ethical considerations in clinical training, care and research in psychopharmacology

12
Ethical considerations in clinical training, care and research in psychopharmacology Rael D. Strous 1,2 1 Beer Yaakov Mental Health Center, Israel 2 Sackler Faculty of Medicine, Tel Aviv University, Israel Abstract Psychopharmacology is a powerful tool in psychiatry; however, it is one that demands responsibility in order to deal with the ethical complexities that accompany advances in the field. It is important that questions are asked and that ethical mindfulness and sensitivity are developed along with clinical skills. In order to cultivate and deepen ethical awareness and subsequently solve issues in optimal fashion, investment should be made in the development of an ethical decision-making process as well as in education in the ethics of psychopharmacology to trainees in the field at all stages of their educational development. A clear approach to identifying ethical problems, engaging various ethical concepts in considering solutions and then applying these principles in problem resolution is demanded. An open- ness in identifying and exploring issues has become crucial to the future development and maturation of psychopharmacologists, both research and clinical. Consideration must be given to the social implications of psychopharmacological practice, with the best interests of patients always paramount. From both a research and clinical perspective, psychopharmacology has to be practised with fairness, sensitivity and ethical relevance to all. While ethical issues related to psychopharmacological practice are varied and plentiful, this review focuses on advances in technology and biological sciences, personal integrity, special populations, and education and training. Received 3 May 2010 ; Reviewed 26 May 2010 ; Revised 11 August 2010 ; Accepted 14 August 2010 ; First published online 22 September 2010 Key words : Ethics, informed consent, mindfulness, psychopharmacology, responsibility. Introduction The practice of psychiatry is a noble endeavour. It has been made all the more effective with breakthroughs in evidence-based psychopharmacology management options over the past 50 years. In fact, never in the history of psychiatry has so much hope been offered to long-suffering patients with mental illness, and never in the history of mental illness have so many been offered such relief by means of rational pharmaco- logical interventions. This flash of optimism, however, is tempered by a minefield of potential dangers in the arena of ethical practice. It is clear that knowledge and scientific advances may be transformed into powerful tools that demand responsibility. It is here that ethics contributes to dealing with the inevitable challenges, providing a framework for coping with the issues that arise naturally out of research and clinical care of in- dividuals with mental illness. Often there are no clear solutions. While legislation can be helpful in guiding practitioners in some cases, it is only one of the many sources of moral knowledge about how to engage ethically in the psychopharmacological field. In many instances, ethical decisions lie in the hands of indi- vidual doctors. What is of utmost importance is that questions are asked and that ethical awareness be- comes as important in clinical skill development as other more explicit physician skills such as heart auscultations and mental status examinations. While the challenges are formidable, there is hope, and the literature on the subject is gradually accumulating as sensitivity regarding the importance of the issues increases. Undoubtedly, the powers that exist in the hands of a psychopharmacologist today are considerable. With the administration of a few pills, over time, personality and behaviour can be affected markedly. Address for correspondence : R. D. Strous, M.D., Director Chronic Inpatient Unit, Beer Yaakov Mental Health Center, PO Box 1, Beer Yaakov 70350, Israel. Tel. : 972-8-9258280 Fax : 972-8-9258224 Email : [email protected] International Journal of Neuropsychopharmacology (2011), 14, 413–424. f CINP 2010 doi:10.1017/S1461145710001112 REVIEW

Upload: rael-d

Post on 09-Dec-2016

213 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Ethical considerations in clinical training,care and research in psychopharmacology

Rael D. Strous1,2

1 Beer Yaakov Mental Health Center, Israel2 Sackler Faculty of Medicine, Tel Aviv University, Israel

Abstract

Psychopharmacology is a powerful tool in psychiatry ; however, it is one that demands responsibility in

order to deal with the ethical complexities that accompany advances in the field. It is important that

questions are asked and that ethical mindfulness and sensitivity are developed along with clinical skills.

In order to cultivate and deepen ethical awareness and subsequently solve issues in optimal fashion,

investment should be made in the development of an ethical decision-making process as well as in

education in the ethics of psychopharmacology to trainees in the field at all stages of their educational

development. A clear approach to identifying ethical problems, engaging various ethical concepts in

considering solutions and then applying these principles in problem resolution is demanded. An open-

ness in identifying and exploring issues has become crucial to the future development and maturation of

psychopharmacologists, both research and clinical. Consideration must be given to the social implications

of psychopharmacological practice, with the best interests of patients always paramount. From both a

research and clinical perspective, psychopharmacology has to be practised with fairness, sensitivity and

ethical relevance to all. While ethical issues related to psychopharmacological practice are varied and

plentiful, this review focuses on advances in technology and biological sciences, personal integrity, special

populations, and education and training.

Received 3 May 2010 ; Reviewed 26 May 2010 ; Revised 11 August 2010 ; Accepted 14 August 2010 ;

First published online 22 September 2010

Key words : Ethics, informed consent, mindfulness, psychopharmacology, responsibility.

Introduction

The practice of psychiatry is a noble endeavour. It has

been made all the more effective with breakthroughs

in evidence-based psychopharmacology management

options over the past 50 years. In fact, never in the

history of psychiatry has so much hope been offered to

long-suffering patients with mental illness, and never

in the history of mental illness have so many been

offered such relief by means of rational pharmaco-

logical interventions. This flash of optimism, however,

is tempered by a minefield of potential dangers in the

arena of ethical practice. It is clear that knowledge and

scientific advances may be transformed into powerful

tools that demand responsibility. It is here that ethics

contributes to dealing with the inevitable challenges,

providing a framework for coping with the issues that

arise naturally out of research and clinical care of in-

dividuals with mental illness. Often there are no clear

solutions. While legislation can be helpful in guiding

practitioners in some cases, it is only one of the many

sources of moral knowledge about how to engage

ethically in the psychopharmacological field. In many

instances, ethical decisions lie in the hands of indi-

vidual doctors. What is of utmost importance is that

questions are asked and that ethical awareness be-

comes as important in clinical skill development as

other more explicit physician skills such as heart

auscultations and mental status examinations. While

the challenges are formidable, there is hope, and the

literature on the subject is gradually accumulating

as sensitivity regarding the importance of the issues

increases.

Undoubtedly, the powers that exist in the hands

of a psychopharmacologist today are considerable.

With the administration of a few pills, over time,

personality and behaviour can be affected markedly.

Address for correspondence : R. D. Strous, M.D., Director Chronic

Inpatient Unit, Beer Yaakov Mental Health Center, PO Box 1,

Beer Yaakov 70350, Israel.

Tel. : 972-8-9258280 Fax : 972-8-9258224

Email : [email protected]

International Journal of Neuropsychopharmacology (2011), 14, 413–424. f CINP 2010doi:10.1017/S1461145710001112

REVIEW

Accompanying this power, however, is an unwritten

social contract between the psychopharmacologist and

the community. The administration of medications

has to be carried out with the utmost ethical and pro-

fessional behaviour, with dedication, commitment and

accountability. Rank implies obligation. Psychiatrists

and psychopharmacologists who engage in medica-

tion administration need to be aware of the ethical

issues that are inextricably linked with its practice.

