naturalised epistemology

21
8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 1/21 On the De-Naturalization of Epistemology Author(s): András Kertész Source: Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, Vol. 33, No. 2 (2002), pp. 269-288 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25171234 Accessed: 03/10/2009 05:52 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer . Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: silencia3

Post on 30-May-2018

237 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 1/21

On the De-Naturalization of EpistemologyAuthor(s): András KertészSource: Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, Vol. 33, No. 2 (2002), pp. 269-288Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25171234

Accessed: 03/10/2009 05:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal for General

Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 2/21

ON THE DE-NATURALIZATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY

ANDR?S KERT?SZ

SUMMARY. Starting from an overview of approaches to naturalized epistemology, the

paper shows, firstly, that Quine's programme yieldsa

sceptical paradox. This means that

Quine's attempt to defeat scepticism itself yieldsa rather strong argument for scepticism

and thus against his own programme of naturalized epistemology. Secondly, it is shown that

this paradox can be solved by anapproach called reflexive-heuristic naturalism. Finally,

the paper also raises some fundamental problems which the solution proposed has to leave

open.

Key words: hermeneutics, heuristics, naturalized epistemology, normativity

1. INTRODUCTION1

Although contemporary epistemological thought has been largely charac

terized by the rapid emergence of naturalized epistemology, it is very far

from being clear what relation the latter bears to traditional epistemology,

what its possibilities are, how far it can go in striving to 'replace' the latter,

what new questions it can raise, what its relationship to 'empirical science'

is etc. Thus, the present paper focuses on the following problem:

(P) What are the possibilities and limits of naturalized epistemology?

As an answer to this question the following thesis will be proposed:

(T) (a) Naturalized epistemology is susceptible to serious difficulties.

(b) These difficulties can be partly avoided if naturalized approachesare not conceived of as theories per se, but rather, as manifesta

tions of heuristics.

(c) Such heuristics reveal a new level ofepistemological thought,which is distinct both from traditional epistemology and current

approaches to naturalized epistemology.

Since the literature concerning naturalized epistemology is character

ized by the use of a very vague terminology, in this paper it will not be

^MJournal for General Philosophy of Science 33: 269-288, 2002.

^r^ ? 2003 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in theNetherlands.

Page 3: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 3/21

270 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

possible to explicate the basic concepts in a satisfactory manner, either.

Therefore, it is important to note that throughout this paper all terms will

be used in a preexplicative sense unless stated otherwise.2

2. FOUR VERSIONS OF NATURALISM

So as to provide a suitable starting point for the discussion of (T), let me

put forward some very simple background assumptions. One can make

sense of the problem (P) only if the main differences between traditional

and naturalized epistemology are first outlined:

(1) Traditional epistemology, which up to the last two or three decades

had dominated epistemological thought, can be characterized by the

following properties:

(a) It is a philosophical discipline.

(b) The way it reflects on 'scientific' inquiry presupposes certain a

priori assumptions concerning the nature of the criteria of ration

ality.

(c) It is normative, because on the basis of these criteria it evaluates

scientific knowledge as true or false, rational or irrational, justified

or not.

(d) It claims to be the only approach (i.e. 'first philosophy') which is

entitled to deal with the foundations of scientific knowledge.

(2) The main tenets of naturalized epistemologyare these:3

(a) Epistemology must not be aphilosophical discipline, but it should

apply 'scientific' methods.

(b) Accordingly, epistemology should proceed in an a posteriori man

ner.

(c) Epistemology is not a normative enterprise and its task is not to

evaluate the results of scientific inquiry but rather, it should strive

to describe and/or explain them.4

As a first approximation, the relationship between (1) and (2) can be statedas follows:

(3) (a) Naturalized epistemology claims to solve or to eliminate the prob

lems which traditional epistemology tackled on the basis of its

philosophical, normative, a priori foundations, by using the a pos

teriori, non-normative methods of 'science' itself,

(b) Accordingly, traditional epistemology should be 'replaced9 by nat

uralized

epistemology.

Page 4: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 4/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 271

Nevertheless, so as to avoid misrepresenting the situation, this very sim

plified picture should be exposed to an at least twofold differentiation. On

the one hand we should ask the question as to what ismeant by 'science'in (3)(a) that is, what should replace traditional epistemology. On the other

hand, it is anything but clear what itmeans to say that 'science', whatever it

may be, should 'replace' traditional epistemology as formulated in (3)(b).

Quine, in his seminal paper (Quine 1969a), seems to hold the view that

'science' should be interpreted in the sense of natural science:

"[...] epistemology,or

something like it, simply falls into placeas a

chapter of psychology

and hence of natural science. It studies a natural phenomenon, viz., aphysical human

subject." (Quine 1969a: 82-83; emphasis added.)

Accordingly, we obtain the following explication of (3)(a):

(4) (a) Naturalized epistemology claims to solve or to eliminate the prob

lems which traditional epistemology tackled on the basis of its

philosophical, normative, a priori foundations, by using the a pos

teriori, non-normative methods of natural science.

However, as Haack (1993) showed, Quine is inclined to allow a con

siderably weaker interpretion as well according to which 'science' must

not be restricted to 'natural science' but should involve any kind of inquiry

such as the social sciences, history, linguistics or even mathematics. See

for example the following illustrative quotation:

"What reality is like is the business of scientists, in the broadest sense, painstakingly to

surmise; and what there is, what is real, is part of that question. [...] The last arbiter is

so-called scientific method, however amorphous [...]. (Quine 1960: 22)

Haack denotes this secondintrepretation by

SCIENCE(Haack

1993:

339) which I shall adopt.5 Thus we receive the second explication of (3)(a)

(5) (a) Naturalized epistemology claims to solve or to eliminate the prob

lems which traditional epistemology tackled on the basis of its

philosophical, normative, a priori foundations, by using the a pos

teriori, non-normative methods of SCIENCE.

