atkinson 2002

22
Toward a Sociocognitive Approach to Second Language Acquisition Author(s): Dwight Atkinson Source: The Modern Language Journal, Vol. 86, No. 4 (Winter, 2002), pp. 525-545 Published by: Wiley on behalf of the National Federation of Modern Language Teachers Associations Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1192723 . Accessed: 30/10/2013 13:50 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Wiley and National Federation of Modern Language Teachers Associations are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Modern Language Journal. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: marcos-vinicius

Post on 14-Jan-2016

73 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Sociocognitive Approach to second language aquisition

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Atkinson 2002

Toward a Sociocognitive Approach to Second Language AcquisitionAuthor(s): Dwight AtkinsonSource: The Modern Language Journal, Vol. 86, No. 4 (Winter, 2002), pp. 525-545Published by: Wiley on behalf of the National Federation of Modern Language Teachers AssociationsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1192723 .

Accessed: 30/10/2013 13:50

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Wiley and National Federation of Modern Language Teachers Associations are collaborating with JSTOR todigitize, preserve and extend access to The Modern Language Journal.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Atkinson 2002

Toward a Sociocognitive Approach to Second Language Acquisition DWIGHT ATKINSON Graduate School of Education

Temple University Japan 2-8-12 Minami Azabu Minato-ku

Tokyo 106-0047

Japan Email: [email protected]

This article develops the notion of a sociocognitive perspective on second language acquisition (SLA), proposed as an alternative to the cognitivism pervading the field. By sociocognitive, I mean a view of language and language acquisition as simultaneously occurring and interac- tively constructed both "in the head" and "in the world." First, I develop a view of language and its acquisition as social phenomena-as existing and

taking place for the performance of action in the (socially-mediated) world. Second, I describe the cognitive nature of language and its acquisition, focusing especially on recent develop- ments in connectionism. Third, I introduce sociocognitive views of language and posit a social interpretation of connectionism as bridging the gap between cognition and social action. Fourth, I discuss sociocognitive perspectives on first language acquisition. Fifth, I describe the cognitivist biases of much SLA research, then suggest how sociocognitive approaches can help overcome them. I end by considering implications of the perspective I develop in this paper.

Theorists and researchers tend to view SLA as a mental pro- cess, that is, to believe that language acquisition resides mostly, ifnot solely, in the mind. (Davis, 1995, pp. 427-428)

Most SLA researchers view the object of inquiry as in large part an internal, mental process. (Long, 1997, p. 319)

SLA has been essentially a psycholinguistic enterprise, domi- nated by the computational metaphor of acquisition. (R. Ellis, 1997, p. 87)

It is fair to say that the dominant theoretical influences [in SLA] have been linguistic and psycholinguistic. ... While more socially oriented views have been proposed from time to time, they have remained relatively marginal to the field overall. (Mitchell & Myles, 1998, p. x)

Much of what we identify as our cognitive capacities may . . . turn out to be properties of the wider, environmen- tally extended systems of which brains are just one (impor- tant) part. (A. Clark, 1997, p. 214)

Individual effort and sociocultural activity are mutually embedded, as are the forest and the trees, and . . . it is

essential to understand how they constitute each other. Rather than according primacy to the role of sociocultural activity or of the individual, the aim is to recognize the essential and inseparable roles of societal heritage, social engagement, and individual efforts. (Rogoff 1990, p. 25)

A RECURRING IMAGE COMES TO MIND WHEN I read much second language acquisition (SLA) research and theory. It is the image of a single cactus in the middle of a lonely desert-the only thing except sand for miles around. The cactus sits there, waiting patiently for that rare cloud to pass overhead and for that shower of rain to come pouring down. Like the solitary cactus, the learner in mainstream SLA research seems to sit in the middle of a lonely scene, and, like the cactus, the learner seems to wait there for life-giv- ing sustenance (or at least its triggering mecha- nism)--input-to come pouring in. At that point the real action begins, and we watch the learner miraculously grow and change.

A contrasting image sometimes also occurs to me, though more often when reading in fields other than SLA, such as language socialization and cultural anthropology. This is the image of a

The Modern Language Journal, 86, iv, (2002) 0026-7902/02/525-545 $1.50/0 @2002 The Modern Language Journal

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Atkinson 2002

526 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

tropical rainforest, so densely packed and thick with underbrush that it would be hard to move through. This forest is constantly wet with humid- ity and teeming with life, sounds, growth, and decay-a lush ecology in which every organism operates in complex relationship with every other organism. Each tree grows in and as a result of this fundamentally integrated world, develop- ing continuously and being sustained through its involvement in the whole ecology. And this image satisfies me at a deeper level, because it corre- sponds to how I (and others) believe language acquisition "really works."

In this article, I undertake a critique of the "lonely cactus" view of SLA and offer in its place a perspective that integrates learners, teachers (not necessarily or perhaps even usually of the classroom variety), acquisitional contexts (both of situation and of culture, e.g., Halliday & Hasan, 1989; Malinowski, 1923; Ochs, 1990), and social practices, products, tools, and worlds (e.g., Berger & Luckmann, 1966; A. Clark, 1997; Gee, 1992; Wertsch, 1985). I argue that our obsession with the decontextualized, autonomous learner has prevented us from conceptualizing SLA as a situated, integrated, sociocognitive process-a view- point that will bear real fruit in attempts to un- derstand the complex phenomenon of SLA.

In order to reach this goal, however, one must start some way back. As SLA theorists (e.g., Gregg, 1988) have pointed out, studying SLA without first defining the substance and scope of the L and the A is a haphazard endeavor. Much of this article will therefore be devoted to estab- lishing what I mean by the two foundational con- cepts language and its acquisition, as a necessary prerequisite to focusing the discussion explicitly on SLA. More specifically, the staging, sequenc- ing, and relative emphasis of the exposition will be: (a) language and language acquisition as so- cial phenomena, (b) language and language ac- quisition as cognitive phenomena, (c) language as a sociocognitive phenomenon, (d) language acquisition as a sociocognitive phenomenon; and (e) second language acquisition as a sociocogni- tive phenomenon.'

LANGUAGE AND LANGUAGE ACQUISITION AS SOCIAL PHENOMENA

Obviously but nontrivially, language is so- cial-a social practice, a social accomplishment, a social tool. People use language to act in and on their social worlds: to convey, construct, and perform, among other things, ideas, feelings, ac- tions, identities, and simple (but crucial) passing

acknowledgments of the existence of other hu- man beings. None of these activities makes sense apart from a fundamentally social environ- ment-All language is language in use, to para- phrase M.A.K. Halliday. Language has brought manifold evolutionary advantages to our species, allowing us the possibility of both working smoothly and efficiently in groups, and critiqu- ing and improving them. The social nature of language is not incidental to its existence and ongoing use-it largely if not completely ex- plains them (e.g., Elman et al., 1996; Seiden- berg, 1996). To the degree that we are cogni- tively predisposed to learn and use language, it is because as a social tool it allowed those who originally took advantage of it (in however ru- dimentary a form) an edge in survival over those who did not. And language as a species-wide ca- pability continues to yield multiple advantages to human beings.