It is no more important to be aware of how a dopa-

mine blocker affects neurotransmitter balance than

it is crucial to obtain optimal informed consent for

any medication administration, and it is no more

important to be aware of doses of SSRI medication

management for the treatment of OCD and de-

pression than it is to be aware of potential conflicting

interests in relationships with the pharmaceutical

industry and drug representative-sponsored ward

lunches.

Awareness of the issues and their repercussions is

integral to the critical development of ‘ethical mind-

fulness’ (Guillemin et al. 2009). While ethical concerns

are varied and plentiful, a consistent approach in

identifying the ethical problem, engaging various

ethical concepts in considering solutions and then

applying these principles in problem resolution is

demanded. Certain ethical issues may be solved in

different ways depending on factors such as time,

ethnicity and cultural considerations (Lombera & Illes,

2009). However, other central concepts of medical

ethics involved in ethical psychopharmacological

practice are not bound in these ways.

Given the length of such a discussion, it would

be impossible to explore in any depth the wealth of

ethical issues appertaining to the ethics of psycho-

pharmacological practice in this framework. The in-

tention here is to touch on a few of the more relevant

and current concerns relating to ethical practice, and

to increase awareness of the pertinent issues, rather

than to solve each individual challenge. The analysis

will focus on advances in technology and biological

sciences, integrity, special populations, and education

and training. While the focus of the discussion is

aimed towards clinicians engaged in psychopharma-

cological practice, the issues also have relevance

to those engaged in psychopharmacological research

who have no direct clinical involvement.

Ethical issues resulting from advances in

technology and biological sciences

During my eighty-seven years I have witnessed a whole

succession of technological revolutions. But none of them has

done away with the need for character in the individual or

the ability to think.

Bernard Mannes Baruch (American statesman, 1870–1965)

Man is an animal with primary instincts of survival.

Consequently his ingenuity has developed first and his soul

afterwards. The progress of science is far ahead of man’s

ethical behavior.

Charlie Chaplin (English actor and director, 1889–1977)

Pharmacogenetics

Research in pharmacogenetics has proliferated in the

past 10–20 years. In the future the field promises to

be able to (and in many cases already does) predict

individual response to various medications including

efficacy, time to response and side-effect profile. This

body of research is predicated in major part on the fact

that metabolism and sensitivity to medication differs

between individuals due to one-base polymorphisms

of drug-metabolizing enzymes. Genotyping of these

enzymes prior to drug administration would enable

the psychopharmacologist to predict individual medi-

cation response and possible adverse reactions. This in

turn would enable tailor-made therapy and usher in

the era of ‘ individualized’ medicine (Shastry, 2006).

However, along with often prohibitive costs are

problems of an ethical nature. While results give great

hope to those who are long-suffering in terms of

medication choice that assures an earlier and better

response, there remains a great deal of uncertainty

regarding the extrapolation of results, much of which

is in the early stages and seldom replicated. Moreover,

how can confidentiality of genetic information be

protected? How should informed consent be conduc-

ted? Should the level of understanding be kept at a

higher standard? What are the potential repercussions

of revealing pharmacogenetic information to families

or health insurance agents? Since the results and ap-

plication of this research will inevitably have immense

clinical, economic and social implications, it is critical

that potential ethical problems are identified early and

addressed.

While not all may agree, genetic research needs to

be held to a higher standard based on the potential

effects on future generations from improper and

potential misuse of information in large databases re-

garding benefits and rights of individuals. The poten-

tial for gross boundary violations exists when dealing

with genetic information, since much becomes known

about family, community and ethnic groups, present-

ing ethical challenges if improperly disseminated.

Furthermore, these risks are amplified by increased

complexity of healthcare delivery systems. Permission

414 R. D. Strous

to receive various medicines might be limited or

revoked based on the genetic potential of toxicity or

efficacy. Thus, while it would be extremely improb-

able that genetic markers would state that a person has

no chance of responding or a 100% chance of toxicity,

a health insurance fund may restrict a medication

despite a small chance of efficacy (Breckenridge et al.

2004). Since most people have difficulty dealing with

probabilities, a sensitive and comprehensive approach

as to how to present this pharmacogenetic information

to patients must be developed. Increasing awareness

of the issues is critical : pharmacogenetics is in its

infancy, but promises to dictate much in the future.

Brain stimulation

Apart from ECT, which has been a mainstay of psy-

chiatric treatment for the past 70 years, the past decade

has seen the relatively rapid innovation of brain

stimulation, electrical and magnetic, in the manage-

ment of various neuropsychiatric illnesses. This has

included techniques such as transcranial magnetic

stimulation (TMS), transcranial direct current stimu-

lation, vagus nerve stimulation (VNS) and deep-brain

stimulation (DBS) (used especially in the management

of Parkinson’s disease). In DBS, electrodes are im-

planted surgically in one or more brain areas of

relevance to the illness. These electrodes are then

connected to a battery-operated stimulator and placed

in the chest near the clavicular area. Activation of

the electrodes, which can be accomplished manually,

subsequently stimulates the relevant areas of the brain.

Ethical issues with these procedures are numerous.

Based on psychiatry’s experience with psychosurgery,

it becomes vital to explore these issues. First, it re-

mains unclear precisely how these techniques work in

the altering of mental states of relevance to thought,

behaviour and personality. It is also unclear which

brain sites are most optimal for effects and at what

frequency stimulation should be delivered (Glannon,

2009). The ethical issue becomes whether it is accept-

able to induce certain effects without knowing the

precise mechanisms of action and long-term effects.

While other such examples of treatments in psychiatry

exist without clearly defined modes of action (includ-

ing various psychotropic medications and ECT), they

nevertheless remain in use since their efficacy and

safety profile is evidence-based. However, the quest

to unravel their modes of action should continue.

Second, many positive reports of these techniques are

based on ‘selective publishing’ with an excessive

reliance on single-patient reports, thus introducing

bias, since there are no cohort studies upon which

to rely (Schlaepfer & Fins, 2010). Third, based on the

unique effects, it has been reported that some patients

select management with DBS for disabling motor

effects from illnesses such as Parkinson’s disease, only

to find themselves disabled by severely impaired

psychiatric states (Glannon, 2009). Issues of autonomy,

competence, the role and opinion of the physician, and

informed consent thus become critical, especially if

the individual chooses the dysfunctional mental state

over that of the dysfunctional motor state (Glannon,

2009).

Since the field of DBS is in its infancy, but potential

implications and effects of its management are sig-

nificant, groups have met to discuss ethical implica-

tions before the field expands exponentially. One such

group recommended that further studies of the effi-

cacy and safety of DBS compared to other treatments

should be done and that for disorders of mood, be-

haviour and thought, DBS should only be used in the

context of carefully designed research trials with the

highest level of scientific standards (Rabins et al. 2009).