I shall label the viewrepresented by (4)(a) 'strong

naturalism' and the

one put in (5)(a) 'weak naturalism'.

What possibilities are there to render the term 'replace' in (3)(b)? The

answer that presents itself first is that traditional epistemology should be

eliminated completely. In this way Quine's famous claim according to

which "epistemology is only science self-applied" (Quine 1969b: 293)

means that traditional epistemology should be radically discarded and its

tasks should be carried out completely by 'science' (whatever the latter

means).Thus we obtain the

following explicationof

(3)(b):

Page 5: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 5/21

272 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

(6) (b) Traditional epistemology should be replaced completely.

However, Quine's writings are ambiguous with respect to the replace

ment of traditional epistemology as well: in particular, he also assumes

the continuity of 'science' (in whatever sense) and philosophy (see also

Haack 1993). Accordingly, the second interpretation of 'replace' is the

following:

(7) (b) Traditional epistemology should not be replaced completely.

Consequently, we obtain two versions of strong naturalism depending

on whether (4)(a) is combined with (6)(b) or (7)(b). Let me call stronginaturalism the set of theses {(4)(a), (6)(b)} and strong2 naturalism the set

{(4)(a), (7)(b)}.The two versions of weak naturalism present themselves in an analog

ous manner. If we combine (5)(a) with (6)(b), we get weak\ naturalism',

and ifwe combine (5)(a) with (7)(b), the result is 'weak2 naturalism'. This

very simple typologycan be summarized in Figure 1.

Versions of Parameter 1 : Paramater 2:

naturalism natural science as the only source complete replacement of

of naturalized epistemology traditional epistemology

strongi +

strong2 +

weakj-

+

weak2

Figure 1

Now, many arguments have been put forward against the assumptions

which we have just labelled strong naturalism and thus characterized. Due

to these well-known arguments, there seems to be considerable agreementon the untenability of strong naturalism.6 Their main effect is that they

question the plausibility of the value "+" of parameter 1 in Figure 1. Ac

cordingly, in the light of the literature, it is plausible to discard both strong

versions7 regardless of the value of parameter 2.

Since the arguments mentioned undermine value "+" of parameter 1,

they do not apply toweak naturalism. Accordingly, at present it seems to be

the case that the two weak versions of naturalism can be maintained. That

is, one of the main properties of naturalism is that it is SCIENTIFIC the

ories which may be the sources of the methods to be applied on the meta

scientific level for analyzing the nature of scientific knowledge. Therefore,

what ismissing is a careful evaluation of weak naturalism.

Page 6: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 6/21

ON THE DE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY273

In order to carry out this task, in the next section I shall try to show that

weaki naturalism leads to a difficulty whose consequences are not less

destructive than those of the strong versions and that the only remainingalternative isweaki naturalism. Accordingly, the following considerations

will focus on the value of parameter 2: I shall discuss the consequences

of the claim that traditional epistemology should be replaced by SCI

ENTIFIC approaches completely. As we have seen, the arguments which

Quine puts forward in favour of the complete replacement of traditional

epistemology and which result in the "+" value of parameter 2 apply-

due to the ambiguity of his use of the term 'science'-

both to strong i and

weaki naturalism. However, we have already discarded both strong ver

sions; that is, strongi naturalism as well. Thus it follows that, although our

conclusions will have to be inferred from the premises Quine formulated,

they should be relativized to weaki naturalism in spite of the fact that they

apply to the strongi version as well.

3. THE PARADOX OF NATURALIZED EPISTEMOLOGY

Quine's starting point is that

"Epistemology is concerned with the foundations of science." (Quine 1969a: 69; emphasis

added)

Accordingly, the central task of traditional epistemology is to show how

the certainity of the foundations of scientific knowledge can be maintained.

This means that the traditional epistemologist has to face the sceptic. Scep

tical arguments do not aim at showing that scientific claims are false but

they try to prove that one cannot know with certainty that they are not false.

Thus it is the rejection of sceptical arguments and the maintenance of the

certainty of scientific knowledge which traditional epistemology should be

primarily concerned with.

However, inQuine's view traditional epistemology failed exactly in this

respect: it could not refute the sceptic and will never be able to do so. He

supports this conclusion by referring to Hume's problem of induction:

'What then of [...] the justification of our knowledge of truths about nature? Here, Hume

despaired. [...] I do not see that we are farther along today than where Hume left us. The

Humean predicament is the human predicament." (Quine 1969a: 72; emphasis added)

What follows from this "desperate" situation is, according to Quine,

the untenability of traditional epistemology: the impossibility of justifica

tion of scientific knowledge, the impossibility of a "first philosophy", the

hopelessness of any attempt to validate the methods of scientific inquiry

on a philosophical basis. Consequently, even if epistemology is not to

Page 7: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 7/21

274 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

be given up entirely, it should be given up as a philosophical enterprise.

Traditional epistemology should, therefore, be 'replaced' by 'science' and

its task must not be justification, but rather, explanation of the nature and

origin of what is considered to be scientific knowledge by using 'scientific'

methods.

However, the argument which Quine puts forward in order to prove this

conclusion is of exactly the same philosophical nature which character

izes both scepticism and traditional epistemology. In particular, it rests on

the premise that Hume's thesis is basically correct and that accordingly,

induction cannot be justified. But Hume's thesis can neither be proved nor

falsified by 'scientific' means: the problem of induction is the paradigmatic

example of a philosophical quandary which is rooted in the assumption

that the justification of claims which one obtains making use of a certain

method, like induction, is important for our understanding of scientific

knowledge. Quine did not analyze this premise by 'scientific' means -

rather, he analyzed it philosophically. He didn't refer to any empirical

evidence which could support the claim that the consequences of Hume's

thesis can be avoided if epistemology is naturalized. As D. Shatz put it in a

very compelling way, his argument is simply "the argument from despair"

(Shatz 1993: 117). This means that Quine argues for the replacement of tra

ditional epistemology in the same way inwhich traditional epistemology is

used to argue. Consequently, his conclusion that traditional epistemology

should be discarded is valid exactly as long as traditional epistemology

exists. As can be easily seen, this boils down to a fundamental problem

which I shall call the paradox of naturalized epistemology'}

(8) Traditional epistemology can be 'replaced' by 'science' if the former

cannot be 'replaced' by the latter.