In the defining moment of 20th-century lin- guistics, Chomsky took structuralism to its logical extreme, completely abstracting language from its social setting and declaring its ontological (or at least methodological) self-sufficiency. By re- ducing the social out of language he was able to produce an idealized pseudolanguage about which some "facts" could be explained using the tools of logic and calculus. Yes, speakers of En- glish certainly do use question transforma- tions-and arguably quite often do not, generally speaking, in oral discourse-but to base a whole linguistic theory on a handful of such phenom- ena belies the reductiveness and abstractness of Chomsky's model of language.2

In fact, grammar (rightly understood) is itself a social accomplishment and social tool. Thus, a recent volume in Cambridge's Studies in Interac- tional Linguistics series (Ochs, Schegloff, & Thompson, 1996) investigates the many ways in which grammatical features both function so- cially and are influenced by and shaped in inter- actional context:

Grammar is part of a broader range of resources-or- ganizations of practices, if you will-which underlie the organization of social life, and in particular the way in which language figures in everyday interaction and cognition. In this view, the involvement of gram- mar in such other organizations as those of culture, action and interaction has as a consequence that mat- ters of great moment are missed if grammar's order is explored as entirely contained within a single, self- enclosed organization. Grammar's integrity and effi- cacy are bound up with its place in larger schemes of organization of human conduct, and with social in- teraction in particular.3 (p. 3)

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 527

More specifically, the authors in this volume investigate how "grammar organizes social inter- action" (p. 33; e.g., how grammatical structure contributes to conversational turn-taking); how "social interaction organizes grammar" (p. 36; e.g., how grammatical structure varies, changes, and is emergent across social settings and socio- historical time); and how "grammar is a mode of social interaction" (p. 38; e.g., how people co- construct utterances using grammar as a shared resource).

Beyond grammar, a brief sampling of phenom- ena which socially-oriented linguists have at- tempted to account for-and which, I would ar- gue, deserve a central place in any valid, comprehensive approach to language and its ac- quisition-include:

1. Politeness, identity, and presentation of self.

A major use of language is to negotiate and main- tain relationships between people. This includes its central role in presenting and performing identities, or socially expressive versions of the self (e.g., Brown & Levinson, 1987; Gee, 1990; Goffman, 1959; Peirce, 1995; Tannen, 1986).

2. Perspective taking and contextualization cueing. All language in use incorporates markers of how it is to be interpreted (e.g., Gumperz, 1982; Quirk, Greenbaum, Leech, & Svartvik, 1985). Thus, the string I hate you, while not devoid of (socially-structured) lexical and grammatical meaning, would usually be incomprehensible as a spoken utterance without at least some of the following (which typically co-occur): intonation, loudness, voice quality, and emphasis (but see next point).4

3. Language-in-context. Of central importance to a truly social understanding of language is what else goes on vis-a-vis the languaging event that contributes to its situated significance. To compli- cate usefully the example given to support the previous point, if the I hate you is accompanied by a passionate embrace, changes in the intonation contour may not be needed to gauge the intent of the statement. Language never occurs apart from a rich set of situational/sociocultural/his- torical/existential correlates, and to separate it out artificially is to denature it. Recent research on the complex implicatedness of speech with gestural systems, eye gaze and head movement, bodily orientation, and the manipulation of ob- jects (e.g., Goodwin, 2000; Goodwin & Goodwin, 1992; Kendon, 1992; McNeill, 2000; Ochs et al., 1996) is highly suggestive in this regard. Dis- course analysts and anthropologists (e.g., Fair- clough, 1992; Gee, 1990; Hutchins, 1995;

Pennycook, 1994, 1998; Street, 1984, 1993) have also dealt with the profound sociohistorical im- brication of written and spoken language in sys- tems of social and cultural practice, hierarchy, professional specialization, and power.

4. Turn-taking, participation structures, and oppor- tunity structures. The mechanisms and ideologies by which participation in language activity is so- cially apportioned are central to the notion of language as a social phenomenon (e.g., Sacks, Schegloff, & Jefferson, 1974). They also vary markedly according to cultural norms of lan- guage use and the distribution of power in society (e.g., Bourdieu, 1991; Edelsky 1981; McDermott, 1988; Ochs, 1988a; Philips, 1983; Tannen, 1993; Tannen & Saville-Troike, 1985).

5. Speech as an interactional accomplishment. A number of scholars (e.g., Goodwin, 1986, 1987, 2000; Lerner, 1996; Ochs, Schieffelin, & Platt, 1979) have shown how oral language is struc- tured across individuals, rather than by indi- viduals operating autonomously. A persistent contention has been that the individual is not the appropriate unit of analysis when examining lan- guage and associated behavior from a truly social point of view (e.g., Bakhtin, 1990; Rogoff, 1990, 1998).

6. Social indexicality. Overlapping and possibly subsuming several of the categories already men- tioned, the notion of indexicality, broadly con- strued, suggests the all-important use of language to orient oneself and others in the (socially-medi- ated) world. Far beyond the perceived oddities of traditional indexicals-e.g., personal pronouns and deictic expressions-social indexicality sees virtually all linguistic referrings as underspeci- fled, and, therefore, as taking their meaning as much from their contextual (and sociocontextu- ally-construed) surroundings as from their literal sense (Hanks, 1996; Ochs, 1990, 1992, 1996).

Other phenomena that a valid approach to language-in-the-world would have to account for, but which cannot be explicated here, include: social knowledge of and participation in speech events, sociolinguistic (including register) vari- ation, and the organization and "addressivity" (Bakhtin, 1990) of discourse. None of the lin- guistic features or functions mentioned to this point should be considered add-ons to a basic framework for understanding language-on the contrary, they comprise part of the core set of phenomena that such a framework needs to ex- plain.

Just as surely as language is social, so is its acquisition. As with other social practices, new-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Atkinson 2002

528 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

borns are actively inducted into "languaging" (Becker, 1988) from day one, or almost certainly before (Foster, 1990; Locke, 1993, 1995). This is not to suggest that infants are not cognitively predisposed to language-related phenomena- to human voices and faces (e.g., Bower & Wishart, 1979; Eimas, 1975), for instance, or pro- nounced intonation contours (Snow, 1995)-or that children themselves are anything less than active participants in the first language (L1) ac- quisition process. What it does suggest is that such cognitive potentials are realized in (and such dynamic actors supported by) extremely rich, nurturing social activities and contexts. Quite opposed to the Chomskyan "poverty of the stimulus" argument, a first principle of L1 ac- quisition should therefore be the richness of the context, that is, the deep, multiplex embedding of language activities in the lush social world that surrounds most children, and which, in the words of Bourdieu (1991), "instead of telling the child what he [sic] must do, tells him what he is, and thus leads him to become durably what he has to be" (p. 52). Thus, whereas communi- cative intentionality as we know it cannot be at- tributed to newborns and early infants, caregivers often interpret their behaviors as in- tentional (Foster, 1990; Smith, 1988) and act on that basis. As Newson (1979, cited in Foster 1990) expressed it: "Human babies become hu- man beings because they are treated as if they already were human beings [italics added]" (p. 16).