DBS should also be carried out only by multi-

disciplinary teams and with adults. One also has to

ensure that the excitement surrounding DBS does not

exclude future consideration of tried and tested tech-

niques such as ECT which, while it has engendered

a negative reputation amongst the public in many

countries due to outmoded misconceptions, might be

excluded as a treatment option, despite exciting tech-

nological developments in its use. Particular attention

needs to be given to issues of informed consent, in-

cluding discussion of what is and is not known about

DBS. Furthermore, there should be no financial bar-

riers to the inclusion of those suitable and it should be

clear who is responsible for follow-up and removal of

the device if necessary (Rabins et al. 2009). Others have

added that disclosure of any potential conflicts of

interest by investigators or clinicians is important and

that the procedure should never be used for political,

social or law-enforcement purposes (Merkel et al.

2007 ; Nuttin et al. 2002). Implementation of various

safeguarding guidelines will be challenging; however,

if employed sensibly they will only enhance the con-

tribution of this exciting new field.

Cognitive enhancement

Perhaps no field in psychiatry has managed to occupy

the attention of the public and media as much as

psychopharmacology’s potential to offer cognitive

enhancement or ‘cosmetic pharmacological ’ benefits

(a term coined by Peter Kramer). These medications

have been referred to as ‘lifestyle drugs’ and may be

The ethical psychopharmacologist 415

defined as medications used to satisfy a non-medical

or non-health-related purpose (Flower, 2004). Indi-

viduals who take such medications are not ‘sick’

in the traditional sense and the question becomes

when precisely a ‘need’ becomes an ‘illness’ requiring

medication. Such designer medications target specific

neurobiological processes that control cognition and

emotions and may be used for purposes of spiritual

experience, shyness, alertness, low self-esteem, confi-

dence, memory and other similar cognitive enhance-

ments (e.g. Stein, 2005). While this is not a new

phenomenon, today much of their use is evidence-

based. However, many questions of an ethical nature

are raised including what level of adverse effects is

acceptable. It should be borne in mind that many

other day-to-day practices continue to proliferate de-

spite some element of danger, e.g. cars, smoking and

alcohol use (Flower, 2004).

Since physicians are ultimately the gatekeepers of

the proliferation of these medications, several ethical

issues need to be addressed. When should attempts

be made to limit their use, if at all? Is it ethically per-

missible to investigate long-term use of enhancers in

healthy individuals? One of the most commonly used

substances of relevance includes methylphenidate

whose use in various school districts and on college

campuses far exceeds the highest estimate of the

prevalence of attention deficit hyperactivity disorder

(Diller, 1996). Following their widespread use, em-

ployers and educators may prefer those who are

enhanced over those who are not enhanced, or vice

versa. Other ethical issues include the potential pre-

scription of its use as a form of ‘neurocorrection’ by

the justice system, whether it is followed voluntarily

or not. Can parents decide to ‘neuro-enhance’ their

children with or without their consent? What are the

social implications, especially if there is unfair access

to such ‘enhancers’?

Farah and colleagues (2004) have defined four

broad areas of ethical relevance with the use of

neurocognitive enhancement. These include factors of

safety (unanticipated complications resulting from

the complex process of neurocognitive enhancement),

coercion (potential pressure on the individual to

enhance cognitive function by employers, educational

facilities, family), distributive justice (unfair allocation

due to cost or social inequality) and personhood issues

(conflict with who we are and what it is to value a

meaningful life and its responsibilities and imperfec-

tions). A central ethical dilemma is the conflict be-

tween improving one’s productivity and function via

medication administration vs. the value of human

dignity and greater investment and effort in one’s

activities and challenges (Farah et al. 2004). Does this

demand policy development and legislation or should

this be left to the decision of the psychopharmacolo-

gist? It would become the physician’s responsibility

to carefully evaluate each individual case for medical

indication, since he/she would be the gatekeeper for

medication administration. This would include full

informed consent, including knowledge of the medi-

cation’s dependence potential, and acknowledging

that not all details about potential risks are known

both in the healthy and ill.

Integrity and the psychopharmacologist

You would expect different cultures to develop different sorts

of ethics and obviously they have ; that doesn’t mean that you

can’t think of overarching ethical principles you would want

people to follow in all kinds of places.

Peter Singer (Australian philosopher, b. 1946)

Relationship with the pharmaceutical industry

An issue that has taken centre stage in the past few

years is the relationship between psychopharma-

cologists, both clinical and research, and the pharma-

ceutical industry. Interestingly it is the media who,

following several celebrated episodes of alleged con-

flicts of interest by psychopharmacology practitioners,

have led the way by forcing the issue to the front stage

of the ethical debate. The issue is complex since a re-

lationship with the industry is unavoidable, given the

nature of required research and information distri-

bution following product approval. At each stage in

this interaction, however, various precautions are de-

manded and become critical for the ethical practice of

psychopharmacology. Often these issues are subtle,

but the ‘slippery slope’ beckons. From the public’s

perspective, there are conflicting reports on whether

relationships with industry affect medical care. One

prominent study among patients enrolled in cancer

research trials indicated that most were not concerned

about financial ties between researchers, medical cen-

tres and drug companies (Hampson et al. 2006). They

indicated that such knowledge would not necessarily

have affected study enrolment. A more recent study,

however, showed that patients believe that financial

ties, including recruitment incentives, do indeed

influence professional behaviour and impair study

quality and therefore should be disclosed. Such

financial ties may even influence interest in study

participation (Licurse et al. 2010). The consensus ap-

pears to be in step with the later study, bearing in

mind that the former study investigated patients with

416 R. D. Strous

cancer, an illness with which patients will often pur-

sue all available new treatment opportunities, given

that in many cases little long-term hope is offered.

While the problem of conflicts of interest exists in

all fields of medicine, many claim that the problem is

especially prevalent in psychiatry, given the psycho-

pharmacology focus of many pharmaceutical compa-

nies (Insel, 2010). For example, antidepressants and

antipsychotics are two of the top five classes of medi-

cations sold in the USA, with sales of over $25 billion

in 2008 (Insel, 2010). Since differences in efficacy

between medications are becoming slight, the role

of marketing and influence of decision-makers and

perceived field-leaders over other physicians and the

public are becoming increasingly important. Public

trust in psychiatrists has been affected by serious ac-

cusations of conflicts of interest arising from failure to

report such conflicts. In a 2005 review of 397 published

reports of clinical trials in four psychiatric journals,

Perlis et al. (2005) found that 60% of papers had

industry funding and 47% had at least one author

reporting a financial relationship with the pharma-

ceutical industry. Furthermore, it was noted that

articles with industry support are approximately five

times more likely to report positive results. While a

relationship with industry in a speaking capacity is

not unethical per se, it becomes unethical not to report

such an association. For example, as shockingly re-

ported by Tom Insel, of the 20 work group members

who authored the American Psychiatric Association

guidelines for the treatment of schizophrenia, bipolar

disorder, and major depressive disorder, 90% had

financial ties to industry, 72% as consultants. None

of these relationships were disclosed (Cosgrove et al.

2009).