The construction of paradoxes is atypical sceptical strategy. Therefore,

Quine's attempt to defeat scepticism itself yieldsa rather strong argument

for scepticism and thus against his own programme of naturalized epistem

ology. The consequences of this paradox are, of course, fatal, for it renders

the elaboration of those versions of naturalized epistemology impossible

which presuppose the complete 'replacement' of traditional epistemology:

thus weaki naturalism as well. Therefore, what we have to show now is

how weak2 naturalism may provide a solution for the paradox.9

Page 8: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 8/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 275

4. A POSSIBLE SOLUTION TO THE PARADOX

4.1. The Heuristics of Reflexive Naturalism

The solution may rest on an observation of the way classic paradoxes

have been resolved. Tarski's and Russell's paradoxes and also others were

solved by the application of a two-step process. In the first step the domain

of the paradox which at the time of its formulation seemed to be unified

and undifferentiated was subdivided according to reasonable criteria into

certain subdomains: for instance, in the case of Tarski's paradox 'language'

was subdivided intoobject-

andmetalanguage,

and Russell introduced a

differentiation between sets of certain types. Then, in a second step, itwas

decided under what circumstances certain problematic categories which

wereoriginally responsible for the paradox at issue could be mapped onto

these subdomains, and in which cases such amapping is blocked. Accord

ingly, Tarski suggested that the category 'truth' must not appear in the

objectlanguage but rather, must be part of the metalanguage; and Russell

maintained that sets must not be their own elements or elements of sets of a

lower type. This mechanism consists in first making some differentiations,and then blocking certain mappings onto some of the subdomains differ

entiated in this way. The fact that such a techniquewas successfully used

for the resolution of classic paradoxes suggests that we should proceed in

an analogous way.10

The domain in which the paradox of naturalized epistemology arose is

'scientific' knowledge. Thus the first question to be answered is, according

to what criteria this domain may be subdivided. The simplest answer is to

suggest a vertical and a horizontal subdivision. Vertically we obtain at least

two levels, namely that of objectscientific knowledge and of metascientific

knowledge. Since any kind of 'scientific' knowledge is usually manifested

in theories,11 a horizontal subdivision will yield a series of theories on both

levels, i.e. objectscientific and metascientific theories.

All this may seem trivial; but if we go on to carry out the second step,

we may arrive at less trivial conclusions.

In particular, there may be many different relations between the the

ories we thus received. However, there seem to be three main groups of

relations which are relevant. They are rooted in Quine's idea of "science

self-applied" (Quine 1969b: 293) which I shall reconstruct here as the

thesis of reflexivity:

(9) The thesis of reflexivity: An approach to naturalized epistemology is

a theory developed on the objectscientific level which has been trans

ferred to the metascientific one so as to describe and/or explain ob

jectscientifictheories.

Page 9: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 9/21

276 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

I shall call the results of this procedure metatheories. Now, how can, on

the background of this basic thesis, the three groups of relations mentioned

be characterized and which mappings between them are to be blocked inwhich cases?

The first class includes relations between certain objectscientific the

ories and the very metatheories which we obtain by projecting the former

on the metascientific level. For example, from an objectscientific theory

Oi we get a metascientific theory MOi, that is, Oi->MOi; analogously,

02->M02 or 03->M03, and in general, On-^MOn. This class of rela

tions, whose elements will be denoted by "-V, I shall call the class of

naturalization-relations, because they exhibit the very idea according to

which naturalized theories of 'scientific' knowledge come into being. Of

course, not every objectscientific theory Oi can be transformed into a

metascientific theory MOi; for example, as recent debates show, there

are serious doubts whether computational approaches to 'scientific' know

ledge which are rooted in AI-research are workable.12 Therefore, it is

important to reveal under what circumstances the relation "->" is allowed

and under what conditions it has to be blocked.

The second class of relations rests on the fact that ametascientific the

ory established on the basis of the naturalization-relation serves to analyze

objectscientific knowledge. That is, it has to be applied to the investigation

of objectscientific theories, and the expected result of such anapplica

tion is the description and/or explanation of the way in which a particular

objectscientific theory works. Therefore, the class of relations between a

metascientific theory MOn and its object of investigation, which is an ob

jectscientific theory Oi,will be called the

application-relationand denoted

by MOn=tOi. There are many possible elements of this class imaginable;

for example, itmay be defined as A={MOi=tOi, MOi=t02, MOi=?03,

M03=}03, M03=40i, M03=t02 etc.}. When is the application-relation

blocked? Let us assume, for example, that Oi and O2 are objectscientific

theories. Let us also assume that Oi and O2 contradict each other along the

lines of Quine's thesis of the underdetermination of empirical theories by

evidence. Then, surely, though naturalization-relations like Oi-*MOi and

O2?^M02are

possible, neither of the application-relations MOi=302 andM02=?Oi is permitted, because both the meta- and the objecttheory make

empirical claims, and since they are incompatible they cannot do this sim

ultaneously without rendering the metascientific enterprise inconsistent.

As opposed to this, it is possible to apply MOi to Oi. Indeed, this kind of

self-application realizes one of the main aspects of naturalism: naturalized

epistemology is what Quine labelled as "science self-applied".