A second principle of L1 acquisition should therefore be the social input (or insertion--Gee, 1995) principle. In opposition to the notion of input as linguistic information presented to and activating the language learning automaton (i.e., the lonely cactus view), input is used here to de- note that the child herself is input/inserted into an ongoing stream of social interaction that sup- ports her language development at every turn. Gee (1995) generalized his nearly identical "in- sertion principle" of L1 acquisition to all kinds of complex learning:

The insertion principle: Efficacious learning of a new complex system is a process involving socially sup- ported and scaffolded insertion into an activity that one does not yet understand. (p. 336)

Gee (1995) also described additional princi- ples by which L1 acquisition takes place vis-a-vis its rich social environment. Among them are:

The routine principle: Early insertion into an activity one does not yet understand requires that the activity be to a certain extent repeated and routinized or

ritualized. Rituals "freeze" meaning for the learner's observation. (p. 336)

The public principle: The meanings of the parts of new systems, whether words, visual symbols, actions, or objects must initially be rendered public and overt, so that the learner can see the connection between the signs and their interpretations. And this is done, in first language acquisition and other forms of learn- ing, by the ways in which words, actions, and social interaction are integrally intertwined. (p. 337)

The context-variability principle: In learning the parts of a new system, the learner will initially tie meanings to specific contexts or experiences. Appreciating wider meaning is a matter of having multiple experiences, not (just) learning "general rules," and mastery re- quires practice at varying aspects of meaning so as to actively fit them to the context of use. People who know only "general meanings" and cannot vary these in context neither know the system, nor are they acquiring it in a useful way. (p. 346)

A substantial literature on child language so- cialization now exists that details the manifold, diverse ways in which language is shaped for and by acquirers into the dynamic, creative social sig- nifying system that it is. The basic assumption underlying socialization in general is that "chil- dren come to share the world view [and social practices] of their community through the ar- rangements and interactions in which they are involved, whether or not such arrangements and interactions are intended to instruct them" (Ro- goff, 1990, p. 98). Consequently, early language socialization studies focus on language learned "through intensive . . . contact under conditions allowing maximum feedback such as we find in home and peer settings" (Gumperz, 1982, p. 139). Given the highly active stimulus-seeking na- ture of children, this makes the "conservative [ly] " estimated 12,000-15,000 hours of intensive con- tact between average caregivers and children over their first years together (Larsen-Freeman, 1991, p. 336; for similar estimates see N. C. Ellis, 1998; McLaughlin, 1987) a period in which a seemingly impossible amount of learning-in-context can take place.

Although language is clearly internalized in a sense during L1 acquisition, however, it never ceases to be part of the learner-as-social mem- ber's set of interactively constructed social tools, practices, and experiences, and, in this way and others, continues to be held jointly with the so- cial world. In fact, I will argue below that too much has been made of the internal/external opposition-the division between the cognizing individual and the social (or socially-mediated) world.

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 529

LANGUAGE AND LANGUAGE ACQUISITION AS COGNITIVE PHENOMENA

To say that language is social is in no sense to deny that it is also cognitive. Humans have evolu- tionarily highly-developed brains, and language, to some substantial degree, is stored in, compre- hended by, produced by, and therefore reflects the basic design features of the human brain. In fact, the human cognitive apparatus is much more of a virtuoso language performer than rather cut- and-dried functional portrayals typically allow (al- though, as will be explained further below, its ef- fective performance can only take place by virtue of a rich, interactive fund of social knowledge, in a rich social/interactional context). Thus, in the act of conversing, we not only store and retrieve linguistic and contextual information "online" al- most instantaneously and normally with great ac- curacy, but we also produce, comprehend, moni- tor our production and comprehension, plan our next contribution, and perform myriad other op- erations (e.g., adopt various politeness strategies, negotiate turn-taking, anticipate what others are going to say, integrate different modes of lan- guage and symbol system use such as reading, ges- turing, eye gaze, and body orientation with speak- ing) virtually all at the same time. It is small wonder then that some psychologists have begun to redefine intelligence in terms of the amazing things all (or at least many) humans do cogni- tively--including, notably, in their use of lan- guage-rather than in terms of intelligence mea- sures which place individuals in rigid hierarchies of difference and deficit (Scribner & Cole, 1981; cf. Gee, 1990; Gould, 1981).

Several recent cognitive theories of language and grammar have presented interesting contrasts to Chomskyan linguistics in the important roles they give to context and use. Thus, Hopper (1988) coined the term emergent grammar to describe a view of grammar as "a vaguely defined set of sedi- mented (i.e., [more or less] grammaticized) re- current partials whose status is constantly being re- negotiated and which cannot be distinguished in principle from stategies for building discourses" (p. 118). He went on to give evidence from written Malay of the ways such discourse phenomena as foregrounding and backgrounding substantially shape the grammar that is used to enact them. Other scholars proposing cognitively focused but context-driven and noncomponential approaches to grammatical knowledge include Becker (1979; 1988), Langacker (1987), C.J. Fillmore, Kay, and O'Connor (1988), and Seidenberg (1996). Their theories all have in common the notion that gram-

mar does not represent a single, logical, a priori system whose basic existence and implementation for communicative purposes is irrelevant to its cognitive status.

Language acquisition as well is obviously a cog- nitive phenomenon. Cognition and language de- velop hand in hand in early childhood, and less dramatically into the later years-in several impor- tant senses their development never ceases (e.g., Kemper, 1987). Cognitive predispositions toward learning and using language (Foster, 1990; Locke, 1993, 1995) are clearly also present at the begin- ning of life-infants truly do seem to come equipped with either linguistic protoknowledge already built in, or cognitive systems primed to learn an amazing amount linguistically in a short time. Operating principles, parameter setting, bootstrapping, and child-directed speech are all attempts to account for the incredible amount of language awareness children display early in life, and for how they so quickly complexify it.

One recent cognitive attempt to explain Li acquisition is connectionism (e.g., Plunkett, 1995; Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986; cf. N. C. Ellis, 1998). Connectionist theories depend on the computational modeling of language (and other kinds of) learning via the gradual buildup of richly internetworked association potentials at the neural level which are selectively and simulta- neously activated in specific patterns to perform cognitive activities, including language produc- tion and comprehension.5 Connectionist L1 ac- quisition models appear to account for how vari- ous complex language systems such as the English past tense verb-marking system (e.g., Plunkett & Marchman, 1993; Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986) can be learned over time with- out assuming innate linguistic knowledge. Al- though much effort has gone into establishing the modeling of this particular grammatical sys- tem as a paradigm example of connectionism's power, connectionist researchers have investi- gated other linguistic domains as well. Thus, El- man (1992) and others have modeled connec- tionist systems that correctly assign syntactic category labels after exposure to a range of syn- tactic strings, and Stemberger (1992) "has of- fered a connectionist model as a plausible ac- count of the characteristics of child phonology" (Leonard, 1995, p. 590).

