is always a fresh encounter with the Other in terms of the decision. This

Page 19: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 164

instability, the singular context in which the decision takes place, shelters the

possibility of any one ethical practice or custom setting itself up as a totality. This

singular context can be thought of in terms of a spatial encounter with the Other, one that guards against the myopic particularities of the decision. The labor to harmonize the demand with the decision mirrors a struggle that finds its locus in medieval epistemology: the problem of universals, of the one and the many.

However, if we stay with only the decision, like Heidegger we will stay with a form of the subject-postdeconstructive or not-and, whether we like it or not, will bear the mark of the last metaphysician. Dasein has been sentenced-he, or rather it, must die the death toward the Other.8 Instead, we must move outward, past the intimate boundaries between the one and the Other and explore the

dangerous but interesting territory of political community. As we move towards a discussion of politics, we reaffirm the Levinasian maxim

that politics is ultimately deduced from ethics. We also understand that ethics is

thought of in terms of the demand of the Other, or as an immanent ethic that comes to us in the face of the Other and, as such, is prior to all ontology. The infinite demand of the Other is actualized in terms of the decision, and decon- structive polity is nothing more than the singularity of each new decision, issu-

ing, not from the Kantian subject, but from the residual presence of the Other in us, from our everyday dealings with the particularity of the world. Thus, for

Critchley, ethical response finds its genesis in the demand of the Other and through the richness of a shared space and the singular finite context which gathers around the decision. In other words, ethics is found in the everyday matrix of the world, for the L6vinasian Other is not a matter to be thought but a face to behold. Fit-

tingly, the "singularity of the context" provides the detail for ethical particular- ization, while the demand of the Other remains the locus of universal demand. In this way, Levinasian ethics is essentially spatial with reference to its framing of both demand and decision. The decision is not merely an artifact of human

subjectivity; indeed, it receives its real thrust from the demand of the Other. This makes the decision a dynamic and unique extension, or mediation, of the phe- nomenological space between the ethical subject and the Levinasian Other that in an advent demanding hospitality comes to me and elicits my ethical response. Because of this dynamic, every ethical decision is a new norm, though it is diffi- cult at times to know how Critchley understands its possible function as a norm of universal criterion. Perhaps his emphasis on the impossibility of normativity within the ethical encounter illustrates how, for Critchley, the universal criterion is nothing else but the infinite demand of the Other, which calls forth and pro- vokes in me the moment of political decision. Thus, "the other's decision is made in me, a decision made but with regard to which I am passive" (276).

Critchley maintains that with each new decision a new norm is enacted in

response to the utter singularity of the existential setting within which the ethi-

8 Though dying a death toward the Other might be reminiscent (and perhaps a reactivation) of a sacrificial structure (as evinced in such thinkers as Girard and Calasso), this death toward the Other and its necessity is not entirely separate from Levinas's debt toJudaism, and his own sacrificial debt to National Socialism: he was detained in a Nazi labor camp for five years during the Second World War. It is also an issue I will take up with Derrida and Critchley in their "Messianic-Cleansing" of the Judaic impulse within Levinas's ethical philosophy.

Page 20: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/165

cal subject encounters the insatiable demand of the Levinasian Other (277). That every decision is a leap of faith, a singular political invention, overwrites the criterion of ethical normativity with the criterion of performance. Against ethi- cists of every Kantian stripe, Critchley's L6vinasian ethic is not a response by a

subject to an ineffable moral law; rather, the contingency of the political deci- sion displays a performative instability resisting any theoretical tendencies that would otherwise render it a totalizing ontology.

