in self defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

11
© 2010 The International Neuropsychoanalysis Society http://www.neurops a.org In Self-Defense: Disruptions in the Sense of Self, Lateralization, and Primitive Defenses Commentary by Christian Salas & Oliver H. T urnbull (Bangor, U.K.) Perhaps the main appeal of Todd Feinberg’s proposal is his effort to undertake the study of one of the most avoided and controv ersial topics in neuroscience and psychoanalysis: the self. The difculties that this endeavor implies are multiple, and it is our intention to engage with Feinberg’s pursuit by constructively challenging and potentially enriching his theory. Our purpose here is to examine four particular aspects of Feinberg’s argument. First, to point out the need to clarify how he understands the notion of self from a psycho- analytic and neuroscientic perspective. Second, to review the evidence regarding how purely cognitive conditions (memory disorders, aphasia, etc.) do affect the sense of self. Third, to examine his claim on how the neuropathologies of the self imply a regression to earlier stages of development , characterized by a recrudescence of patterns of thought and psychological defenses. Fourth, to com- ment on his theoretical suggestion that, because patients with right-sided lesions preserve immature defenses (denial, projection, splitting, fantasy), those primitive defensive processes are somehow left-lateralized, while mature defenses are right-lateralized. Keywor ds: catastrophic reaction; defense mechanisms; functional systems; lateralization; regression; sense of self Christian Salas: Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychol- ogy, Universit y of Wales, Bangor, U.K., & Unidad Psicoterapia Dinámica, José Horwitz Barak Psychiatric Institute, Santiago, Chile. Oliver H. Turn- bull: Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychology, University of Wales, Bangor, U.K. The need to ll (theoretical) gaps A perhaps inevitable limitation in Feinberg’s proposi- tion is the multiple meanings that can be attributed to the notion of self. According to Feinberg’s Target Article, different aspects of a neuropathology of the self might imply disturbances in the patient’s sense of self and of identity, and even the relation with others and him/herself . Feinberg also describes how the neu- ropathologies of the self (NPS) might affect different self-related domains, such as the bodily self, relational self, and narrative self. This denition seems very broad, conating concepts that may belong to differ- ent levels of analysis, or theoretical backgrounds—for 172 Neuropsychoanalysis, 2010, 12 (2)

Upload: christian-salas-riquelme

Post on 08-Apr-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 1/11

© 2010 The International Neuropsychoanalysis Society • http://www.neuropsa.org 

In Self-Defense: Disruptions in the Sense of Self, Lateralization, and Primitive

Defenses

Commentary by Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull (Bangor, U.K.)

Perhaps the main appeal of Todd Feinberg’s proposal is his effort to undertake the study of one of the most avoided and controversial

topics in neuroscience and psychoanalysis: the self. The difficulties that this endeavor implies are multiple, and it is our intention toengage with Feinberg’s pursuit by constructively challenging and potentially enriching his theory. Our purpose here is to examine four

particular aspects of Feinberg’s argument. First, to point out the need to clarify how he understands the notion of self from a psycho-

analytic and neuroscientific perspective. Second, to review the evidence regarding how purely cognitive conditions (memory disorders,

aphasia, etc.) do affect the sense of self. Third, to examine his claim on how the neuropathologies of the self imply a regression to

earlier stages of development, characterized by a recrudescence of patterns of thought and psychological defenses. Fourth, to com-

ment on his theoretical suggestion that, because patients with right-sided lesions preserve immature defenses (denial, projection,

splitting, fantasy), those primitive defensive processes are somehow left-lateralized, while mature defenses are right-lateralized.

Keywords: catastrophic reaction; defense mechanisms; functional systems; lateralization; regression; sense of self 

Christian Salas: Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychol-

ogy, University of Wales, Bangor, U.K., & Unidad Psicoterapia Dinámica,

José Horwitz Barak Psychiatric Institute, Santiago, Chile. Oliver H. Turn-

bull: Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychology, University

of Wales, Bangor, U.K.

The need to fill (theoretical) gaps

A perhaps inevitable limitation in Feinberg’s proposi-tion is the multiple meanings that can be attributed

to the notion of self. According to Feinberg’s TargetArticle, different aspects of a neuropathology of the

self might imply disturbances in the patient’s sense of self and of identity, and even the relation with othersand him/herself . Feinberg also describes how the neu-ropathologies of the self (NPS) might affect differentself-related domains, such as the bodily self, relational self, and narrative self. This definition seems verybroad, conflating concepts that may belong to differ-ent levels of analysis, or theoretical backgrounds—for 

172 Neuropsychoanalysis, 2010, 12 (2)

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 2/11

Neuropathologies of the Self: A General Theory • Commentaries 173

example, when speaking about sense of self and iden-tity. As we describe later, patients with purely cognitivedeficits often show transient disruptions in their senseof self (coherence and continuity). However, they seemto preserve a global experience of identity. As a con-sequence, it seems necessary to make clear what we

mean by sense of self and identity.These issues of precision have previously been

raised in other fields where the self is the focus of study(e.g., Bukobza, 2007; Leary, 2004) and also in the neu-ropsychoanalytic debate (Panksepp, 2002). In addition,it is impossible to speak about a single psychoanalyticdefinition of the self, especially given that psycho-analysis has evolved into many schools, each with itsown account of the self (Westen, 1992). Implicitly,Feinberg appears to use the notion of self consistentwith the ego psychology school, which underscores therole of the ego as a mediator in the adaptation to real-ity, using defense mechanisms to cope with exigencies

of the external world, as well as drive demands (Freud,1936; Hartmann, 1958). However, although the theoryFeinberg proposes mainly relies on the disequilib-rium of the ego, he does not clarify the metapsycho-logical arrangement between ego and self. Is the self a substructure of the ego (Milrod, 2002)? Is it derivedfrom the self-representation of the body and mentallife (Jacobson, 1964)? Also, is Feinberg suggesting anaffective nuclear self (Panksepp, 2002), constitutedon a moment-by-moment basis (Stern, 2002), or anextended-representational self (Damasio, 1999)? Thesetheoretical affiliations generate rather diverse interpre-tations of the clinical phenomena, and they need to bemade explicit if we are to build a solid foundation for the NPS. For instance, if we adhere to a psychoanalyti-cally relational version of the self, we must accept thatthe self can be multiple, context-dependent, and dis-continuous, although always striving to sustain an illu-sory sense of unity and continuity (Bromberg, 1996;Mitchell, 1993). In this view, the efforts of anosog-nosic patients to preserve a coherent inner experienceare not simply an exacerbation of primitive defensemechanisms because of the loss of mature defenses.Rather, they reflect the expression of a basic propertyof the organism, which generates coherence and con-

tinuity regardless of reality constrains. Edelman andTononi (2001) address (in an appealing metaphor) theimplications of this basic tendency of the organismtoward coherence:

One is left with the impression that after a mas-sive stroke or surgical resection, a conscious humanbeing is rapidly “resynthesized” or reunified withinthe limits of a new, solipsistic universe that, to outsideappearances, is warped and restricted. The network 

of relations that make up a conscious event is not leftbroken and discontinuous; rather, the loose ends tendrapidly to cohere again and bridge the rupture. Thedrive to integration is so strong that often no emptyspace is perceived where there is, in fact, a frighteninggap. Apparently, the feeling of an absence is far lesstolerable than the absence of a feeling. [p. 29]

“Cognitive” deficits and transient disruptions inthe sense of self

Feinberg appears to suggest that purely cognitive defi-cits, such as amnesia, aphasia, apraxia, etc., may affectthought and behavior but do not disrupt personal iden-tity, the sense of self, personal significance of self to others, or personal and autobiographical history.An alternative proposition would be that the sense of self, constituted by a sense of coherence and continu-ity, may be transiently disrupted after a brain injury

that compromises purely cognitive functions. In other words, the disruption to cognitive abilities might notdisturb the boundaries of the self (as Feinberg claims),but may well disrupt the experience of a cohesive self.