A major strength of connectionist approaches to L1 acquisition is that, unlike their innatist counterparts, they appear to account for empiri- cally determined hallmarks of the acquisitional process. These hallmarks include: in the acquisi- tion of the lexicon, semantic overextension and

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Atkinson 2002

530 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

underextension (e.g., Barrett, 1995; Gruendel, 1977) and the "vocabulary burst" often seen in children during their second year (e.g., Bates, Dale, & Thal, 1995; Nelson, 1973); overgenerali- zation of past tense verb endings (e.g., Brown, 1973; Marchman & Bates, 1994); the comprehen- sion-production lag in language acquisition (e.g., E. V. Clark, 1983; Plunkett, 1995); and U-shaped growth in a number of areas (e.g., Brown, 1973; Plunkett, 1995).

Just as importantly, perhaps, connectionist re- searchers have modeled interdomain language ac- quisition. Thus, Bates et al. (1995) discussed the efficacy of connectionism in accounting for the "continuity hypothesis" (cf. Foster, 1990) relating early lexical development to early grammatical development in English. They pointed out that in the past tense morphology-learning simulations mentioned above there is "temporal asynchrony" between the acquisition of discrete lexical forms and the emergence of a rule-like system that cor- rectly assigns past tense inflectional endings to previously unseen verbs:

In the early stages of learning, the system appears to learn each mapping from present to past tense by rote, with no generalization to novel lexical forms.... As instances of present/past tense mapping accumu- late, some dramatic nonlinear changes are observed: the rate of learning accelerates markedly, overgener- alization errors start to appear, and the system starts to provide a default mapping to novel items.... Su- perficially, the network behaves as though it has switched from one mode of learning (rote) to an- other (rule). And yet there are no structural discon- tinuities in the system itself, or in the one-verb-at-a- time nature of the input.... Simply put, grammatical generalizations (i.e., rulelike behaviors) do not arise until this system has acquired enough instances to support those generalizations. When the requisite number of items has been acquired, dramatic changes can take place, even within a single system. (Bates et al., 1995, pp. 118-119)

Connectionist approaches to language acquisi- tion thus have the potential to tell us much about the cognitive mechanisms implicated in L1 acqui- sition. In addition, they have characteristics-to be discussed in the following two sections of this article-that allow the cognitive and social as- pects of language use and acquisition to be tied much more closely together than previously.

LANGUAGE AS A SOCIOCOGNITIVE PHENOMENON

In describing the social and cognitive attributes of language to this point, I have purposely tried

to keep them separate. In actual fact, however, a growing number of linguists, anthropologists, de- velopmental psychologists, and language acquisi- tion researchers do not accept such a dichotomy (e.g., Gee, 1990, 1992; Halliday, 1978; Hanks, 1996; Lave & Wenger, 1991; Ochs, 1992, 1996; Rogoff, 1990).6 Along with these scholars, I con- sider the social and cognitive aspects of language to have co-evolved from the beginning, and therefore to function interdependently--if not inseparably. In this section, I will try to describe how the social and the cognitive work together in this way.

A number of linguistic phenomena can, in fact, only be accounted for if the cognizing individ- ual's linguistic knowledge is seen to be abetted by, actuated within, and broadly continuous with a rich social context. Researchers (e.g., Goodwin, 1986, 1987; Lerner, 1993, 1996; Ochs et al., 1979), for example, have described the interac- tional accomplishment of propositions across indi- viduals-the remarkable ability of individuals to contribute jointly to the expression of a single idea or action. Such a feat is possible only in the presence of joint cognition-a form of intersubjec- tivity created and maintained on the basis of both shared (and highly-articulated) cognitive knowl- edge of the activity being engaged in, and a world that gives such activity a social purpose, a conven- tional shape (e.g., a participation structure), and an approximately agreed-upon means of linguis- tic expression.

Among socially-oriented linguists, conversation is frequently considered the paradigm speech ac- tivity within the human language-making capacity (e.g., Ochs et al., 1996). One of the foremost characteristics of conversation is its jointly-accom- plished nature, whether within or across utter- ances. Thus, topic nomination by one party often leads to multiple utterances on the topic (which itself may be subtly negotiated and modified in the interaction) by both the nominator and other parties, leading eventually to the expression of a broadly-shared perspective, if only for the dura- tion of the interaction (e.g., Goodwin, 1981, 1986, 1987). Likewise, conversational storytelling is a highly co-constructed sociocognitive activity, with different parties exercising influence over the story's course through their responses, by sharing more actively in its co-construction, or even by taking it over as it proceeds (Goodwin, 1986, 1987; Mandelbaum, 1987).7 The effective use of any language, in fact, crucially assumes the preexistence and interactionally-achieved devel- opment of shared sociocognitive perspec- tives-thus a basic precondition for effective lin-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 531

guistic reference (e.g., nominal, deictic, or defi- nite reference-H. H. Clark & Marshall, 1981; H. H. Clark & Wilkes-Gibbs, 1986) is that lan- guage users actively co-construct and adopt a common referential ground (Hanks, 1996).8

It is necessary at this point to consider in more detail how the cognizing individual and the so- cially-constructed and mediated world make their integrated contributions to linguistic activity in that world. In order to do so, I will adopt a con- nectionist understanding of cognition, but one that extends rather directly into the social world, and vice versa. My account substantially follows that of Gee (1992).

As described previously, connectionism posits that meaning/knowledge exists largely in poten- tial form in the human cognitive apparatus. That is, rather than having prebuilt cognitive struc- tures, or schemas stored in the brain, all that exists is the potential for such structures to be formed basically online through the activation of various networks of neural associations. Thus, meaning (or its material substrate) is distributed across a large number of neurons, all of which have varying probabilities of firing in concert with other neurons, depending both on the na- ture of the input stimulus and on what has been experienced in the past-and thus what connec- tions have been previously trained/socialized to activate together. For instance, while walking along a New England country road on a sunny summer day, a passing stranger's "Hi!" or "Nice weather we're having"-suitably accompanied by eye contact, a smile, a certain affective disposition (at least to the extent of desiring to communi- cate), the orientation of the speaker's face toward that of the (assumed) recipient of the utterance, delivered in a suitably friendly tone at a socially acceptable distance while enacting a socially ap- propriate identity, and so forth-will, in princi- ple, activate in the recipient a set of previously socialized neural connections leading to the ho- listic understanding that this is the speech act we call a greeting. Quite probably, it will also result in neurally-based and highly-patterned action by the recipient, comprising, among other things, a reciprocal physical orientation, affective stance, facial expression, tone of voice, and utter- ance-what we call a response.

