commentary: epidemiologic methods: beyond clinical medicine, beyond epidemiology

3
Epidemiologic methods: Beyond clinical medicine, beyond epidemiology Francisco Bolu´mar 1 & Miquel Porta 2 1 Universitat Miguel Herna ´ndez, Alacant, Spain; 2 Institut Municipal d’Investigacio ´ Me `dica and Universitat Auto ´noma de Barcelona, Spain Accepted 9 June 2004 The truth likes to hide out in the open. Anne Michaels [1] Professor Olli S. Miettinen is one of the most influential epidemiologists of the 20th century, and his legacy continues to be felt deeply in epidemio- logic reasoning today [2, 3]. He is one of the very few whose class notes have been widely quoted in major textbooks [4]. His influence has been vast in furthering new methodological approaches to clini- cal and public health problems; this has occurred largely through the work of others, i.e., through subsequent reinterpretation of his often obscure words. Thanks to the work of colleagues such as Olli Miettinen and many other, today research methods with strong epidemiological roots are widely and fruitfully applied ‘within’ and ‘outside’ epidemiology. The epidemiological roots are obviously historical, as well as epistemological and ontological. Without much threat to epidemiologic ‘‘coherence’’ and ‘‘cohesion’’ that we are aware of, Miettinen’s work has contributed to a positive blurring of the borders of epidemiologic research methods; e.g., to the integra- tion of population thinking into clinical and public health research [5–9]. The expansion of this influence towards other research areas remains a significant – in our view, highly attractive – challenge for many epi- demiologists [10]. Such an expansion of influence will not be identical to what occurred via ‘‘clinical epide- miology’’ and, later, ‘‘evidence-based medicine’’. The nature of the hypotheses at stake is often quite dif- ferent in clinical medicine than in, say, molecular biology or genetics; largely because of this ontological fact, epidemiologic thinking continues to create new approaches, research designs, strategies of analysis and ways to assess causality for such biological dis- ciplines [5, 6, 11–15]. Furthermore, we believe that the horizons of the present debate on Miettinen’s paper [16] should also include the contributions of epidem- iologic methods to research on those public health problems that are best tackled by blending the rea- soning and the tools of epidemiology and of some of the social sciences [17–20]. We find little of this in the paper under discussion [16]: in our view it is too narrowly centered on the relationships between tra- ditional or classic epidemiologic research and research in clinical medicine; it speaks to epidemiologists almost as if we (they) were closed in a church under siege; and it barely refers to the important methodo- logical advances that are already favoring the inte- gration of epidemiological methods into ‘‘micro- biological’’ and ‘‘macro-social’’ health research [10]. This first comment thus refers to the limits of the ideological framework chosen by the author [16]. Within that framework, Miettinen makes a number of sound criticisms (e.g., on the role of statistics, the importance of the study base, the need for a stronger scientific basis of medicine, the confusion between screening and prevention, the importance of ‘‘intrainstitutional iatrogenesis’’). Yet, we have not been able to discern very many innovative proposals in the text. For instance, the idea that there is a ‘‘need to leave behind the concepts of ‘‘cohort’’ study and ‘‘case–control’’ study’’ and to ‘‘adopt that of the etiologic study as the singular substitute for these’’ [16] does not seem to go beyond the well-known rationale for nested case–control, case-cohort and related designs [21]. Assessing etiologic relationships is a fundamental, common, and well-known aim of several epidemi- ologic research designs. As far as we can tell, not many colleagues would dispute the notion that most ‘‘intervention research’’ can be thought to fall within the domain of etiologic research but Miettinen’s references provide few clues, if any, as to who would argue otherwise. The idea that methods must be coherent with the object of the study seems hardly new, either. Of course, it would not be hard to find examples of poor studies – epidemiologic and otherwise – that over- looked such need; e.g., studies suffering from a hypertrophy or a dissonance of the methodological apparatus vis-a`-vis the study hypotheses; or studies based on a poor conception of the hypotheses; or statistical analyses unguided by knowledge available on the study subject [22, 23]. Should we really think that epidemiologists are the only scientists that need to ‘‘become serious about object design’’ [16]? This is an ancient and elemental principle for any scientist. Without a careful attention to it, the many contri- butions of epidemiology to knowledge on human health would not have happened. European Journal of Epidemiology 19: 733–735, 2004. Ó 2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Upload: francisco-bolumar

Post on 06-Aug-2016

214 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

Epidemiologic methods: Beyond clinical medicine, beyond epidemiology

Francisco Bolumar1 & Miquel Porta21Universitat Miguel Hernandez, Alacant, Spain; 2 Institut Municipal d’Investigacio Medica and Universitat Autonoma de

Barcelona, Spain

Accepted 9 June 2004

The truth likes to hide

out in the open.Anne Michaels [1]

Professor Olli S. Miettinen is one of the mostinfluential epidemiologists of the 20th century, andhis legacy continues to be felt deeply in epidemio-logic reasoning today [2, 3]. He is one of the veryfew whose class notes have been widely quoted inmajor textbooks [4]. His influence has been vast infurthering new methodological approaches to clini-cal and public health problems; this has occurredlargely through the work of others, i.e., throughsubsequent reinterpretation of his often obscurewords.