Page 10: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 10/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 277

Finally, the third class of relations results from the fact that a certain

problem Pi raised in a theory Oi belonging to a subdiscipline Di may be

solved by using information borrowed from a theory O2 belonging to a sub

discipline D2.1 shall call this relation between Oi and O2 constructivity:

O2 is constructive with respect to Oi because it contributes to the construc

tion of somethingnew in Oi, i.e the solution of problems. However, if we

transfer theories to the metascientific level according to the naturalization

relation, we get a special and very interesting subclass of constructivity

relations: since a metatheory MOn may investigate an objecttheory Om, a

constructive interaction is possible not only between theories belonging to

the same level, but also between those of different levels that is between

MOn and Om. Accordingly,ametatheory may be constructive with respect

to an objecttheory and this means that metascientific reflexion may con

tribute to the solution of objectscientific problems. In general the class of

the constructivity-relations may be illustrated as follows: K={{Oi?>02,

02?*03, Oi^03}, {MOi?*M03}, {MOi-MDi, MOi-M32, MO1-O3,

M03-^03, M03-^02, M03-^Oi}} where the symbol "?>" stands for

any kind of

level-preserving constructivity irrespective

of its direction and

"-^" denotes metascientific constructivity with respect to objectscientific

problem solutions. The crucial question is, of course, when the constructiv

ity relation is blocked. For example, it is straightforward that the relation

"?^" is blocked whenever the relation "=3" is blocked: if Oi and O2 are

incompatible and therefore MOi=K)2 and M02=*Oi are not permitted,

then also MOi^02 and M02-^Oi are blocked.

Thus we have carried out both steps mentioned above: we delimited

certain subareas of 'scientific'knowledge by inferring these

three classes

from the basic properties of naturalized epistemology and we illustrated

by the help of examples in which cases the relations discussed may be

blocked. At first sight, it seems to be the case that this really leads to the

resolution of the paradox of naturalized epistemology. Namely, due to the

fact that all the relations enumerated may be blocked in certain cases and,

as the examples mentioned show, they even must be blocked sometimes,

there is no metatheory MO\ which has the right to claim general validity.

The scope of any naturalized metatheory is necessarily restricted: somemetatheories will serve this purpose and others that purpose. This leads to a

very liberal rendering of the 'replacement' thesis: traditional epistemology

may be 'replaced' by some theory On whenever the relations On-+MOn,

MOn=iOn, MOn-^On are not blocked. But when they are blocked, tradi

tional epistemology may be retained and applied. Thus, neither naturalized

nor traditional epistemology are exclusive. If we give up the exclusiveness

of naturalized epistemology, the paradox does not arise.

Page 11: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 11/21

278 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

Superficially, this seems to be a straightforward solution of the paradox,

indeed. But is it really a solution? Unfortunately, the answer is: no.

It is easy to see why. We have, in order to capture the relations men

tioned and to reveal which of them are blocked in which cases, outlined a

set of statements about the relationship between object- and metatheories.

This relationship can, of course, be grasped only if this set of statements is

available, which, in turn, is nothing but ametametatheory itself- therefore,

there is no avoiding the same infinite regress which we have met earlier.

Consequently, the adoption of the technique used for the resolution of

classic paradoxes does not work with respect to the paradox of naturalized

epistemology.

The reason for the failure is obviously the fact that what we have been

after so far were metatheories-

as long as we want to develop theories

of 'scientific' knowledge, the very same difficulty will present itself. For

this reason we should look for something else-

something which does not

require the multiplication of levels on which the descriptions and explan

ations of the phenomena investigated are accessible. There exists such a

thing: namely,

heuristics. What are heuristics and how can

they

avoid the

infinite regress?

As a first approximation, heuristics are sets of very simple rules of

thumb which are used tofind the solution to problems. As is well-known,

algorithms also serve the same purpose. However, there is an essential dif

ference between heuristics and algorithms: whereas algorithms lead to the

solution of the given problem with certainty, heuristics do not guarantee

that the solution isfound. The only thing heuristics can do is to provide

provisionally a strategy, a toolor

a trickor an

idea or anything like thatwhich, among local conditions, possibly but not necessarily may result in

a solution.

Our claim is that if we aim at developing metascientific heuristics in

stead of looking for aparticular metascientific theory, then no infinite

regress emerges and also the paradox of naturalized epistemology can be

avoided. This claim is justified by the fact that heuristics, as just men

tioned, consist of rules. Rule following is, however, a practice. This means

that rules, unlike theories or sets of statements, work even ifwe are not in a

position to describe and/or explain them on the metalevel. Of course, they

may be described or explained; but this is no precondition for their applic

ation. We know this property of rules from the way language works: it is

only natural that one can use the rules of a language perfectly well without

being able to describe these rules. Therefore, if we identify naturalized

epistemology not with a particular metatheory but handle it as heuristics,

then we are not forced tomultiply the levels of description.

Page 12: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 12/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 279

Consequently, in addition to carrying out the two steps exemplified by

the resolution of classic paradoxes we have to develop metascientific heur

istics. This boils down straightforwardly to the fact that the three classesof relations we delimited above correspond to the steps of a metascientific

heuristics. I shall call this the heuristics of reflexive naturalism (which

will be referred to as (HRN)): these heuristics are both naturalistic and

reflexive, because they realize the idea of "science self-applied". So we

get the following simple heuristics:

(HRN) (a) Rule 1 (naturalization): An objectscientific theory Oi is trans

ferred to the metascientific level, the result of which is a 'nat

uralized' metascientific theory MOi. In which cases a given

objectscientific theory can be transferred in this way, and in

which cases it cannot, is a question which needs careful ana

lysis. On the basis of this analysis, one should decide whether,

and if so, to what extent the naturalization relation is to be

blocked.