What I first want to highlight in this example is the interactive, "outside-in" (Shore, 1996) nature of the sociocognitive event. Without the rich con- tribution of social (signifying) practices and tools such as facial expression, physical orientation, voice quality, language, social scene (an isolated New England byway), and social actors (strangers

approaching each other), neither cognition itself nor the resulting speech event could have taken place. Put a bit more metaphorically, perhaps, the acts of cognition described in this example are substantially continuous with the social world-they do not start in the head, although the head is certainly involved, nor do they end in the head, because the output is social action. Nor do the social (signifying) practices involved sim- ply take on their meaning once they arrive in the head; instead, they come with meaning already, in a sense, built in-just as language carries with it meaning that is only "borrowed" (Bakhtin, 1990) in specific instances of language use. The point here, then, is that cognition is not a private activity that occurs exclusively in the confines of an independent, isolated cerebral space, but rather that it is at least a semipublic activity, pro- duced as part of a substantially open system. Whenever we participate in social activity, we par- ticipate in conventional ways of acting and being that are already deeply saturated with signifi- cance.

Gee (1992, p. 12) gave the following example of how cognition (or at least knowledge) is both "in the head" and "in the world":

Consider the way people move around a city. Some people undoubtedly have quite impressive "maps" of the city in their heads, others have less complete ones, and some people have quite impoverished ones. However, people do not need to have any very full representations in their minds... since the struc- ture of the city, out in the world as it is, determines a good deal of their movement. . . . People's "knowl- edge" of the city is stored, in good part, out in the city itself. Their "city schema" ... is not just made up of things in their heads, it is also composed of the struc- tures in the city itself, as well as physical maps (and things like public transportation schedules) that peo- ple can read. (p. 12)

Thus, meaning resides (partway) in social products (e.g., cities, maps, country roads, cars), social practices (e.g., greeting somebody, read- ing, baking a cake, playing the role of teacher or student in a classroom), and social tools (e.g., language, literacy, computer programs, methods of navigation), even as it resides (partway) in the head.

A second, slightly different aspect of the coun- try road greeting example that I want to highlight is the profoundly integrative nature of the socio- cognitive event. That is, language activity and its cognitive correlates always occur as integral parts of larger sociocognitive wholes. Thus, without each of the following occurring and being cog- nized in relation to one another-socially signify-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Atkinson 2002

532 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

ing facial expressions and physical orientations, affective stance, a conventionalized social scene in a social setting with a social purpose per- formed by social actors, and the effective deploy- ment of the social tool of language-the activity of exchanging greetings could not have taken place. An important strength of connectionism is that it can account for such complex intertwin- ings of sensory and affective modalities, emer- gent cognitive structures, social phenomena, and language ability and use in the accomplishment of social activity. It does so in terms of the inter- actions of various sets of activated neurons-of neural networks that work together because of previous exposure to similar experience com- plexes (e.g., Gee, 1992, chap. 2; Strauss & Quinn, 1997, chap. 3). From this viewpoint, language per se is not the privileged and separate summum bonum, but rather an integral element of socio- cognitive activity, the ultimate purpose of which is to perform situated action-in-the-world.

LANGUAGE ACQUISITION AS A SOCIOCOGNITIVE PHENOMENON

Equally good arguments for the sociocognitive nature of language come from the circumstances of its acquisition. A well-established finding in L1 acquisition research is that external context plays a crucial role early on. In early acquisition of the lexicon, for instance, it is vital that children be able to link particular sounds, words, and phrases repetitively to the appearance of particular ob- jects or to the occurrence of particular actions (Barrett, 1995; see also Gee, 1995, described pre- viously). To say that linguistic form is simply being "input" into an autonomous language learning system at this point would be inaccurate; at minimum, both the form and the object/ac- tion are being cognitively represented in some kind of associative relationship. The widely ac- cepted notion of event representation (e.g., Barrett, 1995; Nelson, 1986) goes one step further, pro- viding a richer and, from a sociocognitive per- spective, more plausible view of early language acquisition. It postulates that children already have cognitively well-developed, organized asso- ciations of activity sequences, actors, and objects (along with open slots by which some actors and objects may be substituted for by others) onto which different words are initially mapped, and within which they thereafter become substantially integrated.

Nor is it just any external context that early language development depends on. Rather, social- interactional routines (e.g., Barrett, 1995; Gee,

1995) provide both the framework and the con- tent through which basic context-language form associations are made and internalized. Gee's (1995) routine principle and public principle, de- scribed earlier, capture important facets of how such routines provide repetitive, public, and highly-structured opportunities for infants to con- nect specific utterances with specific semantic complexes. Coordinated activity of infant and caregiver is central in this kind of routine---de- spite the fact that intentionality cannot be strictly attributed to infants, as aggressively stimulus-seek- ing organisms with a natural attraction to interac- tive and repetitive behavior (Locke, 1993) they learn to play their part early on. More specifically, the related notions of scaffolding (e.g., Ninio & Bruner, 1978), vertical constructions (Scollon, 1976), zone of proximal development (e.g., Cole, 1985; Vygostky, 1978), socializing attention (Zukow-Goldring & Ferko, 1994), and proposi- tions across individuals and utterances (Ochs et al., 1979) all reconceptualize the child and the caregiver as an interactional unit in their accom- plishment of sociocognitive tasks that the child could not perform independently, and, therefore, as a central mechanism of developmental growth.

It is generally thought that as L1 development progresses, context becomes a less important part of the acquisitional scheme. Thus, whereas chil- dren's early utterances are tied closely to the here and now (Foster, 1990), they become progres- sively less so as time goes on. This finding is often taken as evidence that some sort of basic lan- guage learning machinery has kicked fully into gear and is now operating on a fairly systematic and autonomous basis.

Although it is no doubt true that qualitative changes take place once linguistic knowledge reaches a certain critical mass for children, con- nectionist theories of cognition and language ac- quisition suggest that much if not all learning is accomplished not by progressively greater separa- tion of the knowledge being acquired from the external world and other domains of cognitive knowledge, but by their increasing integration. If this is the case, then it might be more accurate to say that context, rather than disappearing from the scene altogether, partly "comes inside." That is, as has been widely posited by neo-Vygotskian sociocultural theorists (e.g., Lantolf & Appel, 1994; Wertsch & Stone, 1985), the fundamental dynamic of acquiring language (as well as other "higher mental functions") is that formerly exter- nalized/social knowledge is substantially recon- figured as internalized/cognitive knowledge. But scholars who have recently attempted to link cog-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 533

nition via connectionism more closely to the so- cial and cultural world (e.g., Gee, 1992; Shore, 1996; Strauss & Quinn, 1997) might take excep- tion to the implications of the Vygotskian claim that language is, to some degree, gradually loos- ened during development from its moorings in social life. Rather, from this newer perspective, it might be more accurate to say that social life is now becoming articulated at a cognitive level in the development of cultural models (Gee, 1992; Holland & Quinn, 1987; Shore, 1996)-models that owe both their origins and their continued activation and use directly to their social exist- ence-and that in this important sense the cogni- tive and the social are growing progressively closer together.