For Critchley, the quality of the decision closely mirrors the ethical experience of which it is a hegemonization. If the passage from ethics to politics were to be

thought of in terms of the decision, then Critchley's challenge is "to think the decision outside of its traditionally voluntaristic and 'decisionistic' determina- tions," for that would only affirm the consciousness of the liberal subject (262). Instead, Critchley wants to think the decision as passive or unconscious: "the decision is not something taken by a subject, but rather the subject (in so far as one can still employ this word postdeconstructively) is taken by the decision that is made without its volition" (263). That is, the decision is the momentary experi- ence of an alterity within me, which decides me and which then vanishes away leav-

ing no transcendental guarantees that might found a normative ethic. Levinasian ethics-what Derrida calls la democratie a' venir-is jarring, destablizing, still al- ways to come. Politics must be continually performed, "a responsible decision must be taken-here and now, again and again" (275), and the comfort and certitude of any transcendental ethical guarantees is alleviated by the ceaseless demand for political invention: Derrida emphasizes how the very indeterminacy of the passage from ethics to politics entails that the taking of a political decision must be a response to the utter singularity of a particular and inexhaustible context. The infinite ethical demand of deconstruction arises as a response to a sin- gular context and calls forth the invention of a political decision. Politics itself can here be thought of as the art of response to the singular demand of the other, a demand that arises in a particular context-

although the infinite demand cannot simply be reduced to its context-and calls for political inven- tion, for creation. (276)

Because every momentary performance of the political-what Derrida has called the "madness" of the decision-is always already a return to an originary en- counter with the Other, politics cannot be thought of as apart from aesthetics: it is always a performance of the irreducible trace of the LUvinasian Other. The radical contingency of the decision-its mad, unceasing, inexhaustible perfection -calls for the continual invention and artistry of new norms and rules, insur- ing that no ethic, polity, or form of democratization ever establish itself as a

totality. Derridean politicization continually undermines itself: it enacts an unceas- ing deconstruction.

The decision, writ large throughout the public realm, becomes the radical possibility for Derrida's and Critchley's "New International"-a world-wide prac- tice of an inexhaustible number of transnational decisions that are enacted and which ultimately build up into the larger and more significant movement of a globally deconstructed politics that denies the sovereignty of nation states while nonetheless working within these nation states.

With this concept Critchley and Derrida both acknowledge the structural form of Levinas's ethics (of the other, for them always in the lower case) and at the

Page 21: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE / 166

same time deconstruct hisJewish political context (his Messianic Zionism). That is, they accept "the formal notion of the ethical relation to the other in Levinas- what Derrida calls here and elsewhere a 'structural' or 'apriori' notion of the messianic-while refusing the specific political content that Levinasian ethics seem to entail, namely the vexed question of Levinas' Zionism" (Critchley 278). A great exchange thus takes place: Levinas's Zionism for Critchley's and Derrida's Neo- Marxism. Critchley and Derrida negate the political/ideological-even the theo-

logical-content of Levinas's work in order to shelter their secular rendition of the "New International" from what they have termed the "political fate" of his ethical philosophy, namely, the vexed question of Levinas's Zionism. In their hands, the "New International" becomes a clinically sterile humanitarian politics, one that has its impulse outside of nation states and yet cuts itself off from one of its most striking possibilities.

Consistent with their Marxism, there can be no politics without an enemy, no friend without a foe. In Marx's case the foe is bourgeois Christianity; in Derrida's and Critchley's it is liberal humanism in the form of capitalist nation states. The

enemy of the "New International" proves to be any nationalism that endeavors to totalize-to hold that justice can be incarnated within the ethnic or geograph- ical borders of some state, nation, or tribe. On this account, modern liberal pol- ity (democracy) is a form of foundationalism: it affirms an essential subject and an essential view of the nation state.