Thanks to the work of colleagues such as OlliMiettinen and many other, today research methodswith strong epidemiological roots are widely andfruitfully applied ‘within’ and ‘outside’ epidemiology.The epidemiological roots are obviously historical, aswell as epistemological and ontological. Withoutmuch threat to epidemiologic ‘‘coherence’’ and‘‘cohesion’’ that we are aware of, Miettinen’s workhas contributed to a positive blurring of the borders ofepidemiologic research methods; e.g., to the integra-tion of population thinking into clinical and publichealth research [5–9]. The expansion of this influencetowards other research areas remains a significant – inour view, highly attractive – challenge for many epi-demiologists [10]. Such an expansion of influence willnot be identical to what occurred via ‘‘clinical epide-miology’’ and, later, ‘‘evidence-based medicine’’. Thenature of the hypotheses at stake is often quite dif-ferent in clinical medicine than in, say, molecularbiology or genetics; largely because of this ontologicalfact, epidemiologic thinking continues to create newapproaches, research designs, strategies of analysisand ways to assess causality for such biological dis-ciplines [5, 6, 11–15]. Furthermore, we believe that thehorizons of the present debate on Miettinen’s paper[16] should also include the contributions of epidem-iologic methods to research on those public healthproblems that are best tackled by blending the rea-soning and the tools of epidemiology and of some ofthe social sciences [17–20]. We find little of this in thepaper under discussion [16]: in our view it is toonarrowly centered on the relationships between tra-ditional or classic epidemiologic research and research

in clinical medicine; it speaks to epidemiologistsalmost as if we (they) were closed in a church undersiege; and it barely refers to the important methodo-logical advances that are already favoring the inte-gration of epidemiological methods into ‘‘micro-biological’’ and ‘‘macro-social’’ health research [10].This first comment thus refers to the limits of theideological framework chosen by the author [16].

Within that framework, Miettinen makes anumber of sound criticisms (e.g., on the role ofstatistics, the importance of the study base, theneed for a stronger scientific basis of medicine, theconfusion between screening and prevention, theimportance of ‘‘intrainstitutional iatrogenesis’’).Yet, we have not been able to discern very manyinnovative proposals in the text. For instance, theidea that there is a ‘‘need to leave behind theconcepts of ‘‘cohort’’ study and ‘‘case–control’’study’’ and to ‘‘adopt that of the etiologic study asthe singular substitute for these’’ [16] does not seemto go beyond the well-known rationale for nestedcase–control, case-cohort and related designs [21].Assessing etiologic relationships is a fundamental,common, and well-known aim of several epidemi-ologic research designs. As far as we can tell, notmany colleagues would dispute the notion thatmost ‘‘intervention research’’ can be thought to fallwithin the domain of etiologic research – butMiettinen’s references provide few clues, if any, asto who would argue otherwise.

The idea that methods must be coherent with theobject of the study seems hardly new, either. Ofcourse, it would not be hard to find examples of poorstudies – epidemiologic and otherwise – that over-looked such need; e.g., studies suffering from ahypertrophy or a dissonance of the methodologicalapparatus vis-a-vis the study hypotheses; or studiesbased on a poor conception of the hypotheses; orstatistical analyses unguided by knowledge availableon the study subject [22, 23]. Should we really thinkthat epidemiologists are the only scientists that needto ‘‘become serious about object design’’ [16]? This isan ancient and elemental principle for any scientist.Without a careful attention to it, the many contri-butions of epidemiology to knowledge on humanhealth would not have happened.

European Journal of Epidemiology 19: 733–735, 2004.� 2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Also within the landscape of epidemiologic meth-ods, the paper [16] seems to overlook at least some ofthe most important advances that have been made inthe recent past [24–31]. There is barely any recogni-tion of contributions made by others.

Time has shown that the mind of Olli Miettinenmay hold treasures. It is hence unfortunate that hisstyle of writing ‘‘speaks for itself’’: cryptic, tortuous,enigmatic… Miettinen has long seemed to rejoice inthis.

His is not a text that many clinicians will care tounderstand. Miettinen states that ‘‘only we [‘‘researchepidemiologists’’] can assume the central role in theproduction of the knowledge base for scientificmedicine’’, and that ‘‘we consequently have theobligation to assume this larger and higher, meta-epidemiologic mission’’. The paper refers severaltimes to the ‘‘uniqueness’’ of ‘‘us epidemiologists’’, toa ‘‘mission’’, ‘‘obligation’’, ‘‘vision’’, ‘‘dream’’,‘‘devotion’’… It is unimportant that the languagesounds too ecclesiastic to us. We simply find suchpropositions at odds with much of the contemporaryscientific world: wide open, transdisciplinary – muchmore creative, relevant, efficient, and interesting be-cause of the porousness, flexibility and adaptability ofthe disciplines than because of the putative highermission of their clerics and disciples.