If this version of connectionism is even ap- proximately correct, then the notion of "decon- textualized language"-so important in descrip- tions of later language and literacy learning and early success and failure in schooling-is perhaps neither useful nor accurate. That is, if context is taken to be only the immediate social and physi- cal setting of language behavior in the here and now-the context of situation first described by Malinowski (1923) and later elaborated by Halli- day (in Halliday & Hasan, 1989, chap. 1)-such language behavior might well be seen as thor- oughly decontextualized. But if context is more widely construed as context of culture (Halliday & Hasan, 1989; Malinowski, 1923; Ochs, 1990)-in- volving the increasing cognitive interarticulation of cultural models with social practices, social products, and social tools (including, crucially, how to deploy them effectively) -then to think of language as becoming progressively more decon- textualized and autonomous in the course of its acquisition may be fundamentally misguided.

Event representations in early Li acquisition, although sometimes claimed to be relatively tem- porary and evanescent, suggestively resemble early and relatively unarticulated schemas or mental models (or, in connectionist terms, net- works of neural associations out of which such schemas/models are formed basically online). Whether or not they provide a skeletal base for the later articulation of sociocultural knowledge in the form of cultural models, schemas, frames, or scripts (Cole, 1985), their early existence does suggest a sort of continuity of sociocognitive pro- cesses-the progressive "thickening" of "knowl- edge in the head" by "knowledge in the world"-the basic outside-in dynamic described by Shore (1996) and alluded to above. Put yet another way, any organism's progressive adapta- tion to its environment is a hallmark of develop-

mental growth. The gradual approximation by developing humans of what is "in the head" to what is "in the world" is just such an adaptive dynamic.

Gee (1992; following C. J. Fillmore, 1975) de- scribed the cultural model associated with the lexi- cal item bachelor According to Gee, the dictionary definition of bacheloras unmarried maleis only rudi- mentarily related to the dense linkings of associa- tions that fall within the culturally construed un- derstanding of bachelor. For one, bachelor invokes an idealized, culturally normative view of mascu- line sexuality. Thus, Roman Catholic priests, young boys, homeless men, and so forth, seem to fit into the category only problematically. Like- wise, when contrasted with the term spinster-its apparent gender counterpart-bachelor seems to carry with it the cultural presupposition that sin- gle men become progressively more eligible and desirable marriage partners as they grow older (or at minimum their eligibility never ceases), whereas women become progressively less so.

Although not all connections in the complex web of potential associations with the word bache- lor need be activated on every occasion of its use, the point is that such a rich, articulated back- ground exists, and that this background is located not only in cognitive but also social space. It might also be pointed out that examples of the type I have given in this article cannot even begin to approximate the extremely rich, complex, and highly-articulated kinds of sociocognitive knowl- edge that most humans are privy to simply by virtue of their lived experience and sociogenetic inheritance. To mention just one further (and more or less linguistic) element that must figure importantly in such highly developed knowledge complexes vis-a-vis language use, consider the growing realization among linguists that statisti- cal-collocational relationship between various linguistic features is a major principle in the syn- tagmatic and paradigmatic organization of lan- guage-in-use and its acquisition (e.g., Saffran, Aslin, & Newport, 1996; Seidenberg, 1996; Stubbs, 1996, chap. 2). Such knowledge is easily accounted for in terms of connectionist networks (Seidenberg, 1996), and would obviously be held in joint, if variable, ownership with one's social milieu. Taken together with the other kinds of knowledge I have so far mentioned and exempli- fied, it suggests "a semantics . . . more like an encyclopedia than a dictionary, [which] incorpo- rates the view that linguistic categories exist in relation to 'particular structured understandings of cultural institutions, beliefs about the world'" (Hanks, 1996, p. 244, including a quotation from

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Atkinson 2002

534 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

C. J. Fillmore, 1985). Although this formulation may still assume something of the traditional di- vide between the social and the cognitive I have been arguing against, it also captures some of the interpenetration and connectivity I am trying to portray.9

SLA AS A SOCIOCOGNITIVE PHENOMENON

Let me summarize the main argument of the article as developed to this point: Neither lan- guage acquisition nor language use-nor even cognized linguistic knowledge-can be properly understood without taking into account their fundamental integration into a socially-mediated world. Beyond simply saying that the cognitive and the social interact, I use recent research in linguistics, anthropology, language acquisition, and cognitive science-work I have necessarily had to rely on, because so little of its kind has yet been done in the field of SLA-to argue that they are mutually constituted. It is commonplace for cognitively-oriented and socially-oriented lan- guage researchers to assume (at least for working purposes) the separability of their domains. I ar- gue instead that these two domains cannot use- fully be separated: The coinage "sociocognitive" (e.g., Ochs, 1988b) is adopted to represent this distinct perspective.

With its beginnings in the cognitive psychology revolution of the 1960s (e.g., Brown, 1973; Cor- der, 1967), the field of SLA has adopted, by and large, a highly cognitivist view of second language learning (e.g., Breen, 1985; Crookes, 1997; Firth & Wagner, 1997). By cognitivist, I mean a perspec- tive that places SLA mainly within individual heads and that sees individuals therefore as radi- cally autonomous language acquirers (Penny- cook, 1997). Even where social variables appear to enter in, from this perspective, they do so only as indirect influences on the acquisitional process (R. Ellis, 1994).10

Although this shared perspective has provided a (very) roughly common ground for inquiry in SLA, it comes at the cost of denaturing reduction. If the development of "languaging" depends on greater engagement with and adaptation to the (socially-mediated) world--or, more accurately, on the progressive interarticulation of the social and the cognitive-then a SLA based substan- tially on such master concepts as input, the (ide- alized) learner, and a "lonely" version of cogni- tion is an impoverished endeavor.

Others have, of course, made similar points from time to time, and in recent years main- stream SLA has been increasingly criticized for

this reason (as seen, in part, in the quotations beginning this article). But Breen's (1985) plea to researchers and teachers to treat second lan-

guage classrooms as cultural scenes is still one of the most eloquent statements of the problem:

Given that we wish to understand how the external social situation of a classroom relates to the internal psychological states of the learner, the metaphor of the classroom as provider of optimal input or rein- forcer of good strategies is inadequate. It reduces the act or experience of learning a language to linguistic or behavioural conditioning somehow independent of the learner's social reality. Not only is SLA re- search currently offering us a delimited [sic] ac- count of language learning, reducing active cogni- tion to passive internalisation and reducing language to very specific grammatical performance, the mainstream of SLA research is also asocial. It neglects the social significance of even those vari- ables which the investigators regard as central. The priority given to linguistic and mentalistic variables in terms of the efficient processing of knowledge as input leads inevitably to a partial account of the lan- guage learning process. The social context of learn- ing and the social forces within it will always shape what is made available to be learned and the inter- action of individual mind with external linguistic or communicative knowledge. Even Wundt, the first ex- perimental psychologist, believed that he could not study higher mental processes such as reasoning, be- lief, thought, and language in a laboratory precisely because such processes were rooted within authentic social activity. (pp. 138-139)