This proposition is aligned with Kurt Goldstein’sunderstanding of the impact caused by cognitive dys-function in the relationship between organism andenvironment, what he famously characterized as acatastrophic reaction  (Goldstein, 1956). According toGoldstein, in a catastrophic reaction the individualenters into a disorganized  inner state because of notbeing able to account for environmental demands.Behavior is devoid of clear order, and it lacks a globalpattern that aligns all the organism’s components— somatic and psychic—in the service of a particular task. The patient thus experiences a physical and men-tal “shock,” feeling “unfree, buffeted and vacillat-ing” (pp. 48–49). This shock, according to Goldstein,extends its impact beyond the patient’s person, provok-ing a collapse in his or her experience of the surround-ing world.

Goldstein’s conceptualization of catastrophic reac-tion is deeply rooted in the understanding of how braininjury shatters the coherence and continuity of the self.Contemporary authors, such as Ben-Yishay (2000),

have approached catastrophic reaction in a similar fashion, by defining it as the “behavioral manifestationof a threat to the person’s very existence” (p. 128). Theneuropsychiatric literature, however, has tended to usethe term in a much-reduced way, narrowing it to inad-equate outbursts of frustration, depression, or anger (Carota, Rossetti, Karapanayiotides, & Bogousslavsky,2001; Chemerinski & Robinson, 2000; Starkstein,Fedoroff, Price, Leiguarda, & Robinson, 1993). This

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 3/11

174 Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull

tendency has neglected catastrophic reaction’s coreaspect, which may well be a discontinuity in the expe-rience of the self. From a psychoanalytic background,this discontinuity appears to be characterized as theemergence of primitive anxieties (Salas, 2008a) or “unthinkable anxieties,” such as profound falling anxi-

ety, fear of fragmentation (e.g., the patient Mr. L. inKaplan-Solms & Solms, 2000, p. 120), disorientation,and psychosomatic dissociation (Winnicott, 1965).

Goldstein’s ideas seem to be supported by ArnoldModell’s neuropsychoanalytic conceptualization of theself (Modell, 1993). He has suggested that the coher-ence and continuity of the self is a fundamental biolog-ical value that strives for the organism’s homeostasis.Coherence means, in Goldstein’s terms, the alignmentof the organism’s somatic and psychic components.Thus, a disturbance in the homeostasis of the self implies, to Modell (1993), a fragmentation and a senseof chaos (p. 172). The continuity of the self refers to

the continuous updating of the value-laden memorysystem, over time, in interaction with the environment(p. 163). Coherence and continuity are mutually rein-forcing loops: the “sticking together” of the self rein-forces its continuity, and vice versa (p. 202).

There is a significant literature that supports Gold-stein claims, in opposition to Feinberg’s argument thatpurely cognitive deficits cannot disrupt the continu-ity and coherence of the self. For example, patientswith amnesic disorders describe interruptions in theexperience of continuity, relating episodes where their mind is in a state of “blankness” (Tulving, 1985; Turn-bull, Zois, Kaplan-Solms, & Solms, 2007). PatientN.N. (Tulving, 1985), who suffers both retrograde andanterograde amnesia, portrays this state of mind whentrying to think: “It’s like being in a room with nothing there and having a guy tell you to go find a chair, andthere is nothing there . . . or it’s like swimming in themiddle of a lake. There is nothing to hold you up or do anything with” (p. 4). These memory deficits mayalter the survivor’s relationship with his or her environ-ment. For instance, patient KC (Tulving, 1993), withanterograde amnesia, showed a profound change in hispersonality: “whereas he used to be outgoing, adven-turous, and gregarious, he is now passive, cautious and

reticent . . . he does not typically initiate interactionswith people around him, although he does ask ques-tions from time to time” (p. 150). In a similar trend,patient Jack (Wilson, 1999), again with anterogradeamnesia, described how he avoided situations wherehis memory difficulties would leave him lost and dis-orientated (p. 42). To him, memory deficits also causeda loss of continuity in interpersonal relationships(p. 42).

On the basis of a similar argument, and contraryto Feinberg’s claim to exclude cognitive functionsfrom the realm of the self, one must take into accountlanguage disorders and their impact on the coherenceand continuity of the self. On rare occasions, languagedisorders have been associated with disruptions in the

sense of self, where there is a widespread recognitionof their emotional and interpersonal impact (Gainotti,1997; Wilson, 1999). A possible reason to neglect therelevance of language to the sense of self is the dif-ficulty in establishing accurately the patient’s subjec-tive experience in such cases, because a central tool of communication is compromised. Nevertheless, Moss(1972), an experimented clinical psychologist who hadsuffered a stroke, offers a rare account of the subjec-tive experience of having aphasia. Moss had an initialglobal aphasia, which later evolved into an expressiveaphasia, and he describes his experience as follows:initially it was like “living in a vacuum of self produced

concepts . . . with absolutely no words to express whatwas happening to me, not even to myself . . . I was ren-dered concrete in terms of my thinking . . . I could dealonly with the immediate present in terms of concreteactions” (pp. 76–79). As regards his interpersonal life,he explains: “trying to follow each person’s contribu-tion, to integrate the various topics, and also attemptingto formalize what I might say in response was just tootaxing, and after a while I inevitably lapsed back intoa semiconscious reverie” (p. 91). Although Moss’sreport suggests that language deficits might underminethe continuity and time-traveling quality of thoughtprocesses, in other aphasic patients such capacitiesseemed to be preserved, suggesting a possible dissocia-tion between thinking and language (Kapur, 1996, pp.111–113; Varley & Siegal, 2000).