While dialogue between clinical and research

scientists is critical, it is important to ensure that the

association remains ethical and free of conflicts of

interest. The stakes are too high and the demands for

progress too vital to waste the potential symbiotic re-

lationship. Constant awareness of these dangers at all

levels is necessary and psychiatrists need to ensure

transparency by means of disclosure of these inter-

actions with industry, both with respect to financial

compensation received and any other associated con-

flict of interest (Mitchell, 2009). In addition, psychiatric

educators need to develop creative methods for edu-

cating medical students and residents about industry’s

marketing practices so that they may cope with

marketing biases in therapeutic information (Yager &

Feinstein, 2010). Other more subtle but nevertheless

profound influences include the phenomenon of gift-

giving to psychopharmacologists (Stokamer, 2003).

The practice is endemic to the profession. It is always

fascinating to record how many times a name of a

commercial medication product or company appears

in a doctor’s office. The existence of these subtle, al-

most subliminal forms of advertising is widespread.

‘Direct to consumer’ advertising may also be ethically

problematic, often basing itself on the public’s desire

for a quick fix (McHenry, 2006). Along these lines,

psychopharmacologists need to beware of the overuse

of medications when there are no good indications

and when non-pharmacological measures might be

just as effective, as in mild depression (Fournier et al.

2010).

Although there are problems with the relationship

with the pharmaceutical industry, completely ignor-

ing studies with commercial support would also be

ethically questionable since it may benefit patients.

Thus, careful discrimination between poor and well-

designed studies is demanded, along with attempts by

academic publications to include a range of studies,

including those with negative results. Clear guidelines

and a ‘Proposal of Recommendations’ regarding

the ‘Ethical Implications of Relationships between

Psychiatrists and the Pharmaceutical Industry’ have

been published by the World Federation of Societies of

Biological Psychiatry (http://www.wfsbp.org/pub-

lications). These guidelines are comprehensive and

greatly assist the clinical and research psychophar-

macologist in managing interaction with the pharma-

ceutical industry.

Research ethics

Any research that is not carried out by the most rigid

of ethical principles and guidelines is simply not

worthy and definitely not suitable for publication. The

medical profession has learned its lesson from the

Nazi-physician experience. The vast majority of re-

search by national-socialist physicians during the Nazi

era was pseudoscience and without any value, with

research carried out under the most wicked of condi-

tions and no attention paid to informed consent

and patient safety (Lifton, 1986). Many physicians be-

lieved, however, that what they were involved in was

in the genuine best interests of society and the patient

including the most egregious of this activity, namely

euthanasia (‘mercy killing’).

The medical profession has learned from this, and

there has been a substantive change in what is con-

sidered ethically acceptable in research and practice.

The first official response came with the Nuremberg

Code in 1949, followed in the mid-1960s by the

World Health Organization’s more extensive Helsinki

The ethical psychopharmacologist 417

Declaration and the Belmont Report in 1979. In 1977,

the World Psychiatric Association (WPA) approved

the Declaration of Hawaii, which detailed the specific

ethical demands of psychiatry (Roberts & Roberts,

1999). Finally, the WPA Declaration of Madrid in

August 1996 implemented a comprehensive code of

professional behaviour for psychiatrists with rel-

evance to clinical psychopharmacology.

While it is important to safeguard patient/subject

welfare in research, patients have the right to be in-

cluded in research protocols in order to further scien-

tific understanding of their disorder and in order to

obtain improved modes of treatment. Participation in

research still remains an option for those without de-

cisionary capacity on condition that proper informed

consent is obtained from the relevant legal guardian

and that the relevant stipulations of the institutional

review board (IRB) are met (Byerly, 2009). Further

vital considerations for informed consent, termed

‘voluntarism’ in the landmark paper by Roberts

(2002), include developmental factors, illness-related

considerations, cultural and religious values, and ex-

ternal pressures. It is crucial that patients know the

difference between clinical care and research protocol

participation. This is referred to as ‘therapeutic mis-

conception’, the clarification of which is essential to

any ethical study (Dunn et al. 2006). Optimal informed

consent includes the need for an informed psy-

chiatrist, non-technical presentation, patient famili-

arity, involvement of other potential informants,

information repetition and ensuring that the patient

is as free as possible to make the choice without

any unreasonable pressure (Appelbaum, 2007; Taylor,

1983). In addition, despite cognitive impairment in

some individuals with schizophrenia, the ability to

give informed consent can and should be enhanced

with educational interventions (Dunn&Roberts, 2005).

Several unresolved issues regarding informed consent

remain. For example, is there a difference in the level

of competence required for informed consent between

blood testing for a biomarker and blood testing for

pharmacogenetics?, and is there a difference between

consent for a questionnaire and a new antipsychotic

medication? Furthermore, there are some instances

where no informed consent from the patient is ob-

tained, such as in the case of post-mortem brain

analysis. Is it acceptable in such cases to obtain in-

formed consent from the family?

There are several special problems in research of

psychiatric disorders. While decisionary capacity is

one well known ethical issue, as mentioned above,

others include the place of challenge paradigms

(Benjamin, 2002), what precisely may be considered

risk in research (Young, 1998) and the ethics of offering

financial compensation to mentally ill patients who

may be unfairly coerced into study participation based

on economic need (Marson et al. 2006). Legal require-

ments for informed consent may differ between

countries. However, requirements that are stricter

than the law allows may be considered in various

situations where ethical principles may preclude cer-

tain practices, e.g. especially in consideration of patient

confidentiality (Strous, 2009).

Other more practical ethical concerns with research

include those of medication ‘wash-out’ phases

(medication-free intervals) and the use of placebos.

Those who oppose the use of placebo controls in

psychopharmacological studies maintain that such

a study design negates the beneficent-based, ‘best

proven diagnostic and therapeutic method’ that the

original Helsinki Declaration of 1964 demanded of all

medical research. Others have argued that those ad-

ministered a placebo, particularly in cases of psychosis

or depression, would be adversely affected by not re-

ceiving a known efficacious compound (Baldwin et al.

2003). While this argument is cogent, it has been called

into question by many maintaining that these risks are

exaggerated, as well as several reports of increased

risk for suicidality with some antidepressants, and

finally the need to prove that the study compound is

better than the placebo. This must be explored, since

the specific or ‘true’ extent of the pharmacological

response is determined by the difference between the

drug and placebo response. Sample numbers needed

of patient participants are also smaller. The con-

sequentialist response would be that there are net

benefits for patients considering the value and quality

of data resulting from using placebo controls (Dunlop

& Banja, 2009). The use of placebos in research trials

may also vary between disorders and between levels

of severity. For example, in randomized controlled

trials of antidepressant medications, since there is

sufficient evidence of their efficacy in severe de-

pression, the use of placebo controls may only be

ethically admissible in mild to moderate depression

(Fournier et al. 2010). While placebos are often re-

quired by regulatory bodies for optimal research, their

use is not always in the best interest for the well-being

of the patient and needs to be carefully considered

prior to inclusion in research protocols. A further

ethical consideration in such clinical trials is the con-

cept of clinical equipoise which is satisfied if there is

genuine uncertainty over whether the treatment in a

randomized clinical trial involving patients assigned

to different treatment arms will be beneficial

(Freedman, 1987).