Likewise, Vygotskian researchers (e.g., Hall, 1997; Lantolf, 2000; Lantolf & Appel, 1994) have argued against the reductive cognitivism of the field. Lantolf and Appel (1994), for example, criticized a view of the language learner "as a solipsistic biological organism whose cognitive powers simply unfold or ripen with the passage of time, rather than as someone who experiences productive participation in joint activity" (p. 11). Discourse analysts Firth and Wagner (1997) also offered a broad critique of SLA research as "indi- vidualistic and mechanistic"-as based on a per- spective that is:

weighted against the social and the contextual, and heavily in favour of the individual's cognition, par- ticularly the development of grammatical compe- tence. This has led to an imbalance of adopted theo- retical interests, priorities, foci, methodologies, perspectives..,. resulting in distorted descriptions of and views on discourse, communication, and inter- personal meaning-the quintessential elements of language. Moreover, this has occurred even in SLA work that is concerned with discourse and interac- tion. (p. 288)

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 535

Although I do not agree with elements of Firth and Wagner's argument, their general claim that mainstream SLA is lopsidedly cognitivist-and that much of its current practice virtually com- pels a view of language as radically disconnected from its natural environment, even in studies that seem to investigate language use in that environ- ment-is, in my opinion, all too accurate.11

Taking the just-mentioned critiques of SLA as part of a larger critical endeavor, I would like to delineate my own understanding of some key concepts in the field, and indicate where I find them at odds with a sociocognitive perspective.

Input

As dramatized at the beginning of this paper, I see the notion of input in mainstream SLA as coming fairly close to that of a switch or trigger, whether one adopts a Universal Grammar per- spective or not. At least one can say that input is of interest in this approach mainly as a stimulus activating an autonomous cognitive learning ap- paratus, which is assumed to perform certain (often unclearly-specified) processing opera- tions. In this way, the stimulus is converted into some kind of internal grammatical repre- sentation, which finds, over time, its proper rela- tionship with other such representations in a rule-governed structuralist system that is virtually immune to nonlinguistic influence. Even SLA studies of input modification and interaction (see below), which focus nominally on language-in- use, seem to adopt this scenario-or something quite like it-as their underlying "central dogma" (Crick, 1988).

Much of this characterization is problematic from a sociocognitive perspective. If knowledge of the world, including linguistic knowledge, is organized in the form of "actional wholes" (Hanks, 1996, p. 245, where actional refers to the fundamental purpose of language to contribute to the carrying out of action in the world), it is hard to imagine how such knowledge would de- velop via decontextualized internalization. The developing grammatical system as I have de- scribed it furthermore lacks any motivation other than perhaps a purely genetic one, which is why its description is often pervaded by an odd sort of anomie, in my opinion-it just is because it is. As I have tried to make clear, any approach to lan- guage and its acquisition which ignores or dis- misses the basic functionality of language for hu- man beings in society is lacking in descriptive and theoretical adequacy.

Interaction

Most SLA researchers who study "interaction" do so mainly for the sake of understanding its conditioning effect on input. This is made clear by Gass (1998):

The goal of my work (and the work of others within the input/interaction framework...) has never been to understand language use per se ... but rather to understand what types of interaction might bring about what types of changes in linguistic knowledge. (p. 84)

This is truly a pale reflection of the study of authentic human (linguistic) interaction, as Lid- dicoat (1997) noted:

What is missing... [in] the study of interaction in L2 contexts is interaction between people who have a preexisting relationship, who are interacting for the purpose of engaging in that relationship, and who are engaged in interaction in which their options for participating are not constrained by institutional roles.12 (p. 314)

In other words, what is missing in mainstream SLA is any concern whatsoever for the dominant forms of interaction in the world, and for those interactions qua interactions. The term therefore seems to be a misnomer, given the fact that the focus of work that purportedly studies it is still language-in-the-head. Again in the words of Lid- dicoat: "Essentially, what is happening here [in the contrived interactional settings favored in mainstream SLA] is an interaction designed to allow the NNS to produce a language sample [italics added]" (p. 315). From a sociocognitive perspec- tive this is hardly interaction at all.

The Language Learner

To put it bluntly, the language learner in main- stream SLA is something like an automaton, in- teresting only in the sense that it houses a discrete language learning system. This view is well at- tested in writing on the goals of SLA; to restate the words of Long (1997), cited at the beginning of this article: "Most SLA researchers view the object of inquiry as in large part an internal, mental process" (p. 319). If SLA is about lan- guage-learning human beings, they are therefore human only in a derivative sense-analogous, more or less, to the attenuated manner in which language is considered "creative" by Chomskyans.

As noted previously, I frequently find the read- ing of SLA research to be almost an exercise in surrealism-based, I believe, in the just-men- tioned contradictory "present absence" of human

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: Atkinson 2002

536 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

beings. Human beings as I know them, whether people on the street, students I teach and work with, professional colleagues, or those I am close to and love, appear to act, think, and feel in ways and for reasons entirely different than those most typically featured in SLA research. Case studies, diary studies, and (mostly earlier) work that fo- cuses on authentic interaction and language use (e.g., L. W. Fillmore, 1979; Saville-Troike, 1988; Schmidt, 1983; Schmidt & Frota, 1986) are some of the exceptions I know of in this regard-and they are admirable exceptions.

(Scientific) Methods

From the start, SLA was "scientized" by its prac- titioners (Block, 1996). This was partly because it adopted cognitive psychology and linguistics as its source disciplines (e.g., Crookes, 1997; Mitchell & Myles, 1998). As time went on, however, a sec- ond good reason for seeing SLA as science be- came apparent: Academic politics and prestige favored doing so, especially if SLA was thereby dissociated from the low-status occupation of lan- guage teaching (Schachter, 1993). Although this move may have brought a certain amount of re- spect-by-(dis?) association to the field, recent charges of "science envy" (Block, 1996) or "phys- ics envy" (Lantolf, 1996) are, in some respects, not far off the mark. The idea that one can study inherently social phenomena by applying meth- ods and approaches originally developed to de- scribe the behavior of inanimate objects has been widely critiqued, starting as far back, perhaps, as Wundt (see quotation from Breen, 1985, given above). Strong arguments have also been made to the effect that quantitative scientific method- ologies, because they neutralize by design what is variable and individual (in human behavior or otherwise), produce epiphenomenally uniform accounts (e.g., Daston, 1995; Hacking, 1981; Por- ter, 1995). That is, uniform results have been ar- gued to be substantially an artifact of methodolo- gies which, in a sense, presuppose them-for example, by statistical generalization or strict con- trol of "extraneous" variables. Although such cri- tiques have been widespread in the social sci- ences over the past 20 or so years, it is of more than passing interest that defenders of main- stream scientized SLA (e.g., most of the contribu- tors to Beretta, 1993) tend to rely for their argu- ments more on the (nonempirical) philosophy of science, than on actual, empirical accounts of sci- entific behavior (e.g., Collins, 1985; Gilbert & Mulkay, 1984; Latour & Woolgar, 1986; Traweek, 1988).