(b) Rule 2 (application): As a result of the successful realization

of rule 1, the properties ofan

objectscientific theory On maybe described and/or explained by using MOi. On may but need

not be identical with Oi. Here again it is important to clarify

under what conditions MOi may be applied to a given On and

in the case of which On the application is blocked.13

(c) Rule 3 (constructivity): The successful realization of rule 2

yields metascientific knowledge of the nature of the object

scientific theory investigated (e.g. of On). This knowledge may

be used for the improvement of objectscientific research car

ried out within the frames of On itself. Just as in the case of

the first two rules, also here it is crucial to reveal the criteria

according to which MOi may contribute to the improvement

of research conducted inOn. For example, if (b) is blocked for

whatever reason, then (c) is blocked as well.

Accordingly, it seems to be the case that the main thing one has to do

to avoid theparadox

of naturalizedepistemology

isfollowing

the rules of

(HRN). Unfortunately, however, the situation is not as simple as it seems

tobe.

4.2. Realizations of (HRN)

Although (HRN) appears to have resolved the paradox, in this form it

is still too weak to serve as a workable tool for revealing the nature of

'scientific' inquiry. We have seen above that the reason why the heuristics

Page 13: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 13/21

280 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

proved to be useful in avoiding the fatal consequences of an infinite regress

was that it consisted of rules', however, from another point of view the

fact that the solution rests on such rules is responsible for its weakness.

In particular, no rule can exist per se; rules have a virtual existence and

therefore they are always coupled with some kind of manifestation. Again,

by analogy, we may say that justas rules of language are manifested in ut

terances, also (HRN) cannot exist without being realized somehow. Since

scientific heuristics normally manifest themselves in scientific theories, it

is straightforward to assume that metascientific theories are manifestations

of(HRN).

Thisis,

ofcourse,

not tosay

that(HRN)

should beidentified

with

a metascientific theory, just as we must not think that rules of language are

identical with the utterances they govern. The only thing we have to admit

is that (HRN) cannot work per se, rather, itmust be supplemented by the

very metascientific theories which itmanifests itself in.

Another point results from Quine's thesis of the underdetermination

of theories by evidence (see e.g Quine 1975). In a simplified manner, the

thesis says that on the basis of the sameempirical evidence, it will always

be possible to develop different theories capturing this evidence but incom

patible with each other. Consequently, the decision between these theories

cannot rest onempirical data themselves. If naturalized metatheories are

nothing but empirical theories transferred to the metascientific level, then

the metatheories which come into being in this way are underdetermined

by experience to the same extent as the objectscientific theories which they

are rooted in. The result is that we have to do with a plurality of metathe

ories which (i)may be generated by (HRN), (ii)may be incompatiblewith

each other, (iii) may capture the same evidence, i.e. certain data concerning

the nature of scientific inquiry.14

Accordingly, the task which one has to carry out is this:

(a) Firstly, one should find a set of objectscientific theories which, in the

sense of (HRN)(a) can be transferred to the metascientific level; according

to (HRN)(b) are capable of being applied to the description and/or explan

ation of certain aspects of scientific knowledge; and, due to (HRN)(c), may

contribute to the furthering of objectscientific inquiry-

in sum, which are

possible realizations of the heuristics of reflexive naturalism.15

(b) Secondly, if such a set of metatheories is given which may be in

compatible with each other but which are compatible with (HRN), one has

to look for further considerations so as to select the very metatheory which

is suitable for the solution of the particular metascientific problems which

have been raised. Which one chooses is, therefore, not amatter of general

decisions, but depends solelyon the particular tasks and purposes which a

given metatheory has to serve.16

Page 14: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 14/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 281

5. CONCLUSIONS

Our task has been to put forward a possible solution to (P) by arguing forthe thesis (T). Our preliminary result is this:

(T)(a). A brief analysis of the state of the art led to a very simple sys

tematization of current approaches to naturalized epistemology. The two

strong versions which were defined turned out to be untenable right at the

outset. Therefore, the question was: which of the two remaining versions,

namely, weaki and weak2, should be accepted?

Quine's thesis according to which traditional epistemology ought to be

given up completely applies to weaki naturalism as well. Since this thesis

was motivated by the problem of scepticism, first we had to find out to

what extent weaki naturalism could avoid those traps which traditional

epistemology was not able to. The result was definitively negative, because

we showed that Quine's antisceptical argumentation itself yielded a scep

tical paradox which we called the paradox of naturalized epistemology.

Thus we could not avoid drawing the conclusion that itwas not only the

two strong versions that had to be discarded but also weaki naturalism that

led to a problem without whose solution the programme of naturalized

epistemology seemed to be unrealistic. In this way we have shown the

plausibility of(T)(a).

(T)(b). Thus our next task was to find a possible solution to the paradox

mentioned. As astarting point, we tried tomake use of a pattern accord

ing to which certain classic paradoxes had been solved, but this attempt

was not successful. In particular, it turned out that as long as we want to

construct 'theories' on the metascientific level, the

argumention

will result

in an infinite regress. However, it is possible to avoid this regress if we do

not aim at developing naturalized theories of scientific inquiry, but rather,

a kind of heuristics which we called the heuristics of reflexive naturalism.

The reason why the regress did not necessarily arise was that heuristics are

rules, and that rules need not be captured on a higher meta-level in order

to be followed. Consequently, (T)(b) has been shown.

(T)(c). The argumentation which yielded (T)(b) rested on two theses.

The first one was the thesis of reflexivity (see (9)) which summarized thebasic idea of any approach to naturalized epistemology. The second thesis

was an assumption specific to our solution of the paradox; it can be stated

in this way:

(10) The thesis of heuristics: A naturalized metatheory is the realization of

the heuristics of reflexive naturalism.