418 R. D. Strous

An important theme that runs through all ethical

issues related to psychopharmacological research is

the preoccupation with the best interest of patients

and protection of the rights and well-being of partici-

pating subjects. With this as a focus, the public will be

more open to supporting research in order that hope

may be maintained for this long-suffering group of

individuals. Most patients participating in psycho-

biological research actually find it to be a positive

experience (Rosen et al. 2007), notwithstanding the

public image of such research. Finally, the principles

of Morse (2007) represent a good summary of the

guidelines to consider in psychopharmacological re-

search studies, namely that medical care has priority

over research, that there is an absolute requirement to

intervene when safety is a question and to separate

clinical and research functions, placing patient well-

being above research goals if ever in conflict, and

safeguarding patient confidentiality and researcher

well-being.

It would be ethically important to convert research

observations from psychopharmacological research

into clinical benefits if the information is considered

sound and replicable. This includes the ethical

requirement for physicians to maintain ongoing/

continuing medical education (CME), updating with

journals, conference attendance and regular recerti-

fication where mandated. Care and attention should

are advised when reading research and reviews from

industry-sponsored investigation since they may be

less transparent and are often accompanied by limited

methodological reservations and considerations. Such

reviews consistently demonstrate more favourable

results compared to equivalent Cochrane reviews

(Jørgensen et al. 2006). It also may be ethically im-

portant to notify research subjects of study results and

to ensure that all clinical trials are publicized, for

example, by means of national and/or international

clinical trial databases.

Unfortunately, based on various precautions in

clinical research, several subpopulations of indivi-

duals are often excluded due to the fear of adverse

effects including possible litigation. These include

the young, the old, minorities, substance abusers

and pregnant women. Other populations often ex-

cluded in research protocols include patients re-

ceiving chronic maintenance mediation including

intramuscular depot antipsychotic formulations.

While this is understandable, these individuals also

suffer from illness and have rights too. Special safe-

guards may be required, and decisional capacity

must be closely evaluated together with legal guard-

ians if applicable, to allow all ill members of

society to benefit from participation in research

projects.

Collaboration with governmental interests and

involvement in social policy

The mandated ‘social contract ’ of a psychopharma-

cologist with the community is to describe, under-

stand, predict, and modify behaviour in cases of

mental illness. Most importantly, the mental health-

care provider, armed with tools of psychopharmaco-

logy, is committed to assisting the identified individual

and alleviating emotional pain. The psychopharma-

cologist as a mental health practitioner has privileged

access to the human psyche and behaviour. This

privilege demands responsibility and the primary

duty to care for patients’ mental health. To act other-

wise would constitute abdication of professional

responsibility (Strous, 2007). Thus, involvement of

a psychopharmacologist in political activity and nar-

row governmental interests would constitute a gross

boundary violation. A psychiatrist with tools of psy-

chopharmacology absolutely has to resist any external

pressure, be it governmental or other, to utilize skills

and training in areas where they do not belong

(Scheurich, 2000). It would be unethical for the psy-

chopharmacologist to allow his skills to be exploited in

order to carry out political plans of governing bodies

or nations. Utilizing psychopharmacology skills to

advance political agendas or other non-medical goals

must be considered unethical.

Notoriously, such involvement has included assist-

ance in torture (Gluzman, 1991; Summers, 1992), lie

detection in the context of a government-sponsored

interrogation or evaluation if some element of coercion

or abuse is engaged (Wilks, 2005). This would be true

even in the interest of national security. In this man-

ner, behavioural clinicians would be challenging their

professionalism and subsequently their ethical stan-

dards of conduct. Several medical associations have,

for example, prohibited involvement of physicians

in judicial executions. In addition, the American

Psychiatric Association has deemed treatment of psy-

chosis in order to prepare an individual for the death

penalty unacceptable and unethical practice. Since

doctors have been allowed the right to develop certain

skills and engage in invasive procedures in order to

save lives and provide comfort, exploiting this privi-

lege even in the best interests of the state would be

considered a serious boundary violation (Gawande,

2006). Court-ordered pharmacological management

for criminal behaviour may also be problematic, es-

pecially if administered under coercion (Farah, 2002).

The ethical psychopharmacologist 419

Psychopharmacology and special populations

A man is ethical only when life, as such, is sacred to him,

that of plants and animals as that of his fellowmen, andwhen

he devotes himself helpfully to all life that is in need of help.

Albert Schweitzer

(German theologian, philosopher and physician, 1875–1965).

Ethical considerations in the face of ethnic diversity

While cultural and ethnic factors affect many stages in

research and clinical management of various ethno-

cultural groups, very limited attention has been placed

on ethical factors influencing these conditions. In a

rare review of the subject, Miskimen et al. (2003) ex-

plore how ethnic factors may affect psychopharma-

cology including recruitment, retention and follow-up

of adult minority patients participating in research.

For example, while minorities make upmore than one-

third of the USA, they are grossly underrepresented in

research trials, ethically problematic since this limits

generalizability of research observations to their

communities. While this may be due to researchers

wanting to protect ‘vulnerable populations’, under-

representation of minority groups in psychopharma-

cological research is a problem for application of

research results for their healthcare. This phenomenon

may also partially be due to distrust by minorities of

the health establishment ; e.g. by African Americans as

a result of the Tuskegee experiments and decades of

discrimination in the USA. Medication administration

in minority populations without adequate research

opens up the possibility of idiosyncratic side-effects or

inappropriate dosing (Turner & Cooley-Quille, 1996).

Since treatment outcome information is crucial for

policy decision-making and resourceplanning itwould

be unethical not to consider the interests of minorities

(Miskimen et al. 2003).

In addition, informed consent among minorities

becomes a special problem due to language inequities

(subjects not understanding the process), financial

compensation (economically disadvantaged partici-

pating for money, thus undermining true volunteer-

ism) and respect (minimal questioning of authority

figures). Furthermore, all clinical research centres

need to make sure that culturally competent personnel

with a common language wherever possible engage

subjects/patients when explanation of research or

treatment protocols in psychopharmacology is re-

quired (Miskimen et al. 2003). Efforts need to be in-

vested in ensuring that ‘ inappropriate paternalism’ is

eliminated when dealing with patient groups different

from that of the study investigators, including when

research is done in different countries.

Psychopharmacology in children

Many would argue there is no more vulnerable

population, based on size and needs, than the paedia-

tric patient population. As Tan & Koelch (2008)

indicate, a paradoxical situation develops when, due

to excessive protective mechanisms and fear or re-

sistance to include children in research protocols,

minimal data exists regarding safety and efficacy

of psychopharmacological treatments. Furthermore,

pharmaceutical companies are reluctant to fund

studies on children due to the perception that there is

less financial gain.