It is almost certain that epidemiology wouldbenefit from a stronger philosophical base, includ-ing epistemology and ontology. As it would benefitfrom a proper ‘sociology of epidemiology’ [10].What we are not sure of is whether we are loosinga great expert in scientific methods while reallygaining a philosopher of epidemiology. It wouldhave been too easy to title this commentary ‘‘Quovadis, Olli Miettinen?’’.

References

1. Michaels A. Poems. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2000:163.

2. Rothman KJ, Greenland S, eds. Modern epidemiology,

2nd edn. Philadelphia: Lippincott–Raven, 1998.3. Kleinbaum DG, Sullivan KM, Barker ND. ActivEpi

companion textbook/ActivEpi CD-ROM. New York:

Springer, 2003.4. Kleinbaum DG, Kupper LL, Morgenstern H. Epidemi-

ologic research. Principles and quantitative methods.Belmont, CA: Lifetime Learning Publications, 1982:

61, 94, 157, 193, 319.5. Vandenbroucke JP. Clinical investigation in the 20th

century: The ascendancy of numerical Reasoning.

Lancet 1998; 352 (Suppl 2): 12–16.6. Vandenbroucke JP. Medical journals and the shaping

of medical knowledge. Lancet 1998; 352: 2001–2006.

7. Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: An integratedintroduction to the ideas, theories, principles and

methods of epidemiology. New York: Oxford Univer-sity Press, 2002.

8. Trichopoulos D. Accomplishments and prospects of

epidemiology. Prev Med 1996; 25: 4–6.9. Spitzer WO. The future of epidemiology. J Clin Epi-

demiol 1996; 49: 705–709.

10. Porta M, Alvarez-Dardet C. Epidemiology: Bridgesover (and across) roaring levels. J Epidemiol CommunHealth 1998; 52: 605.

11. Garner C. Epidemiology: Molecular potential. Nature1992; 360: 207–208.

12. Hunter DJ. The future of molecular epidemiology. Int J

Epidemiol 1999; 28: S1012–S1014.13. Khoury MJ, Burke W, Thomson E. Genetics and

public health in the 21st century. Using genetic infor-mation to improve health and prevent disease. New

York: Oxford University Press, 2000.14. Porta M. Epidemiologic plausibility. Re: ‘‘Biologic

plausibility in causal inference: Current method and

practice’’. Am J Epidemiol 1999; 150: 217–218.15. Porta M, Malats N, Vioque J, Carrato C, Soler M,

Ruiz L, et al. Incomplete overlapping of biological,

clinical and environmental information in molecularepidemiologic studies: A variety of causes and a cas-cade of consequences. J Epidemiol Commun Health

2002; 56: 734–738.16. Miettinen OS. Epidemiology: Quo vadis? Eur J Epi-

demiol 2004; 19: 713–718.17. Babbie E. The practice of social research, 10th edn.

Belmont, CA.: Thomson/Wadsworth, 2004.18. Berkman LF, Kawachi I. Social epidemiology. New

York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

19. Krieger N. Sticky webs, hungry spiders, buzzing flies,and fractal metaphors: On the misleading juxtapositionof ‘‘risk factor’’ versus ‘‘social’’ epidemiology. J Epi-

demiol Commun Health 1999; 53: 678–680.20. Marmot M, Wilkinson RG. Social determinants of

health. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.21. Hernandez-Dıaz S, Hernan MA, Meyer K, Wer-

ler MM, Mitchell AA. Case-crossover and case-time-control designs in birth defects epidemiology. AmJ Epidemiol 2003; 158: 385–391.

22. Hernan MA, Hernandez-Dıaz S, Werler MM, Mitch-ell AA. Causal knowledge as a prerequisite forconfounding evaluation: An application to birth defects

epidemiology. Am J Epidemiol 2002; 155: 176–184.23. Greenland S, Morgenstern H. Confounding in health

research. Annu Rev Public Health 2001; 22: 189–212.

24. Clayton D, McKeigue PM. Epidemiological methodsfor studying genes and environmental factors in com-plex diseases. Lancet 2001; 358: 1356–1360.

25. Greenland S, Pearl J, Robins JM. Causal diagrams for

epidemiologic research. Epidemiology 1999; 10: 37–48.26. Greenland S, Brumback B. An overview of relations

among causal modelling methods. Int J Epidemiol

2002; 31: 1030–1037.27. Robins JM, Hernan MA, Brumback B. Marginal

structural models and causal inference in epidemiology.

Epidemiology 2000; 11: 550–560.28. Hernan MA. A definition of causal effect for epidemi-

ological research. J Epidemiol Commun Health 2004;58: 265–271.

734

29. Vineis P. History of bias. Soz Praventiv Med 2002; 47:156–161.

30. Vandenbroucke JP. The history of confounding. Soz

Praventiv Med 2002; 47: 216–224.31. Morabia A. History of epidemiologic methods and

concepts. Basel: Birkhauser, 2004.

Address for correspondence: Miquel Porta, InstitutMunicipal d’Investigacio Medica, UniversitatAutonoma de Barcelona, Carrer del Dr. Aiguader,

80 E-08003 Barcelona, SpainPhone: +34-93-225-7550/221-1009; Fax: +34-93-221-3237E-mail: [email protected]

735