In what follows, I shall call the approach which accepts (9) and (10)

reflexive-heuristicnaturalism.

Now,the

questionarises as to which extent

Page 15: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 15/21

282 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

these two main theses of our approach lead to the maintenance of the

intended weak2 version of naturalized epistemology.

(i) Since,as we have

seen,heuristics do not solve

necessarilythe

problems which they tackle, the application of metascientific heuristics does not

necessarily result in the development of metatheories which are capable

of working in the expected way. Therefore, one central feature of our ap

proach is itsfallibilism according towhich the uncertainly, the local nature

and the restricted scope of any metatheory compatible with the heuristics

of reflexive naturalism has to be acknowledged.

(ii) From the fact that our approach to naturalized epistemology is con

ceived of as a special kind of heuristics it follows, as we have seen inthe preceding section as well, that it can manifest itself inmany different

metatheories which are incompatible with each other. Thus this approach

is inherently pluralistic.

(iii) Last but not least our approach is relativistic, because we have

emphasized that one may choose from among the metatheories compatible

with the heuristics of reflexive-naturalism on the basis of the problems,

aims, conditions etc. given.

These three properties of our approach are compatible with weak2 na

turalism.17 In particular, they inevitably lead to the conclusion that tradi

tional epistemology and 'SCIENCE self-applied' within the scope of the

heuristics of reflexive naturalism may coexist. However, this coexistence

can be interpreted only in a way which says that, although traditional

epistemology remains, its scope will be changed in at least two respects.

Firstly, itwill be narrowed, because certain tasks which it carried out in the

past will be tackled by the 'naturalized' metatheories which the heuristics

of reflexive naturalism generates. Secondly, in accordance with this, tradi

tional epistemology is not located on the meta-level immediately following

objectscientific inquiry, but rather, one lever higher. In between there is

a new level: in particular, that of reflexive-heuristic naturalism.18 So, the

following hypothesis presents itself:

(11) There is a level of metascientific reflexion

(a) which is located between objectscientific inquiry and traditional

epistemology, and

(b) which can be identified with reflexive-heuristic naturalism.

Thus, (T)(c) seems to be plausible as well. However, the far-reaching

consequences of (11) cannot be overlooked. Therefore, let me indicate

briefly some of the unsolved problems itmay give rise to.

Page 16: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 16/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 283

6. OPEN QUESTIONS

6.1. Normativity

One of the central problems of naturalized epistemology is the question as

to what extent it can dispense with the normative aspect of metascientific

reflexion. Although this question has been widely discussed and there is

an immense literature devoted to it, the main tendency seems to be clear:

Quine's intention of elaborating a non-normative approach to epistemo

logy (see also (2)(c)) is untenable, and there is noepistemology without a

normativecomponent.

However, if this is so, the next question is, in what sense reflexive

heuristic naturalism may be normative. As an answer, the following argu

mentation presents itself (see also Itkonen 1999):

(a) The solution of the paradox of naturalized epistemology rests on the

constitutive properties of heuristics.

(b) By definition, heuristics consist of rules.

(c) By definition, these rules are normative.

Therefore:

(d) Heuristics are normative

Therefore:

(e) Our solution of the paradox is normative as well.

Accordingly, the really interesting question is not whether reflexive

heuristric naturalism is normative, because it goes without saying that it is.

The really interesting problem is the relationship between (i) this kind of

normativity resulting from the nature of heuristics, (ii) the normativity of

traditional epistemology and (ii) the possible normativity of the very meta

theories which the heuristics manifests itself in within the mechanisms of

reflexive-heuristic naturalism. This is a problem which, on the one hand,

needs careful consideration, but on the other hand shows once again that

the original tenets of naturalism are anything but straightforward.

6.2. Hermeneutics

An extremely problematic consequence of the present states of affairs con

cerning naturalism is connected to hermeneutics. Let us turn to Quine,

again:

"Naturalism does not repudiate epistemology, but assimilates it to empirical psychology.

Science itself tells us that our information about the world is limited to irritations of our

surfaces, and then the epistemological question is in turn a question within science [...]".

(Quine1981:

72; emphasis added)

Page 17: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 17/21

284 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

The quotation focuses on two aspects. According to the first, the main

source of metascientific theories is empirical psychology. The second says

that psychology is part of natural science and that, consequently, metascience should be treated as a natural science as well. However, the inter

esting thing is that though Quine's idea of naturalizing epistemology gave

rise to remarkable new developments, these developments differ consider

ably from what Quine had presumably inmind. Firstly, as we have already

seen, it is not only the natural sciences that may be used for the construc

tion of 'naturalized' metatheories. Secondly, and this is what we have to

discuss now, in fact it was not empirical, behaviouristic psychology, but

rather, cognitive psychology in particular and cognitive science in gen

eral which to a considerable extent, though not exclusively, are expected

to yield approaches to naturalized epistemology.19 As a result, the idea

of a 'cognitive science of science' emerges as the possible manifestation

of the programme of naturalized epistemology. Downes (1993: 453-454)

characterizes this situaton as follows:

"Much recent naturalized philosophy of science can be characterized ascognitive sci

ence of science. Cognitive scientists of science apply techniques from the cognitive sci

ences to issues previously examined by the philosophy of science, for example, theory

change, theory evaluation, the nature of scientific theories, and scientific discovery. In

general, cognitive-science-of-science researchers set their work apart from more tradi

tional approaches to philosophy of science such aslogical empiricism. They are naturalists

who hold that empirical results from current sciences, particularly, the cognitive sciences,

should inform and constrain philosophical theories. Some further suggest thatphilosophyshould be abandoned and replaced by

aparticular science, or some suggest that cognitive

science of science should replace philosophy of science."20

This state of affairs affects reflexive-heuristic naturalism aswell,

be

cause cognitive science is one of the major sources of possible metatheor

ies which reflexive-heuristic naturalism may manifest itself in.21 However,

cognitive science is an extremely heterogeneous set of approaches.22 As

an extreme case, certain cognitive scientists, for example, even go as far as

tomaintain that the whole of cognitive science is a basically hermeneutic

enterprise:

"[...] cognitive science is itselfa human interpretative science (that is, a hermeneutic

science) so that what we have said about hermeneutics should apply to it also." (Arbib

& Hesse 1986: 182; emphasis added, A.K.))