As a result, this nonfoundational politics, issuing from a decentered subjectiv- ity (externalized in the form of the postdeconstructive decision), takes its form as a democracy to come-a sort of secular Nietzschean eschaton, defined as the radical immanence of the political rather than an opening onto a future utopia. The democracy to come is coming and is always arriving-it is the arrival of the

arriving--and because of this is inherently unstable and therefore antagonistic to any totalizing ideologies. This is Critchley's deterritorialized democritization: a democracy to come that works outside the state but never against the state. It is "the democracy to come" not in terms of futurity, but in terms of instability; that is, it is structurally performative. The goal, then, of this ethical anarchism is not to function without the state, but to put pressure on the state. "Ethical anarchism" resists political foundationalism: it resists setting up one ideology (anarchy) in

place of another (nationalism).9 What, then, is the glue that holds the "New In- ternational" together? What is the ultimate (or penultimate) catalyst behind the thickness of the political decision, a phenomenon that is made to do the work of a metaphysic without itself being a metaphysic? This is not a question of what is behind the decision and, more profoundly, the face (and this is where their

thought leans most heavily upon the brilliance of Heideggerian disclosure), but of what is in the decision and, more interestingly, what is in the face. The en- chantment with humanity, through an encounter with the face of the Other, is the glue that holds the "New International" together beyond nation states-beyond even the hypercontingency of the decision. This is the essence of Critchley's uni- versal criterion: if there were no face, no demand of the Other, there would cer-

tainly be no decision. Enchantment with the Other is the condition of possibility

9 Except in the case of Levinas's displaced Judaism.

Page 22: Postdeconstructive necrophilia, by floyd dunphy

POSTDECONSTRUCTIVE NECROPHILIA/167

for the decision and hence of ethics for politics. The decision only comes after private intention-after the face of the Other has registered itself within our sub-

jectivity. This is the insight to which Iris Murdoch has so penetratingly drawn attention. And yet we must decide. Without decisions there would be no politics, only interesting speculation. This is the insight that finally led Simon Critchley to his hauntingly provocative avowal: "If ethics without politics is empty, then

politics without ethics is blind" (283). But is the price too high to pay for Critchley's formulation of subjectivity to get

a purchase on a "globally deconstructed politics"? His recasting of subjectivity, albeit in nonessentialized terms, still looks back to the voluntarism of Existential- ism. Does Critchley's postdeconstructive voluntarism still fall prey to Iris Murdoch's

critique of the Existentialists? Does the reduction of Critchley's ethical self to the decision only show up within the public margin? Is there room, and this is the idea that Murdoch wants to articulate, for the internal struggles that go on pri- vately? Is there really no politics without a decision? Does Critchley's view fall down as a soft form of utilitarianism, surrendering value (private intention) to the brute arena of fact (the decision)? Whatever the outcome of these questions, Critchley goes a long way towards making possible a postdeconstructive human- ism, perhaps even a neo-humanism: The subject is no longer the self-positing origin of the world; it is a hostage to the other. Humanism should not begin from the datum of the human being as an end-in-itself and the foundation for all knowledge, certainty, and value: rather, the humanity of the human is defined by its service to the other. Levinasian ethics is a humanism, but it is a humanism of the other being. (67)

If this holds, then perhaps we can also entertain discussions about the possibili- ties of ethics in a new light, one also sheltered from predictable conversations about morality and normativity. On this provisional nonfoundational account, Levinasian ethics may provide a way of getting on with others in the larger struc- tures that make up our political and ethical institutions.

University of British Columbia

Works Cited

Aristotle. Nichomachean Ethics. Trans. Martin Oswald. New York: Macmillan, 1962.

Augustine. Confessions. 1890. Trans. J.G. Pilkington. The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers 1. Ed. Phillip Schaff. Edinburgh: T. and T. Clark, 1994.

Blanchot, Maurice. The Instant of My Death. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994.

Critchley, Simon. Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity. London: Verso, 1999.

Derrida,Jacques. DemeureFiction and Testimony. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998. - . The Politics of Friendship. London: Verso, 1997.

Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings. San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1977. . Being and Time. 1927. Trans.J. Stambaugh. New York: SUNY, 1996.

LUvinas, Emmanuel. Entre Nous: Thinking of the Other. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998. -. Totality and Infinity. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press, 1969.

Murdoch, Iris. Existentialists and Mystics. New York: Penguin, 1999.