The psychotherapeutic exploration of aphasicpatients offers an opportunity to disentangle howspecific language deficits might impact differentiallythe patient’s sense of self. In a neuropsychoanalyticaccount, Kaplan-Solms and Solms (2000) compare thepsychic transformations after Broca’s aphasia (Mr. J)and Wernicke’s aphasia (Mrs. K). In the case of Mr. J,the damage to the motor element of speech (Broca) didnot compromise his capacity to think, to relate to others,

or to test reality. In fact, they conclude that the motoriclanguage areas lie at the sensorimotor “periphery” of the ego (p. 89). The case of Mrs. K was quite different.Her main difficulty lay in her inability to retain audio-verbal material in working memory, which generated a“perforation in her consciousness, and therefore in thefabric of her being” (p. 107). Mrs. K complained aboutbeen unable to think, experiencing regular gaps in her sense of continuity, as if the ongoing awareness of her 

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 4/11

Neuropathologies of the Self: A General Theory • Commentaries 175

self, and thought, kept disappearing (p. 98). The senseof estrangement from herself is clearly depicted in her disjointed account: “now I can’t think . . . I don’t knowwhat is going on . . . it is too terrible. I can’t remember the simplest things, it is just not me . . . I’m so mixedup, sometimes I remember things and sometimes they

are gone . . . I’m in bits and pieces through my mind. . . often I just want to sit down on my own so I don’thave to talk, because I can’t remember things . . .when things go, everything goes” (pp. 99–102).

In yet another cognitive domain, lesions to the leftparietal cortex typically produce spatial disorders, con-structional apraxia, and impairment of quasi-spatialsynthesis (Luria, 1973). In Luria’s The Man with aShattered World (1972), the patient Zazetsky describeshis inner experience after an injury, which has a pro-foundly fragmented quality: “whatever I do remember is scattered, broken down into disconnected bits andpieces . . . I’m in a kind of fog all the time, like a

heavy half sleep. My memory is blank” (pp. 23–25).Zazetsky’s sense of continuity in time was also dis-rupted: “I remember nothing! Just separate bits of information that I sense have to do with one field or another. But that’s all! I have no real knowledge of anysubject. My past has been just wiped out!” (p. 116). Thecoherence between recognizing objects and using themalso appears to have been altered, as was his bodilyself-experience. Similar to this is Kaplan-Solms andSolms’s (2000) patient with damage to the left parietalcortex. The impact of a lack of quasi-spatial synthesisto “glue” experience together is seen in Mr. L, whohas transcortical aphasia and Gertsmann syndrome (p.118). He showed an almost complete absence of men-tal activity, apparently without being able to realizeany kind of associative thinking. Although he exhib-ited extreme anxiety and panic, and his mood was thatof someone whose world was entirely devastated, hewas not able to do anything with those preoccupations,besides having them (pp. 120–124).

In sum, we would offer a mixed conclusion onFeinberg’s account of the role of cognition in the main-tenance of the self. Fundamentally, we endorse hisoverall claim that a break in the boundaries of the self can be catastrophic after focal brain lesion, especially

involving midline (and perhaps right-lateralized) brainstructures. Such a breakdown in the boundaries of theself is indeed often associated with the deployment of defenses, often of the most primitive type. Our com-mentary serves primarily to better clarify the preciserole of cognitive deficits in producing disruptions onthe self. In contrast to Feinberg’s position—that theyare neutral with reference to the patient’s personalrelatedness to self—it appears that a variety of cogni-

tive impairments (in the domain of memory, language,and visuospatial skills) do indeed disrupt the sense of self.

Lateralization and primitive defenses

A further issue of note raised by Feinberg is that of defenses and their neuroanatomical basis. First, wenote that Feinberg draws on the idea of regression, anargument that has long been suggested in the brain-injury literature (Jackson, 1884), and also related to theidea of defenses (Freed, 2002; Kaplan-Solms & Solms,2000; Lewis, 1999). Notably, Feinberg observes thatpatients with right-sided lesions exhibit immaturedefenses, further suggesting that these mechanisms aretypically lateralized to the left hemisphere). Further-more, he hypothesizes the existence of a “left-brainto right-brain defensive shift” during development,

between 3 and 8 years, such that the right hemispheretakes over, inhibiting immature defenses and allowingthe development of mature ones.

Feinberg’s suggestion that different forms of defenses may be related to different neuroanatomi-cal substrates has some merit. Indeed, the discrimina-tion between mature and immature defenses is wellestablished on clinical grounds (Cramer, 2006, 2008;Vaillant, 1994), and there is a small literature offeringopinions on laterality and defense mechanisms (i.e.,Gainotti, 2006; Ramachandran & Blakeslee, 1998;Stern, 1997; Tucker, 1981). We would like to offer afurther analysis of the problem, which we hope willallow us to understand the neuropsychological basis of defense, from first principles.

We begin with the assumption of Luria’s functionalsystem concept, which suggests that all complex psy-chological processes, presumably including defensemechanisms, have multiple component parts (Luria,1973). This approach is also congruent with contempo-rary efforts to understand defenses as complex modesof emotion–cognitive interaction, where neural activitybetween distant and remote brain regions is adjusted,coordinated, and harmonized (Northoff & Boeker,2006). The classic psychoanalytic literature on defense

mechanisms has, for example, long suggested that thedefensive process implies: (1) an undesirable thoughtor impulse, (2) the emergence of anxiety as the thoughtor impulse approaches consciousness, (3) the use of a“counterforce” that allows the diminution of the driveor drive derivate (Freud, 1894).

If we consider this classical—and broad—definitionof the defensive process, we might suggest a neuropsy-chological translation of the possible component parts.

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 5/11

176 Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull

First, there is an increase in arousal of negative valencecaused by an aversive mental representation and/or external event. There is an active modulation (perhapsinhibiting or buffering) of this elevated level of arousalby exercising a set of cognitive–affective processes,which might vary according to the defense mechanism

used. In the case of mature defenses (rationalization,intellectualization, sublimation, repression, etc) thiswould require the use of more complex mental opera-tions (Cramer, 2008), or higher order psychologicalfunctions (voluntary orienting of attention, language,executive functions, etc.), which allow anxiety mini-mization and flexible adaptation to the environment(Clarkin, Lenzenweger, Yeomans, Levy, & Kernberg,2007). In contrast, immature defenses (denial, projec-tion, splitting) might require the use of more automaticand bodily based operations (Hofer, 2005; Schore,2003, pp. 59), which are more rigid and inflexible inadapting to external reality (Clarkin et al., 2007).

At this point we might find our first disagreementwith Feinberg’s argument. If mature defenses requirethe use of “higher order” psychological processes, itseems reasonable to suggest that some of their neuro-psychological components might be left-lateralized,considering the reported laterality of language (Binder et al., 1997; Gazzaniga & Sperry, 1967), determinate(as opposed to indeterminate) reasoning (Gazzaniga,2000; Gazzaniga & Smylie, 1984; Goel & Dolan,2004; Goel et al., 2007), verbal working memory(D’Esposito & Postle, 2002; Paulesu, Frith, & Frack-owiak, 1993), or verbal memory retrieval (Buckner,1996). The field of emotion regulation offers further evidence that might support the participation of left-hemisphere structures in mature defenses. Individualswith high levels of baseline left-prefrontal activationare particularly skilled in the down-regulation of neg-ative emotions (Davidson, 2000a, 2000b). Further-more, in reducing negative affect by reappraisal (thevoluntary language-based self-regulatory process thatresembles rationalization), the left prefrontal cortexstructures activate (Goldin, McRae, Ramel, & Gross,2008; Ochsner, Bunge, Gross, & Gabrieli, 2002). Insum, many of the complex processes that would logi-cally appear to underpin mature defenses depend on

left-sided neural structures. However, Feinberg sug-gests that mechanisms of mature defenses in their entirety are right-lateralized.