"[...] we would argue for a continuity between natural and hermeneutic science based on

the fact that they both have the same domain of objects (namely, bodies, including persons'

bodies) carrying their properties around in space and time." (Arbib & Hesse 1986: 183;

emphasis added, A.K.)

The potential hermeneutic nature of cognitive science doesn't result

from its

diversity,

and the

properties

of its

subject

matter

only,

but also

Page 18: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 18/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 285

from its constitutive reflexivity which defines it as a possible source of

metatheories connected to reflexive-heuristic naturalism right at the outset:

"[...] cognitive science is essentially self-reflective; that is, itmust subject its own method

ologyto its own critique. In the course of doing this, cognitive science has broken with the

notion of 'scientific method' aspurely empiricist and positivist. For example,

we look at the

contributions of Piaget [...] and Freud [...] to the understanding of the cognitive, and also

find parallels within cognitive science for the theory of interpretation,or hermeneutics."

(Arbib& Hesse 1986: 12; emphasis added)

The perspective that cognitive science, as one of the main possible

manifestations of reflexive-heuristic naturalism, may definitively be con

ceived of as a hermeneutic activity raises the problem whether it is possibleat all to consider those metascientific investigations which it yields as -

in

whatever sense - a posteriori. Namely, if (a) cognitive science may be of

a hermeneutic nature; (b) hermeneutic disciplines are, by definition, not a

posteriori; and (c) the subtheories of cognitive science may also be seen as

potential manifestations of the heuristics of reflexive naturalism; then the

answer is explicitly 'no'. Therefore, there is no avoiding the question what

it is that remains from the programme of naturalism.

7. SUMMARY

Our task has been to solve the problem (P) by arguing for thesis (T). In

doing so we put forward an approach which we called reflexive-heuristic

naturalism. This approach, however, presupposed the assumption that two

main aspects of Quine's naturalism (namely, the complete replacement of

traditional epistemology and its replacement by natural science) had to be

given up. As a result, we maintained that reflexive-heuristic naturalism and

traditional epistemology can coexist in a specific way indicated in (11).

Reflexive-heuristic naturalism, however, is, as the examples mentioned

in section 6 have witnessed, still susceptible to serious unsolved prob

lems concerning basic concepts and assumptions. Therefore, there is no

avoiding the conclusion that, on the one hand, the elaboration of reflexive

heuristic naturalism itselfgrew

out of thenecessity

ofde-naturalising epi

stemology; but on the other hand, the problems it leaves open seem to

strengthen this need decisevely. Whether reflexive-heuristic naturalism is

an idea which may be conceived of as a workable attempt to reconcile

the seemingly antagonistic processes of naturalising and de-naturalising

epistemology, is a question that must be asked but cannot be answered at

this point.

Page 19: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 19/21

286 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

NOTES

1

My researchwhich thepresent paperrests on

has been supported byOTKA

T34662.2To indicate this I shall put relevant terms used in a preexplicative way within single

quotation marks.

3 It is questionable whether it is justified to characterize naturalized epistemology by a

well-defined set of theses. Althought the situation is very complicated and there have been

many attempts to classify current trends, for the sake of argument in this paper we shall

draw a simplified picture. For more sophisticated discussions of current naturalized epi

stemology see e.g. Almeder (1990),Maffie (1990,1995), Kornblith (1985), Kitcher (1992),

Koppelberg (1996) etc. Moreover, the list of theses characterizing naturalized epistemology

doesn't contain (2)(d) which would decide whether naturalized epistemology is pluralisticor not. However, in section 4.2. we shall give

aspecific

answer to this question.4

See also section 6.1. for a short discussion of the problem of normativity.5

In what follows SCIENCE will stand for this sense, science for natural science and

'science' will indicate that the term is used in anunspecified way.

6These arguments apply predominantly to the scientism, dogmatism and one-sidednes of

naturalized epistemologyas discussed e.g. in Davidson and Hintikka (1969), Hahn and

Shilp (1986), Haack (1993), Maffie (1995) etc.7

For lack of space it is not possible to review these arguments here in detail.

8The term 'paradox' is not meant in a

strictly logical sense (that is A if and only ifnot-A),

but rather, in a wider epistemological sense according to which it is a problem leading to

inconsistent consequences.9

Let us remember that the versions weakj and strongj share the property of fixing the

parameter 2 at the value '+'. Since we have already rejected both strong versions on the

basis of arguments concerning the value of parameter 1, in the present context it is sufficient

to interpret (8) as the refutation of weak i naturalism although the argument just put forward

applies to strongi naturalism as well.

10The argument that follows rests on an

analogical inference of the following type:

Premisses:

(1) The paradox of naturalized epistemology is similar to classic paradoxes.

(2) Classic paradoxes can be solved by firstly, subdividing the domain in which the para

dox arose into subdomains and secondly, blocking certain relations between these

subdomains.

Conclusion:

The paradox of naturalized epistemologycan be solved by firstly, subdividing the

domain in which the paradox arose into subdomains and secondly, blocking certain

relations between these subdomains.