Thus ‘off label ’ use becomes the standard for man-

agement, which is ethically and scientifically less ideal

due to a lower standard of safety. The younger the

patient, the truer this is, with a correlation between

age and study recruitment potential. While many

exclude completely the right and necessity for child

study assent and rely merely on parental or legal

guardian consent, a concerted effort must be invested

in obtaining child assent, especially with older

children who are more mature emotionally and intel-

lectually. Evidence for competence of children to

understand and make many management decisions

exists by age 9, and by age 14 many children can

understand treatment information at adult levels

(Billick et al. 1998). This holds true despite difficulties

with autonomous decision-making, susceptibility to

various external pressures and impact of the mental

illness (Ondrusek et al. 1998 ; Tan & Koelch, 2008).

‘At risk ’ syndromes

It has been proposed that a new diagnostic category of

‘psychosis risk syndrome’ be included in the forth-

coming fifth edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical

Manual of Mental Disorders. This may be a welcome

addition, due to its potential to generate funds for

research of this subcategory of being at risk for de-

veloping psychotic illness. While this may contribute

to the early intervention, management and modifi-

cation of the illness (thus potentially preventing or

delaying full blown psychosis), several important

ethical issues arise. First, there is a significant potential

for high rates of false-positives since there is con-

siderable difficulty in differentiating mild symptoms

from normal variants. Such false-positive identifi-

cation could lead to unnecessary stigma, discrimi-

nation and even potential exposure to antipsychotic

medication at an early age without definitive illness

evidence (Corcoran et al. 2010). Since over 50% of

identified subjects do not progress to psychosis (Yang

et al. 2010), physicians identifying individuals with

420 R. D. Strous

psychosis-risk syndrome are contributing to unfairly

labelling them with a potentially severe illness and

all its untoward consequences. For an adolescent at a

critical stage in development, the repercussions could

be marked. For those in whom psychosis is correctly

predicted, however, intervention could change the

course of the illness. To what extent should physicians

attempt to predict future illness at the potential ex-

pense of some who may be wrongfully labelled and

treated? If the phenomenon of individuals with ‘at risk

psychosis’ is real and potentially identifiable, what

percentage of false-positive identification would be

considered acceptable? How should an unfavourable

risk–benefit ratio be defined? While it is clear that

better identification of these individuals, for example,

by means of biomarkers, is optimal, the issue will

continue to interest psychopharmacological clinicians

and researchers in the coming years (Corcoran et al.

2010).

Animal research in psychopharmacology

The ethical concerns surrounding animal research

with psychopharmacological relevance is poorly ad-

dressed in the psychiatric literature. Due to recent

increased violent attacks on researchers by anti-animal

research activists, aptly termed terrorists by some

(Krystal et al. 2008), there is more awareness. It is

critical to clarify the necessity for animal research

and its beneficial extrapolation to humans (Francione,

2007). Although not all would agree, ethically one

could justify such research since benefits to humans

are clear, ranging from phenomenal breakthroughs in

genetic research with gene–knockout animal models

to the very obvious and direct benefits of new medi-

cation development with Phase 1 and Phase 2 appli-

cation. Predictability and transferability, however,

need to be more fully confirmed (Perry, 2007).

Various bodies have analysed the problem, with

guidelines laid out for ethical research. One such re-

port by an independent UK body, the Nuffield Council

on Bioethics, detailed ethical issues with recommend-

ations including the need to assess pain, distress, and

suffering in animals during the research process both

for scientific and ethical purposes. In addition to ex-

ploring absolute limits of research, they emphasize the

following issues : What are the goals of the research?

What is the probability of success? Which animals are

to be used? What effect will there be on animals used

in the experiment?, and, Are there any alternatives? It

is absolutely imperative that any such analysis of these

issues be conducted in a fair and informed manner

(Perry, 2007). If not, the phenomenon of terrorism

targeting medical scientists (Krystal et al. 2008) will

become more prevalent – a tragedy and a disservice to

both sides of the debate.

Ethical education and training in

psychopharmacology

Education is the art of making man ethical.

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

(German philosopher, 1770–1831)

Education in ethics of psychopharmacology

As early as 1931, the German code of medical ethics

was already known to be one of the strictest and most

advanced in the world. German doctors in the 1930s

were well aware of this code. They were trained in-

tensively in its intricacies, as evidenced for example by

manuscripts in the literature at the time, and devotion

to concepts of physician responsibility and medical

ethics in medical education and textbooks (Proctor,

2000). It did not, however, affect their practice. The

attitude of psychiatrists to their patients during this

period indicates, in a most unjust fashion, how science

may be affected by external considerations. Thus

without including a focus on the history of where our

profession has transgressed, ethics training becomes

an empty intellectual exercise (Strous, 2010). While

the Nazi-psychiatry experience is one such example

of psychobiological theory gone wrong (euthanasia,

eugenics), others exist in the history of psychiatry.

These include Dr Henry A. Cotton’s preoccupation

in Trenton Hospital with infection and ‘focal sepsis’

as the biological source of psychiatric illness. Without

true informed consent he removed teeth, tonsils, gall

bladders, stomachs, spleens, cervixes, testicles, ovaries

and even colons as potential sources of infection. It

is estimated that at least 30% of his patients with co-

lectomy died (Scull, 2006).

In order to avert such ethical misjudgement in

psychiatric research and clinical practice, education in

research ethics is crucial for psychopharmacology

trainees. This includes discussing ethical concerns and

norms governing research, sensitivity to ethical im-

plications of actions, and proficiency in ethics problem

solving. Research ethics can be learned and it is im-

perative to actively devote time to the teaching of this

fundamental issue (Chen, 2003). Chen (2003) has sug-

gested that small-group case-based learning is best

for teaching ethics problem-solving skills. It is worth

mentioning that the National Institutes of Health

(NIH) in the USA has a requirement that any trainee-

ship programme sponsored by them must have a

The ethical psychopharmacologist 421

specific element of training in research ethics. What-

ever the context, ethics awareness and sensitivity in

education needs to be ongoing and maintained as an

active aspect of psychopharmacological clinical and

research practice.

Resolution of ethical concerns

Since ethical issues are abundant in psychopharma-

cology, it is important not only to know what the

issues are, but also how to deal with them. Trainees in

psychiatry receive very little guidance in how to re-

solve ethical dilemmas if and when they arise, despite

basic education in general medical ethics. After iden-

tifying ethical concerns, the next step becomes ethical

decision-making. How is this accomplished? There are

several approaches to ethical decision-making, with

the final decision differing according to the different

modes of decision-making. Although ethical decisions

may ultimately differ, it is critical that the process

begins, is comprehensive, has some element of peer

review and discussion and is open to revisitation.

There are various approaches to ethical decision-

making. Wright & Roberts (2009) briefly review

various ethical decision-making models and encour-

age the use of the ‘Four Topics Method’. This par-

ticular model, developed by Siegler (1982), proposed

that solutions to ethical concerns should arise based

on consideration of operant factors and potential out-

comes arrived at in a systematic fashion. These would

include deliberation over medical indications, patient

preferences, quality-of-life factors and contextual

features (Wright & Roberts, 2009).