The idea that immature defenses are cognitivelyless complex seems supported by two main arguments.First, primitive defenses (projection/identification)appear early on in development, as psychological pro-cesses that allow the building of a primary sense of self (Freud, 1925; Klein, 1946) and the communication

of states of mind between child and caregiver (Bion,1959). This early appearance of primitive defensesmight fit with the proposed early development of theright hemisphere (Chi, Dooling, & Gilles, 1977; Chironet al., 1997; Crowell, Jones, Kapuniani, & Nakagawa,1973; Geschwind & Galaburda, 1987) and its role in

the generation of an image of the body in space andtime (Benton & Silvan, 1993) and the sense of agency(Farrer & Frith, 2002; Farrer et al., 2003). Moreover,primitive defense mechanisms are less sophisticated inpart because their main function is to rapidly regulatebodily based states (Schore, 2003, p. 59) of intensenegative affect (Kernberg, 1986, p. 148) in a rigid andinflexible fashion (Clarkin et al., 2007), addressing sur-vival situations presumably to avoid the fragmentationof the self (McCarthy, 2004). In particular, immaturedefenses appear to deal with negative arousal “spa-tially” (by placing it outside the body), nonverbally(by doing something concrete with the affect instead

of symbolizing), and holistically (pars pro toto). Allthese cognitive abilities have typically been attrib-uted to the right  hemisphere (Borod, 2000, p. 7),as has the association of the right hemisphere withwithdrawal-related emotions (Davidson, 1984; Heller,1 990; Kinsbourne & Bemporad, 1984), sympatheticarousal (Craig, 2010), physiological arousal (Eidelberg& Galaburda, 1984; Heilman, Schwartz, & Watson,1978; Heller, 1993; Heller, Nitschke, & Lindsay, 1997;Liotti & Tucker, 1992; Tucker & Williamson, 1984),negative emotional states (Heller, 1990; Sackeim etal., 1982; Silberman & Weingartner, 1986), and theprocessing of somatic information (Damasio, 1994).Such findings offer further support for the rightwardlateralization of many or most of the likely componentparts of primitive defenses.

A consequence of the argument presented in theprevious paragraph would be that patients with right-sided lesions should somehow lose immature defenses,leaving only the left hemisphere and its respectivemature defenses. This argument not only runs counter to Feinberg’s proposal, it may also be oversimplistic,appearing inconsistent with a substantial body of lit-erature on the dynamic nature of defense mechanismsin the brain-injured population. First of all we must

acknowledge that the psychoanalytic notion of defenseitself has changed in recent decades, moving from anintrapsychic process whose goal is the preservation of internal equilibrium toward a psychological processhighly dependent on context and shaped by interper-sonal settings (i.e., Cooper, 1998; Stolorow & Atwood,1992). This contextual feature of defense mechanismshas also been stressed by Cramer (2008) when suggest-ing that the use of defense mechanisms varies accord-

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 6/11

Neuropathologies of the Self: A General Theory • Commentaries 177

ing to exposure to situations that trigger excessiveanxiety or threaten self-esteem. Finally, as regards thedynamic nature of defenses in psychoanalysis, it seemsappropriate to keep in mind the meaning of the Klei-nian idea of “positions” (Klein, 1935), which entails a(normal) oscillation of the ego in relation to anxieties,

defenses, and object relations.In the brain-injured population, a similar claim

has been suggested, specifically regarding the waythat patients reduce their defensiveness when proper contextual support is offered (Fiegelson, 1993; Salas,2009; Ylvisaker & Feeney, 2000), or maintain it whendenial stabilizes an interpersonal system (Clarici &Giuliani, 2008). The fluctuation in the use of defensemechanisms has also been reported in patients withright-brain damage and anosognosia, where varia-tions seem to appear spontaneously (Moss & Turn-bull, 1996), are sensitive to sensory manipulations(Ramachandran & Blakeslee, 1998), or depend on the

self-referential quality of the interview questions (Mar-cel, Tegnér, & Nimmo-Smith, 2004). This dynamicapproach does not deny the recrudescence of primitivedefense mechanisms (à la Feinberg), after right-braindamage, but challenges the idea that brain injury gen-erates a static regression to a previous developmentalstage, abolishing the possibility of a more complexfunctioning. Even in psychoanalysis itself, regressionis a functional , not a structural, clinical concept. Aview like this also ignores the complex relationshipbetween context and brain functioning, a point stressedby so-called cultural neuropsychology (i.e. Ylvisaker & Feeney, 1998), which has been progressively incor-porated in the neuropsychological rehabilitation litera-ture (Salas, 2008b; Yeates et al., 2008).

A dynamic approach toward defense mechanismsalso raises other questions regarding Feinberg’sproposal. Is the recrudescence of primitive defensemechanisms restricted to the awareness of post-injurydisabilities? Are primitive defenses present in other domains, such as interpersonal conflicts? Do other contextual situations elicit, or facilitate, the use of mature defenses in the same patients? Clarificationof this point is crucial for the understanding of theneural basis of defense mechanisms. If we find that

after right-sided lesions patients still use both types of defense, then the hypothesis that each defense mecha-nism is lateralized to a specific hemisphere cannot besustained. If we approach the problem from our pointof view, acknowledging the dynamic nature of defensemechanisms used in brain-injury patients, the questionseems to be: which are the components that, after right-brain damage, generate the so-called recrudescence of primitive defense mechanisms?

In our opinion, a possible key to understandingthe deployment of primitive defense mechanisms isthe role of the right hemisphere in the regulation of arousal. A recrudescence  does not imply that maturedefenses are abolished, but that immature defensesare exacerbated . If we have a patient who previously

tended to use mature defenses, what might cause theshift to using immature defenses more often? We sug-gest that in order to use mature defenses, we need to becapable of tolerating an amount of negative arousal, asa means of generating psychological conflict, but not ina survival situation that requires immediate discharge.Freed (2002) has stressed this point before, by sug-gesting that brain-injury patients have difficulties inusing signal anxiety, experiencing automatic anxietyinstead. In other words, anxiety cannot be used by theego as an anticipatory reaction that signals danger, thusmobilizing ego-defensive capacities. On the contrary,the ego is overwhelmed by excessive stimulation that

the organism is incapable of modulating (Freed, 2002,p. 63).