Nevertheless, the analogy indicated in premise (1) is a weak one: while the paradoxes of

Tarski and Russell have the logical structure 'A if and only if not-A', the paradox of nat

uralism, as already mentioned, has the structure 'A ifnot-A'. Accordingly, the probability

of the truth of the conclusion is smaller than if the two paradoxes had the same logical

structure. This may be one of the reasonswhy

- as we shall see-

in our case the pattern of

classic solutions to paradoxes will not work.

11But not only in theories, of course. It would be more

appropriate to handle the results

of the horizontal subdivision asunspecified 'units' which may be theories, or models, or

explanations,or methods and the like.

Page 20: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 20/21

ON THEDE-NATURALIZATION F EPISTEMOLOGY 287

12See, for example, thedebate inSocial Studies of Science 19(1989)-22(1992) andKert?sz

(1993) as an evaluation of thisdebate.13For example, Kert?sz (1991) and (1995) tried to develop approaches to the cognitivescience of science. In Kert?sz (1995) it has been shown that in the course of rule 2 a

'modular' metatheory must not be applied to the description and/or explanation of objects

cientific theories belonging to the 'holistic' tradition and vice versa.

14Again, the analogy to the rules of language presents itself. Itmay be, of course, the case

that the same rules underly utterances which areincompatible with each other but which

refer to the same states of affairs.

15This means thaton the one hand (HRN) is so general that itmay bemanifested inmany

different metatheories, even if these are inconsistent with each other. On the other hand, it

is so restrictive that it allows only those metatheoretical approaches which are conceived

of as its possible manifestations.16

See also footnote 3.

17These three properties of reflexive-heuristic naturalism are highly problematic, of course,

because they may yield far-reaching epistemological consequences. However, the question

as to what extent and in what way their scope may be restrected can be answered only with

respect to the particular metatheories which the heuristics manifests itself in. Therefore,

amajor task will be the relativization of this problem to the metatheories at issue and

the exploration of particular ways to its solution which may differ from metatheory to

metatheory.18

I amgrateful

toMarta Feh?r forcalling my

attention to thisinsight.19

With respect to the current state of affairs in the general philosophy of science, another

candidate is the sociology of knowledge. The problem whether cognitive and sociological

approachesare

antagonistic and, if not, to what extent their integration within the pro

gramme of naturalism is possible is one of the central issues being discussed. See e.g.

Kert?sz (1993) for an analysis of their relationship.20

A careful distinction between naturalized epistemology and naturalized philosophy of

science would be beside the point in the present context.

21For case studies supporting this assumption

see Kert?sz (1995).22

See Eckardt (1993) on the question whether and if so to what extent cognitive science

may be called adiscipline.

REFERENCES

Almeder, P.: 1990, 'On Naturalizing Epistemology', American Philosophical Quarterly

27, 263-279.

Arbib,M.A. and

Hesse,M.B.:

1986,The Construction

of Reality, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Davidson, D. and Hintikka, J. (eds.): 1976, Words and Objections: Essays on the Work of

W. V. Quine, Dordrecht, Reidel.

Downes, S.: 1993, 'Socializing Naturalized Philosophy of Science', Philosophy of Science

60, 452^*68.

Eckardt, B. von: 1993, What is Cognitive Science? Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Haack, S.: 1993, 'The Two Faces of Quine's Naturalism', Synthese 94, 335-356.

Hahn, L.E. and Schilpp, P.A. (eds.): 1986, The Philosophy ofW.V.O. Quine. La Salle, IL:

Open Court.

Page 21: naturalised epistemology

8/14/2019 naturalised epistemology

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/naturalised-epistemology 21/21

288 ANDR?S KERT?SZ

Itkonen, E.: 1999, A Comment on 'Metalinguistik als Forschungsprogramm' by Andr?s

Kert?sz. Sprachtheorie und germanistische Linguistik 9, 89-94.

Kert?sz, A.: 1991, Die Modularit?t der Wissenschaft. Konzeptuelle und soziale Prinzipien

linguistischer Erkenntnis, Braunschweig/Wiesbaden: Vieweg.

Kert?sz, A.: 1993, Artificial Intelligence and the Sociology of Knowledge: Prolegomena to

anIntegrated Philosophy of Science. Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

Kert?sz, A.: 1995, Die Ferse und der Schild. ?ber M?glichkeiten und Grenzen kognitions

wissenschaftlicher Theorien der Erkenntnis. Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

Kitcher, P.: 1992, 'The Naturalists Return', The Philosophical Review 101, 53-114.

Koppelberg, D.: 1996, 'Was macht eine Erkenntnistheorie naturalistisch?' Journal for

General Philosophy of Science 27, 71-90.

Kornblith, H.: 1985, Introduction: What is Naturalized Epistemology? In: Kornblith, H.

(ed.) (1985), 1-15.Kornblith, H. (ed.): 1985, Naturalized Epistemology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

Maffie, J.: 1990, 'Recent Work on Naturalized Epistemology', American Philosophical

Quarterly 27, 281-293.

Maffie, J.: 1995, 'Naturalism, Scientism and the Independence of Epistemology', Erkennt

nis 43, 1-27.

Quine, W.V.O.: 1960, Word and Object, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Quine, W.V.O.: 1969a, Epistemology Naturalized. In: Quine, W.V.O. (1969): Ontological

Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, 69-90.

Quine, W.V.O.: 1969b, Reply to Smart. In: Davidson, D. and Hintikka, J. (eds.) (1975),292-295.

Quine, W.V.O.: 1975, 'On Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World', Erkenntnis 9

(1975), 313-328.

Quine, W.V.O.: 1981, Theories and Things. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Shatz, D.: 1993, 'Scepticism and Naturalized Epistemology'. In: Wagner, S.J. and

Warner, R. (eds.): Naturalism: A Critical Reapparaisal. Notre Dame, IN.: Notre Dame

University Press, 117-145.

University of Debrecen

Pf.47

H-4010 Debrecen

(akertesz @ fox.klte.hu)