Another more widely disseminated and very useful

approach to ethical decision-making of particular

relevance to research and clinical psychopharma-

cology is that of the World Medical Association

(Williams, 2005). This method encourages the analysis

of ‘rational ’ vs. ‘non-rational ’ approaches to ethical

decision-making ; weighing up different factors on

each side. Non-rational approaches include obedience,

imitation, feeling or desire, intuition and habit, while

rational approaches engage concepts of deontology,

consequentialism (utilitarianism), principlism and vir-

tue ethics. While very comprehensive, it makes a great

deal of sense and is a wonderful tool for teaching and

engaging students in discussion and exploration of

factors relevant to ethics and psychopharmacology.

The principlism method is probably best known and

includes the concepts of autonomy, beneficence, non-

malfeasance and justice. Often there are competing

arguments within each principle, but it is a useful

model for commencing the ethical discussion process.

In order to educate the psychopharmacologist and

assist in the prevention and management of ethical

problems during research, ethical issues should be

considered and anticipated, ideally along with the

assistance of an ethicist, at each stage of the research

process (Derenzo & Moss, 2005). This includes study

design, subject selection/recruitment, consent, data

analysis, unexpected events, privacy considerations

and issues regarding special populations. These

authors recommend that every research protocol

should include an ethics section detailing how re-

searchers will ensure that the proposal will uphold the

strictest of ethical standards. In this manner, aware-

ness and sensitivity to ethical issues will be main-

tained and potential ethical problems alleviated.

The ethical psychopharmacologist : responsibilities

and challenges

To sum up, ethical considerations in psychopharma-

cology begin with proper education and training

and continue with ethical clinical care and research.

Training must emphasize ethical mindfulness, most

critical to the development and maturation of ethical

psychopharmacologists, both research and clinical.

This openness in identifying the issues and investi-

gating them must be developed within the context of

a good ethics education programme. Furthermore,

the concepts of ethical analysis must be included in

the rubric of psychopharmacological training and

practice. Consideration must be also given to social

implications of psychopharmacological practice that

allow us to manipulate our own minds (Fuchs, 2006).

On the research front, current ethical approaches to

research can still be improved, with respect for the

patient remaining as the foundation. Safeguards must

include minimal risk and serious, systematic IRBs. It is

also important to ensure that empirical ethics research

is encouraged and developed with the full support of

scientific bodies, along with other empirical and clini-

cal research (Tan & Koelch, 2008). Thought should be

invested in the inclusion of a research or clinical ethi-

cist in study design as well as in clinical management

settings. Moreover, ethical clinicians and researchers

must keep pace with technological advances and

subsequent ethical challenges. Despite the fact that

physicians in the current economically driven climate

of medicine are under great time constraints, it re-

mains critical to devote time to comprehensive and

careful ethical evaluation, obtaining ethical consent

and optimal ethical decision-making.

Given the direction of psychiatry and the central role

of medication in many aspects of illness management,

422 R. D. Strous

ethical practice in psychopharmacology and con-

sideration of the best interests of patients are essential.

The practice of psychopharmacology from both a re-

search and clinical perspective must be implemented

with parity, sensitivity and ethical relevance to all –

nothing less than the legitimacy of our profession is at

stake.

Acknowledgements

None.

Statement of Interest

None.

References

Appelbaum PS (2007). Clinical practice. Assessment of

patients’ competence to consent to treatment. New England

Journal of Medicine 357, 1834–1840.

Baldwin D, Broich K, Fritze J, Kasper S, et al. (2003).

Placebo-controlled studies in depression: necessary,

ethical and feasible. European Archives of Psychiatry and

Clinical Neuroscience 253, 22–28.

Benjamin J (2002). Challenge paradigms in psychiatric

research : what do they contribute and are they ethical?

Israel Journal of Psychiatry Related Sciences 39, 86–89.

Billick SB, Edwards JL, Burgert 3rd W, Serlen JR, et al.

(1998). A clinical study of competency in child psychiatric

inpatients. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry

and Law 26, 587–594.

Breckenridge A, Lindpaintner K, Lipton P, McLeod H, et al.

(2004). Pharmacogenetics : ethical problems and solutions.

Nature Reviews Genetics 5, 676–680.

Byerly WG (2009). Working with the institutional review

board. American Journal of Health – System Pharmacy 66,

176–184.

Chen DT (2003). Curricular approaches to research ethics

training for psychiatric investigators. Psychopharmacology

(Berlin) 171, 112–119.

Corcoran CM, First MB, Cornblatt B (2010). The

psychosis risk syndrome and its proposed inclusion in

the DSM-V: a risk-benefit analysis. Schizophrenia Research

120, 16–22.

Cosgrove L, Bursztajn HJ, Krimsky S, Anaya M, et al.

(2009). Conflicts of interest and disclosure in the

American Psychiatric Association’s Clinical

Practice Guidelines. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics 78,

228–232.

Derenzo E, Moss J (2005). Writing Clinical Research Protocols :

Ethical Considerations. San Diego, CA: Elsevier Academic

Press.

Diller LH (1996). The run on Ritalin. Attention deficit

disorder and stimulant treatment in the 1990s. Hastings

Center Report 26, 12–18.

Dunlop BW, Banja J (2009). A renewed, ethical defense of

placebo-controlled trials of new treatments for major

depression and anxiety disorders. Journal of Medicine and

Ethics 35, 384–389.

Dunn LB, Candilis PJ, Roberts LW (2006). Emerging

empirical evidence on the ethics of schizophrenia research.

Schizophrenia Bulletin 32, 47–68.

Dunn LB, Roberts LW (2005). Emerging findings in ethics

of schizophrenia research. Current Opinion in Psychiatry 18,

111–119.

Farah MJ (2002). Emerging ethical issues in neuroscience.

Nature Neuroscience 5, 1123–1129.

Farah MJ, Illes J, Cook-Deegan R, Gardner H, et al.

(2004). Neurocognitive enhancement : what can we do

and what should we do? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 5,

421–425.

Flower R (2004). Lifestyle drugs : pharmacology and the

social agenda. Trends in Pharmacological Science 25, 182–185.

Fournier JC, DeRubeis RJ, Hollon SD, Dimidjian S, et al.

(2010). Antidepressant drug effects and depression

severity : a patient-level meta-analysis. Journal of the

American Medical Association 303, 47–53.

Francione GL (2007). The use of nonhuman animals in

biomedical research : necessity and justification. Journal

of Law, Medicine & Ethics 35, 241–248.

Freedman B (1987). Equipoise and the ethics of clinical

research. New England Journal of Medicine 317, 141–145.

Fuchs T (2006). Ethical issues in neuroscience. Current

Opinion in Psychiatry 19, 600–607.

Gawande A (2006). When law and ethics collide – why

physicians participate in executions. New England Journal

Medicine 354, 1221–1229.

Glannon W (2009). Stimulating brains, altering minds.

Journal of Medical Ethics 35, 289–292.