Our hypothesis, in contrast to Feinberg’s, suggeststhat the recrudescence of primitive defense mechanismsmay be caused by a failure in the capacity to regulate theintensity of arousal and negative emotional states. Thiselevated arousal would imply a dampening of higher cognitive processes (needed for mature defenses), anda “survival” situation, activating primitive defensesthat are able to restore the organism’s homeostasis bydifferent means. In consequence, we propose that it isnot that primitive defenses (left-lateralized accordingto Feinberg) “take over” because of damage to the righthemisphere, but that damage to the right hemisphereimpairs the arousal regulation capacity, which formsone component of mature defenses. This then producesa setting in which left-lateralized components (e.g.,determinate reasoning) operate in a primitive fashion (e.g., delusional, promoting discharge and immediatealleviation of negative affect). In this sense, Feinberg’slateralization argument appears limited by suggestingthat primitive defense mechanisms are largely basedon verbal mechanisms. Verbal mechanisms, or a verbalcomponent thereof, can collaborate in the generation of both mature (e.g., rationalization) and immature (e.g.,

delusional rationalization) defense mechanisms. Theyare not the exclusive province of primitive maturedefenses. In our view, the capacity to tolerate a certainamount of negative arousal is the key factor that per-mits the use of mature defense mechanisms.

We believe that this hypothesis can accommodate toFeinberg’s observation that primitive defenses are morecommon after right-sided lesions (by virtue of disrup-tion to emotional regulation), but it also adds complex-

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 7/11

178 Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull

ity by considering the dynamic nature of defenses froma functional system perspective (Luria, 1973). We havecited a significant literature that supports the relation-ship of the right hemisphere with negative valenceemotions, physiological arousal, and the processingof somatic information. We would like to take this

hypothesis further by pointing to some studies thathave associated left-hemisphere activity with anxietyapprehension, and right- hemisphere activity with anx-ious arousal  or  somatic anxiety (Engels et al., 2007;Nitschke, Heller, & Miller, 2000).

A further exploration of this dynamic hypothesis of defense mechanisms, specifically in relation to primi-tive defenses, would potentially disentangle the preciserole of the right anterior and posterior zones. Feinbergdemonstrated that right frontal damage is related tohigher levels of delusional pathology and to somato-paraphrenia. This claim is congruent with the psycho-analytic exploration of patients with right convexity

lesions by Kaplan-Solms and Solms (2000), wherelarger lesions that involved anterior structures gener-ated more pervasive delusional symptoms and failurein reality testing (Mr. D and Mr. E). However, patientswith more posterior lesions (Mr. A, Mr. B, and Mr. C)also exhibited primitive defense mechanisms (projec-tion, splitting, and abrupt dissociation of affect). Of special interest, in the context of the right hemisphereand negative arousal, these posterior-lesioned patientsalso showed a significant difficulty in tolerating their negative emotional states, and they even lacked thecapacity to bring them to full conscious awareness,though reality testing was not as severely impaired asin the frontal cases. For Kaplan-Solms and Solms, thesymptoms observed after lesions to the right convexityare caused by a diminution in whole-object relation-ships, which generates the emergence of primitivedefenses (p. 197). If we take Feinberg’s and Kaplan-Solms & Solms’s evidence together, it is possible tosuggest: (1) right-hemisphere damage to posterior andanterior regions generates a recrudescence of primi-tive defense mechanisms; (2) right frontal-lobe lesionsgenerate more delusional symptoms than do posterior lesions, where external reality is obliterated; (3) pos-terior lesions generate an impairment in the capacity

to experience, and sustain, a negative affective statebut preserve reality testing. This suggests a regula-tory role of right frontal cortex, supported by studiesthat propose a role of this brain region in social skills(Bach, Happe, Fleminger, & Powell, 2000), emotionalprocessing (Bechara, 2004; Tranel, Bechara, & Den-burg, 2002), “hot” executive functioning (Zelazo &Cunningham, 2007), decision making (Manes et al.,2002), evaluation of beliefs (Davies, Aimola Davies, &

Coltheart, 2005; Coltheart, 2005, 2007; McKay, Lang-don, & Coltheart, 2005), reasoning under uncertainty(Goel & Vartanian, 2005), and maintaining on-lineambiguous representations (Goel, Stollstorff, Nakic,Knutson, & Grafman, 2009; Goel et al., 2007). In sum,the role of the posterior zones in assembling subjective

emotional experience seems supported by studies thatrelate this area to interoceptive feelings (Craig, 2009),corporeal awareness (Berlucchi & Aglioti, 1997), self-relatedness to the body (Tsakaris, 2009), attribution of action to the self (Blakemore & Decety, 2001; Farrer & Frith, 2002; Frith & Frith, 1999; Ruby & Decety,2001), the experience of emotion from “secondaryinducers” (Damasio, Bechara, Tranel, & Damasio,1997), and imagining other peoples’ feelings (Adolphs,2001; Adolphs, Damasio, Tranel, Cooper, & Damasio,2000).

Closing remarks

Perhaps it is necessary to conclude this commentaryby addressing Feinberg’s core proposal of what a neu-ropathology of the self is. For Feinberg, neuropatholo-gies of the self appear to have three main features: (1)there is a disturbance in the sense of self, identity, andrelatedness to others and the world; (2) they are associ-ated with confabulation; (c) they are related to braininjury. A possible limitation of Feinberg’s proposal ishis emphasis on syndromes that include confabula-tions, with less emphasis on other cases where there isno sign of confabulation but changes in the experienceof the self are evident. It would be helpful if a surveyof changes in the NPS were undertaken based on lesionsite, but focused more broadly than on confabula-tion. Along this line, we have expanded Feinberg’sunderstanding of the NPS by describing disturbancesin the sense of self  that are related to pure cognitivedeficits. One might take this argument further, con-sidering instances where only the bodily self appearsabnormally changed, with no signs of confabulation,as is observed after left parietal lesions (Luria, 1972,1973; cf. cases of supernumerary phantom limbs after stroke—McGonogle et al., 2002; Miyazawa, Hayashi,

Komiya, & Akiyama, 2004). Our final point is thus thatFeinberg’s emphasis seems to be centered on the delu-sional component, which seems likely to be merelya subgroup of the NPS, albeit containing the mostextreme cases. An all-encompassing account of the NPSshould then include syndromes where the self may bemodified, by either cognitive or somatic changes. Fur-thermore, an inclusive account should even consider modifications of the self that are not exclusively caused

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 8/11

Neuropathologies of the Self: A General Theory • Commentaries 179

by brain injury to the central nervous system, as in thecase of phantom limbs after amputation (Chen, Cohen,& Hallett, 2002; Giummarra, Gibson, Georgiou-Karis-tianis, & Bradshaw, 2007), changes in body schemaafter quadriplegia (Salas, 2010), or peripheral injury(Sacks, 1998). In sum, we believe that Feinberg’s pro-

posal of the neuropathologies of the self would increaseits value if, as a theoretical framework, it were capableof incorporating the many different ways by which theself can change after a neurological insult.

REFERENCES

Adolphs, R. (2001). The neurobiology of social cognition. Cur-rent Opinion in Neurobiology, 11: 231–239.

Adolphs, R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Cooper, G., & Damasio,

A. (2000). A role of somatosensory cortices in the visual rec-

ognition of emotions as revealed by three dimensional lesion

mapping. Neuropsychologia , 41: 119–126.