Gluzman SF (1991). Abuse of psychiatry : analysis of the

guilt of medical personnel. Journal of Medical Ethics 17

(Suppl.), 19–20.

Guillemin M, McDougall R, Gillam L (2009). Developing

‘ethical mindfulness’ in continuing professional

development in healthcare : use of a personal narrative

approach. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 18,

197–208.

Hampson LA, Agrawal M, Joffe S, Gross CP, et al. (2006).

Patients’ views on financial conflicts of interest in cancer

research trials. New England Journal of Medicine 355,

2330–2337.

Insel TR (2010). Psychiatrists’ relationships with

pharmaceutical companies : part of the problem or part of

the solution? Journal of the American Medical Association 303,

1192–1193.

Jorgensen AW, Hilden J, Gotzsche PC (2006). Cochrane

reviews compared with industry supported meta-analyses

and other meta-analyses of the same drugs : systematic

review. British Medical Journal 333, 782.

Krystal JH, Carter CS, Geschwind D, Manji HK, et al.

(2008). It is time to take a stand for medical research and

against terrorism targeting medical scientists. Biological

Psychiatry 63, 725–727.

The ethical psychopharmacologist 423

Licurse A, Barber E, Joffe S, Gross C (2010). The impact of

disclosing financial ties in research and clinical care.

Archives of Internal Medicine 170, 675–682.

Lifton R (1986). The Nazi Doctors : Medical Killing and the

Psychology of Genocide. New York : Basic Books.

Lombera S, Illes J (2009). The international dimensions of

neuroethics. Developing World Bioethics 9, 57–64.

Marson DC, Savage R, Phillips J (2006). Financial capacity

in persons with schizophrenia and serious mental illness :

clinical and research ethics aspects. Schizophrenia Bulletin

32, 81–91.

McHenry L (2006). Ethical issues in psychopharmacology.

Journal of Medical Ethics 32, 405–410.

Merkel R, Boer G, Fegert J, Galert T, et al. (2007). Intervening

in the Brain : Changing Psyche and Society. Springer :

Heidelberg.

Miskimen T, Marin H, Escobar J (2003).

Psychopharmacological research ethics : special issues

affecting US ethnic minorities. Psychopharmacology (Berlin)

171, 98–104.

Mitchell PB (2009). Winds of change : growing demands for

transparency in the relationship between doctors and the

pharmaceutical industry. Medical Journal of Australia 191,

273–275.

Morse JM (2007). Ethics in action : ethical principles for doing

qualitative health research. Quality Health Research 17,

1003–1005.

Nuttin B, Gybels J, Cosyns P, Gabriels L, et al. (2002).

Deep brain stimulation for psychiatric disorders.

Neurosurgery 51, 519.

Ondrusek N, Abramovitch R, Pencharz P, Koren G (1998).

Empirical examination of the ability of children to consent

to clinical research. Journal of Medical Ethics 24, 158–165.

Perlis RH, Perlis CS, Wu Y, Hwang C, et al. (2005). Industry

sponsorship and financial conflict of interest in the

reporting of clinical trials in psychiatry. American Journal of

Psychiatry 162, 1957–1960.

Perry P (2007). The ethics of animal research : a UK

perspective. Institute of Laboratory Animal Resources 48,

42–46.

Proctor RN (2000). Nazi science and Nazi medical ethics :

some myths and misconceptions. Perspectives in Biology and

Medicine 43, 335–346.

Rabins P, Appleby BS, Brandt J, DeLong MR, et al. (2009).

Scientific and ethical issues related to deep brain

stimulation for disorders of mood, behavior, and thought.

Archives of General Psychiatry 66, 931–937.

Roberts LW (2002). Informed consent and the capacity for

voluntarism. American Journal of Psychiatry 159, 705–712.

Roberts LW, Roberts B (1999). Psychiatric research ethics :

an overview of evolving guidelines and current ethical

dilemmas in the study of mental illness. Biological

Psychiatry 46, 1025–1038.

Rosen C, Grossman LS, Sharma RP, Bell CC, et al. (2007).

Subjective evaluations of research participation by persons

with mental illness. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease

195, 430–435.

Scheurich N (2000). Commentary : psychiatry and values :

mental health as Trojan horse. Psychiatric Times 17, 6.

Schlaepfer TE, Fins JJ (2010). Deep brain stimulation and the

neuroethics of responsible publishing : when one is not

enough. Journal of the American Medical Association 303,

775–776.

Scull A (2006). Madhouse : A Tragic Tale of Megalomania and

Modern Medicine. Yale University Press.

Shastry BS (2006). Pharmacogenetics and the concept of

individualized medicine. Pharmacogenomics Journal 6,

16–21.

Siegler M (1982). Decision-making strategy for

clinical-ethical problems in medicine. Archives of Internal

Medicine 142, 2178–2179.

Stein DJ (2005). Cosmetic psychopharmacology of anxiety :

bioethical considerations. Current Psychiatry Reports 7,

237–238.

Stokamer CL (2003). Pharmaceutical gift giving: analysis of

an ethical dilemma. Journal of Nursing Administration 33,

48–51.

Strous R (2007). Commentary : Political activism: should

psychologists and psychiatrists try to make a difference?

Israel Journal of Psychiatry and Related Sciences 44, 12–17.

Strous RD (2009). To protect or to publish : confidentiality

and the fate of the mentally ill victims of Nazi euthanasia.

Journal of Medical Ethics 35, 361–364.

Strous RD (2010). Psychiatric genocide : reflections and

responsibilities. Schizophrenia Bulletin 36, 208–210.

Summers C (1992). Militarism, human welfare, and the

APA Ethical Principles of Psychologists. Ethics and Behavior

2, 287–310.

Tan JO, Koelch M (2008). The ethics of

psychopharmacological research in legal minors. Child

and Adolescent Psychiatry and Mental Health 2, 39.

Taylor PJ (1983). Consent, competency and ECT: a

psychiatrist’s view. Journal of Medical Ethics 9, 146–151.

Turner SM, Cooley-Quille MR (1996). Socioecological and

sociocultural variables in psychopharmacological

research : methodological considerations.

Psychopharmacology Bulletin 32, 83–192.

Wilks M (2005). A stain on medical ethics. Lancet 366,

429–431.

Williams JR (ed.) (2005). WMA Medical Ethics Manual. The

World Medical Association.

Wright MT, Roberts LW (2009). A basic decision-making

approach to common ethical issues in consultation-liaison

psychiatry. Psychiatric Clinics of North America 32, 315–328.

Yager J, Feinstein RE (2010). Medical education meets

pharma: moving ahead. Academic Psychiatry 34, 92–97.

Yang LH,Wonpat-Borja AJ, OplerMG, Corcoran CM (2010).

Potential stigma associated with inclusion of the psychosis

risk syndrome in the DSM-V: an empirical question.

Schizophrenia Research 120, 42–48.

Young SN (1998). Risk in research–from the Nuremberg

Code to the tri-council code : implications for clinical trials

of psychotropic drugs. Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience

23, 149–155.

424 R. D. Strous