Bach, L., Happe, F., Fleminger, S., & Powell, J. (2000). Theory

of mind: Independence of executive function and the role of 

the frontal cortex in acquired brain injury. Cognitive Neuro-psychiatry, 5 (3): 175–192.

Bechara, A. (2004). The role of emotion in decision-making:

Evidence from neurological patients with orbitofrontal dam-

age. Brain and Cognition, 55: 30–40.

Benton, A., & Silvan, A. (1993). Disturbances of body schema.

In: Clinical Neuropsychology, ed. K. Heilam & E. Valen-

stein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 123–140.

Ben-Yishay, Y. (2000). Post-acute neuropsychological rehabili-

tation: A holistic perspective. In: Critical Issues in Neuro-psychology: International Handbook of Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, ed. A. L. Christensen & B. P. Uzzell. Amster-

dam: Kluwer Academic.

Berlucchi, G., & Aglioti, S. (1997). The body in the brain: Neu-

ral basis of corporeal awareness. Trends in Neuroscience, 20: 560–564.

Binder, J., Frost, J., Hammeke, T., Cox, R., Rao, S., & Prieto, T.

(1997). Human brain language areas identified by functional

magnetic resonance imaging. Journal of Neuroscience, 17

(1): 353–362.

Bion, W. (1959). Attacks on linking. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 40: 308–315.

Blakemore, S., & Decety, J. (2001). From the perception of 

action to the understanding of intention. Nature ReviewsNeuroscience, 2: 561–567.

Borod, J. (2000). The Neuropsychology of Emotion. New York:Oxford University Press.

Bromberg, P. (1996). Standing in the spaces: The multiplicity

of self and the psychoanalytic relationship. ContemporaryPsychoanalysis, 32: 509–535.

Buckner, R. (1996). Beyond HERA: Contributions of specific

prefrontal brain areas to long-term memory retrieval. Psy-chonomic Bulletin & Review, 3 (2): 149–158.

Bukobza, G. (2007). The epistemological basis of selfhood.

New Ideas in Psychology, 25: 37–65.

Carota, A., Rossetti, A., Karapanayiotides, T., & Bogousslavsky,

J. (2001). Catastrophic reaction in acute stroke: A reflex

behavior in aphasic patients. Neurology, 57: 1902–1905.

Chemerinski, E., & Robinson, R. (2000). The neuropsychiatry

of stroke. Psychosomatics, 41 (1): 5–14.

Chen, R., Cohen, L., & Hallett, M. (2002). Nervous system

reorganization following injury. Neuroscience, 111 (4):

761–773.Chi, J., Dooling, E., & Gilles, F. (1977). Gyral development of 

the human brain. Annals of Neurology, 1: 86–93.

Chiron, C., Jambeque, I., Nabbout, R., Lounes, R., Syrota, A.,

& Dulac, O. (1997). The right hemisphere is dominant in

human infants. Brain, 120: 1057–1065.

Clarici, A., & Giuliani, R. (2008). Growing up with a brain-

damaged mother: Anosognosia by proxy? Neuropsycho-analysis, 10: 59–79.

Clarkin, J., Lenzenweger, M., Yeomans, F., Levy, K., & Kern-

berg, O. (2007). An object relations model of borderline per-

sonality. Journal of Personality Disorders, 21 (5): 474–499.

Coltheart, M. (2005). Delusional belief. Australian Journal of Psychology, 57: 72–76.

Coltheart, M. (2007). The 33rd Bartlett Lecture: Cognitive

neuropsychiatry and delusional belief. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60: 1041–1062.

Cooper, S. (1998). Changing notions of defense within psycho-

analytic theory. Journal of Personality, 66 (6): 947–964.

Craig, B. (2009). How do you feel—now? The anterior insula

and human awareness. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 10:

59–70.

Craig, B. (2010). The insular cortex and subjective awareness.

In G. Prigatano (Ed.), The Study of Anosognosia. New York:

Oxford University Press, pp. 63–88.

Cramer, P. (2006). Protecting the Self: Defense Mechanisms inAction. New York: Guilford Press.

Cramer, P. (2008). Seven pillars of defense mechanisms theory.

Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 2 (5): 1963– 

1981.

Crowell, D., Jones, R., Kapuniani, L., & Nakagawa, J. (1973).

Unilateral cortical activity in newborns humans: An early

index of cerebral dominance? Science, 180: 205–208.

Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Grosset/Putnam.

Damasio, A. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. London: Heine-

mann.

Damasio, H., Bechara, A., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. (1997).

Double dissociation of emotional conditioning and emo-

tional imagery relative to the amygdala and right somato-

sensory cortex. Society for Neuroscience Abstracts, 23:1318.

Davidson, R. (1984). Affect, cognition and hemispheric spe-

cialization. In: Emotions, Cognitions and Behavior, ed. C. E.

Izard, J. Kagan, & R. Zajonic. Cambridge: Cambridge Press,

pp. 320–365.

Davidson, R. (2000a). Affective style, psychopathology and

resilience: Brain mechanisms and plasticity. American Psy-chologist , 55: 1196–1214.

Davidson, R. (2000b). Cognitive neuroscience needs affective

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 9/11

180 Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull

neuroscience (and vice versa). Brain and Cognition, 42:

89–92.

Davies, M., Aimola Davies, A., & Coltheart, M. (2005).

Anosognosia and the two-factor theory of delusion. Mind and Language, 20: 209–236.

D’Esposito, M., & Postle. B. (2002). The organization of work-

ing memory function in lateral prefrontal cortex: Evidence

from event-related potential. In: Principles of Frontal LobeFunction, ed. D. Stuss & R. Knight. Oxford: Oxford Univer-

sity Press, pp. 168–187.

Edelman, G., & Tononi, G. (2001). The Universe of Conscious-ness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. New York: Basic

Books.

Eidelberg, D., & Galaburda, A. (1984). Divergent architectonic

asymmetries in the human brain. Archives of Neurology, 41:

843–852.

Engels, A., Heller, W., Mohanty, A., Herrington, J., Banich, M.,

Webb, A., et al. (2007). Specificity of regional brain activity

in anxiety types during emotion processing. Psychophysiol-ogy, 44 (3): 352–363.

Farrer, C., & Frith, C. D. (2002). Experiencing oneself v/s

another person as being the cause of an action: The neural

correlates of the experience of agency. NeuroImage, 15:

596–603.

Farrer, C., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Frith, C. D., Decety, J., &

Jeannerod, M. (2003). Modulating the experience of agency:

A positron emission tomography study. NeuroImage, 18:

324–333.

Feigelson, C. (1993). Personality death, object loss and the

uncanny. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 74: 331– 

345.

Freed, P. (2002). Meeting of the minds: Ego reintegration after 

traumatic brain injury. Bulletin of the Menninger Clinic, 66

(1): 61–78.

Freud, A. (1936). The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense.

New York: International University Press.

Freud, S. (1894). The neuro-psychoses of defense. Standard Edition, 3: 43–61.

Freud, S. (1925). Negation. Standard Edition, 19: 235–239.

Frith, C., & Frith, U. (1999). Interacting minds: A biological

basis. Science, 286: 1692–1695.

Gainotti, G. (1997). Emotional, psychological and psychosocial

problems of aphasic patients: An introduction. Aphasiology,

11 (7): 635–650.

Gainotti, G. (2006). Unconscious emotional memories and the

right hemisphere. In: Psychoanalysis and Neuroscience, ed.

M. Mancia. Milan: Springer, pp. 151–173.

Gazzaniga, M. (2000). Cerebral specialization and interhemi-

spheric communication: Does the corpus callosum enablethe human condition? Brain, 123: 1293–1326.

Gazzaniga, M., & Smylie, C. (1984). Dissociation of language

and cognition. Brain, 107: 145–153.

Gazzaniga, M., & Sperry, R. (1967). Language after section of 

the cerebral comissures. Brain, 90: 131–147.

Geschwind, N., & Galaburda, A. (1987). Cerebral Lateraliza-tion: Biological Mechanisms, Associations, and Pathology.

Boston, MA: MIT Press.

Giummarra, M., Gibson, S., Georgiou-Karistianis, N., &

Bradshaw, J. (2007). Central mechanisms in phantom limb

perception: The past, present and future. Brain ResearchReviews, 54: 219–232.

Goel, V., & Dolan, R. (2004). Differential involvement of left

prefrontal cortex in inductive and deductive reasoning. Cog-nition, 93: B109–B121.

Goel, V., Stollstorff, M., Nakic, M., Knutson, K., & Grafman,

J. (2009). A role of right ventrolateral prefrontal cortex inreasoning about indeterminate relations. Neuropsychologia ,

47: 2790–2797.

Goel, V., Tierney, M., Sheesley, L., Bartolo, A., Vartanian, O.,

& Grafman, J. (2007). Hemispheric specialization in human

prefrontal cortex for resolving certain and uncertain infer-

ences. Cerebral Cortex, 17: 2245–2250.

Goel, V., & Vartanian, O. (2005). Dissociating the roles of right

ventral lateral and dorsal lateral prefrontal cortex in genera-

tion and maintenance of hypothesis in set shifting. Cerebral Cortex, 15: 1170–1177.

Goldin, P., McRae, K., Ramel, W., & Gross, J. (2008). The neu-

ral bases of emotion regulation: Reappraisal and suppression

of negative emotion. Biological Psychiatry, 63: 577–586.

Goldstein, K. (1956). The Organism. New York: Zone Books,

1995.

Hartmann, H. (1958). Ego Psychology and the Problem of Adaptation. New York: International Universities Press.

Heilman, K., Schwartz, H., & Watson, R. (1978). Hypoarousal

in patients with the neglect syndrome and emotional indif-

ference. Neurology, 28: 229–232.

Heller, W. (1990). The neuropsychology of emotion: Develop-

mental patterns and implications for psychopathology. In:

Psychological and Biological Approaches to Emotion, ed.

N. Stein, B. Leventhal, & T. Trabasso. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-

rence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 167–211.

Heller, W. (1993). Neuropsychological mechanism of indi-

vidual differences in emotion, personality and arousal. Neu-ropsychology, 7: 476–489.

Heller, W., Nitschke, J., & Lindsay, D. (1997). Neuropsycho-

logical correlates of arousal in self-reported emotion. Cogni-tion and Emotion, 11: 383–402.

Hofer, M. (2005). The psychobiology of early attachment.

Clinical Neuroscience Research, 4: 291–300

Jackson, J. H. (1884). Evolution and dissolution of the nervous

system. In: Selected Writings of John Hughlings Jackson,

ed. J. Taylor. London: Staples Press, 1958, pp 45–75.

Jacobson, E. (1964). The Self and the Object World . New York:

International Universities Press.

Kaplan-Solms, K., & Solms, M. (2000). Clinical Studies inNeuro-Psychoanalysis. Introduction to a Depth Neuropsy-

chology. London: Karnac.Kapur, N. (1996). Injured Brains of Medical Minds: Views fromWithin. New York: Oxford University Press.

Kernberg, O. (1986) Identification and its vicissitudes as

observed in psychosis. International Journal of Psycho-analysis, 67: 147–159.

Kinsbourne, M., & Bemporad, B. (1984). Lateralization of 

emotions: A model and the evidence. In: The Psychobiologyof Affective Development, ed. N. Fox & R. Davidson. Hills-

dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 259–291.

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 10/11

Neuropathologies of the Self: A General Theory • Commentaries 181

Klein, M. (1935). A contribution to the psychogenesis of manic-

depressive states. International Journal of Psychoanalysis,

16: 145–174.

Klein, M. (1946). Notes on some schizoid mechanisms. Inter-national Journal of Psychoanalysis, 27: 99–110.

Leary, M. (2004). What is the Self? A plea for clarity. Self and Identity, 3: 1–3.

Lewis, L. (1999). Transference and countertransference inpsychotherapy with adults having traumatic brain injury.

In: Psychotherapeutic Interventions for Adults with BrainInjury or Stroke: A Clinician’s Treatment Resource, ed. K. G.

Langer, L. Laatsch, & L. Lewis. Madison, CT: Psychologi-

cal Press, pp. 113–130.

Liotti, M., & Tucker, D. (1992). Right hemisphere sensitivity

to arousal and depression. Brain and Cognition, 18: 138– 

151.

Luria, A. (1972). The Man with a Shattered World: The Historyof a Brain Wound . New York: Basic Books.

Luria, A. (1973). The Working Brain. An Introduction to Neuro-psychology. New York: Basic Books.

Manes, F., Shahakian, B., Clark, L., Rogers, R., Antoun, N., &

Aitken, M. (2002). Decision making processes following

damage to the prefrontal cortex. Brain, 125: 624–639.

Marcel, A., Tegnér, R., & Nimmo-Smith, I. (2004). Anosogno-

sia for plegia: Specificity, extension, partiality and disunity

of bodily unawareness. Cortex, 40: 19–40.

McCarthy, J. (2004). Primitive anxiety and countertransference

engagement. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 21 (4): 618–621.

McGonogle, D., Hanninen, R., Salenius, S., Hari, R., Frack-

owiak, R., & Frith, C. (2002). Whose arm is it anyway? An

fMRI case study of supernumerary limb. Brain, 125 (6):

1265–1274.

McKay, R., Langdon, R., & Coltheart, M. (2005). “Sleights of 

mind”: Delusions, defenses and self-deception. CognitiveNeuropsychiatry, 10: 305–326.

Milrod, D. (2002). The concept of the self and the self represen-

tation. Neuropsychoanalysis , 4 (1): 7–23.

Mitchell, S. (1993). Hope and Dread in Psychoanalysis. New

York: Basic Books.

Miyazawa, N., Hayashi, M., Komiya, K., & Akiyama, I. (2004).

Supernumerary phantom limbs associated with left hemi-

spheric stroke: Case report and review of the literature.

Neurosurgery, 54 (1): 228–231.

Modell, A. (1993). The Private Self . Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Moss, A., & Turnbull, O. (1996). Hatred of the hemiparetic

limbs (misoplegia) in a 10 year old child. Journal of Neurol-ogy, Neurosurgery, & Psychiatry, 61: 210–211.

Moss, S. (1972). Recovery with Aphasia: The Aftermath of MyStroke. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

Nitschke, J., Heller, W., & Miller, G. (2000). Anxiety, stress and

cortical function. In: The Neuropsychology of Emotion, ed.

J. Borod. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 298–319.

Northoff, G., & Boeker, H. (2006). Principles of neural integra-

tion and defense mechanisms: Neuropsychoanalytic hypoth-

esis. Neuropsychoanalysis , 8 (1): 69–84.

Ochsner, K., Bunge, S., Gross, J., & Gabrieli, J. (2002).

Rethinking feelings: An fMRI study of the cognitive regu-

lation of emotion. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14:

1215–1229.

Panksepp, J. (2002). The Self and “its” vicissitudes: Critique of 

commentaries. Neuropsychoanalysis , 4 (1): 44–61.

Paulesu, E., Frith, C., & Frackowiak, R. (1993). The neural cor-

relates of the verbal component of working memory. Nature,

362: 342–345.

Ramachandran, V., & Blakeslee, S. (1998). Phantoms in theBrain: Human Nature and the Architecture of the Mind .London: Fourth State.

Ruby, P., & Decety, J. (2001). Effect of subjective perspective

during simulation of action: A PET investigation of agency.

Nature Neuroscience, 4: 546–550.

Sackeim, H., Greenberg, M., Weiman, A., Gur, R., Hunger-

buhler, J., & Geschwind, N. (1982). Hemispheric asym-

metry in the expression of positive and negative emotions:

Neurologic evidence. Archives of Neurology, 39: 210– 

218.

Sacks, O. (1998). A Leg to Stand On. New York: Touchstone.

Salas, C. (2008a). Psicoterapia e intervenciones terapéuticas en

sobrevivientes de lesión cerebral adquirida. Revista Chilenade Neuro-Psiquiatria, 46 (4): 293–300.

Salas, C. (2008b). Elementos relacionales en la rehabilitacion de

sobrevivientes de lesion cerebral adquirida. Alianza de tra-

bajo, transferencia y contratransferencia, usos del terapeuta.Revista Gaceta Psiquiatria Universitaria, 4 (2): 214–220.

Salas, C. (2009). La reconstrucción de identidad en sobrevivi-

entes de traumatismo cráneo-encefálico. Una conversación

con Mark Ylvisaker. Revista Chilena de Neuro-Psiquiatria,

4 (1): 64–74.

Salas, C. (2010). Naturaleza muerta. Transformaciones psiqui-

cas en un caso de tretraplejia. Revista Chilena de Neuropsi-cologia, 5 (2): 160–169.

Schore, A. (2003). Clinical implications of a psychoneurobio-

logical model of projective identification. In: Affect Regula-tion and the Repair of the Self. New York: W.W. Norton, pp.

58–107.

Silberman, E., & Weingartner, H. (1986). Hemispheric lateral-

ization of functions related to emotion. Brain and Cognition,

5: 322–353.

Starkstein, S., Fedoroff, J., Price, T., Leiguarda, R., & Robin-

son, R. (1993). Catastrophic reaction after cerebrovascular 

lesions: Frequency, correlates, and validation of a scale.

Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience, 5:

189–194.

Stern, D. (1997). Handedness and the lateral distribution of 

conversion reactions. Journal of Nervous Mental Disorders, 164: 122–188.

Stern, S. (2002). The self as a relational structure: A dialoguewith multiple self theory. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 12 (5):

693–714.

Stolorow, R., & Atwood, G. (1992). Contexts of Being: TheIntersubjective Foundations of Psychological Life. Hills-

dale, NJ: Analytic Press.

Tranel, D., Bechara, A., & Denburg, N. (2002). Asymmetrical

functional roles of right and left ventromedial prefrontal

cortices in social conduct, decision making and emotional

processing. Cortex, 38: 589–612.

8/7/2019 In Self Defense: disruptions in the sense of self, laterality and primitive defenses

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/in-self-defense-disruptions-in-the-sense-of-self-laterality-and-primitive 11/11

182 Christian Salas & Oliver H. Turnbull

Tsakaris, M. (2009). My body in the brain: A neurocogni-

tive model of body-ownership. Neuropsychologia , 48 (3):

703–712.Tucker, D. (1981). Lateral brain function, emotion and concep-

tualization. Psychological Bulletin, 89 (1): 19–46.

Tucker, D., & Williamson, P. (1984). Asymmetrical neural

control systems in human self regulation. Psychological 

Review, 91: 185–215.Tulving, E. (1985). Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psy-

chology, 26: 1–12.

Tulving, E. (1993). Self-Knowledge of an amnesic individual is

represented abstractly: The mental representation of trait and

autobiographical knowledge about the self. In: The Mental Representation of Trait and Autobiographical Knowledgeabout the Self , ed. T. Srull & R. Wyer. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-

rence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 147–156.

Turnbull, O., Zois, E., Kaplan-Solms, K., & Solms, M. (2007).

The developing transference in amnesia: Changes in inter-

personal relationship, despite profound episodic-memory

loss. Neuropsychoanalysis , 8 (2): 199–204.

Vaillant, G. E. (1994). Ego mechanisms of defense and person-

ality psychopathology. Journal of Abnormal Psychology,

103 (1): 44–50.

Varley, R., & Siegal, M. (2000). Evidence for cognition without

grammar from causal reasoning and “theory of mind” in

agrammatic aphasic patient. Current Biology, 10: 723–726.

Westen, D. (1992) The cognitive Self and the psychoanalytic

Self: Can we put our selves together? Psychological Inquiry,

3 (1): 1–13.

Winnicott, D. (1965). The Maturational Processes and theFacilitating Environment . Madison, CT: International Uni-

versities Press.Wilson, B. (1999). Case Studies in Neuropsychological Reha-

bilitation. New York: Oxford University Press.

Yeates, G., Hamill, M., Sutton, L., Psalia, K., Gracey, F.,

Mohamed, S., et al. (2008). Dysexecutive problems and

interpersonal relating following frontal brain injury: Refor-

mulation and compensation in cognitive analytic therapy

(CAT). Neuropsychoanalysis , 10: 43–58.

Ylvisaker, M., & Feeney, T. (1998). Collaborative Brain InjuryIntervention: Positive Everyday Routines. San Diego: Sin-

gular Publishing.

Ylvisaker, M., & Feeney, T. (2000). Reconstruction of identity

after brain injury. Brain Impairment , 1 (1): 12–28.

Zelazo, P., & Cunningham, W. (2007). Executive function.

Mechanisms underlying emotion regulation. In: Handbook of Emotion Regulation, ed. J. Gross. New York: Guilford

Press, pp. 135–158.