Cognition

In mainstream SLA cognition is a "lonely" pro- cess taking place within an autonomous language learning organism. Its forte is the processing of input/construction of linguistic knowledge. It serves as a bank of internal linguistic knowledge, or competence, which most often has only an indirect connection to language performance. Even non-mainstream areas of SLA that focus on language performance, such as interlanguage pragmatics, sometimes seem to assume this view (e.g., Kasper, 1997).

Language

Where language is reduced substantially to grammar, and its use largely to the provision of input, there exists a reductiveness approaching that of Chomksy's influential vision. From a socio- cognitive perspective, however, language is an abundantly rich resource for getting on in the world-for performing social action. Language is intricately but dynamically interwoven with hu- mans' other means of ecological adaptation and activity, and removing it from that context comes at a real cost.

Beyond simply defining a sociocognitive ap- proach to SLA negatively by criticizing SLA ortho- doxy, however, I would also like to provide a view of what it is, or, more accurately, what it could be. One thing is clear: Such a perspective does not yet exist in SLA. For this reason, it will be possible to go just so far in conjuring up its image.

First, a sociocognitive approach to SLA would take the social dimensions of language and its acquisition seriously. Interaction in sociocognitive SLA would have its full sociocognitive signifi- cance and constitute a foundational concept. Language is learned in interaction, often with more capable social members. Classroom teach- ers are part of this group where second languages are concerned, but only a part-peers, mentors, role models, friends, family members, and signifi- cant others can also fall into this category. Al- though interaction might not include conversa- tion in all cases, it would certainly entail the deep, holistic investment of learners in learning activi- ties, and would see those learners as active agents, not passive recipients.

Second, language and its acquisition would be fully integrated into other activities, people, and things in a sociocognitive approach to SLA. They would be seen as integral parts of larger sociocog- nitive wholes, or, in Gee's (1992) term, Discourses: "Discourses are composed of people, of ob-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 14: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 537

jects . . . and of... talking, acting, interacting, thinking, believing, and valuing, and sometimes. . .writing, reading, and/or interpreting .... Dis- courses are out in the world, like books, maps, and cities" (p. 20). In other words, language would be seen in terms of its rich ecological/con- textual/relational "worldliness" (Pennycook, 1994) and complexity rather than its simplicity, parsimony, and autonomy.

Third, language and its acquisition, from a so- ciocognitive perspective, would be seen in terms of "action" and "participation"-as providing an extremely powerful semiotic means of perform- ing and participating in activity-in-the-world (Ro- goff, 1990, 1998; Lave & Wenger, 1991). It is just because language serves this vital function, one could say, that it exists and that people acquire it: One does not usually acquire a language in order to acquire it, or talk about it, or provide data for SLA researchers. One acquires a language in or- der to act, and by acting, in a world where lan- guage is performative. This is exactly why and how children learn their first language, and it accounts as well for most of the second/addi- tional language learning going on in the world today. It is an extremely unfortunate matter that we have some influential myths suggesting other- wise-for example, that SLA takes place primarily in cases where students are taught something dis- crete called language (Gee, 1990), or that SLA takes place within isolated heads whose only mo- tivation is creative construction.

Finally, a sociocognitive perspective should not, strictly speaking, exclude. As an approach to language, it is fundamentally cognitive and funda- mentally social. A sociocognitive perspective does not diminish a view of language as one or the other-it argues for the profound interdepen- dency and integration of both. Thus, although I have described a cognitivist view of SLA as "im- poverished," that is not the same as saying it is wrong. In fact, I believe that cognitivists have contributed to our understanding-however ten- tative and partial at this point--of SLA. But if language is in the world at the same time as it is in the head, then we need to account for its integrated existence, rather than adopt positions that reduce the life-the humanity--out of lan- guage.

A NOTE ON NEO-VYGOTSKIAN SOCIOCULTURAL THEORY IN SLA

Given the increasing popularity of a non-main- stream form of SLA theory-neo-Vygotskian so- ciocultural theory--which tries to address some

of the same problems with mainstream SLA re- search discussed in this article, I would like here briefly to indicate where I believe my approach differs from this one and is not simply reducible to it.

A major claim of Vygotsky-and a claim that seems typically to be assumed or endorsed by current neo-Vygotskian SLA researchers (e.g., Lantolf, 2000)-was that language appears, devel- opmentally speaking, first on the interpsychologi- cal plane (i.e., as social speech) and only after- wards on the intrapsychological plane (i.e., as internalized or inner speech). There is thus a gradual process of internalization whereby a fully externalized social practice becomes a substan- tially internalized cognitive practice (e.g., Lan- tolf, 2000; Lantolf with Pavlenko, 1995). In fact, according to Vygotsky, this is how people learn to cognize-how "higher mental development" oc- curs: "Any higher mental function was external because it was social at some point before becoming an internal, truly mental function [italics added]" (Vy- gotsky, 1981, p. 162).

In a recent major statement of sociocultural theory in SLA, Lantolf (2000) has echoed Vygot- sky's view:

Internalization is in essence the process through which higher forms of mentation come to be. Inter- nalization then assumes that the [original] source of consciousness resides outside of the head and is in fact anchored in social activity. At first the activity of individuals is organized and regulated (i.e., medi- ated) by others, but eventually, in normal develop- ment, we come to organize and regulate our own mental and physical activity through the appropria- tion of the regulatory means employed by others. At this point psychological functioning comes under the voluntary control of the person. (pp. 13-14)

From this point of view, we could say that lan- guage is sociocognitive in a manner of speaking, but only or most substantially in its developmental profile (see also Kirshner & Whitson, 1997, for a similar critique). That is, language starts social, but becomes substantially cognitive as develop- ment proceeds: in the words, once again, of Lan- tolf (2000), "The convergence of thinking [i.e., the cognitive] with culturally created mediational artifacts [i.e., the social] ... occurs in the process of internalization, or the reconstruction on the inner, psychological plane, of socially mediated external forms of goal-directed activity" (p. 13). For some neo-Vygotskians this may be a sufficient explanation of both language development and use in toto, given that for Vygotsky, "to under- stand behavior means to understand the history of

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 15: Atkinson 2002

538 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

behavior [italics added] "(cited in Cole, 1993, p. 9).13

But my own argument-as developed on a step- by-step basis in this article-is that although lan- guage may perhaps be seen from some points of view as more or less internalized and self-regu- lated-as the property of an individual, cognitive self-in actuality it always and everywhere exists in an integrated sociocognitive space. In terms of the above-given formulation of Vygotsky (1981), I would therefore argue that, contra his view, language (no matter what its stage of develop- ment) never takes on an "internal, truly mental function" at all. Rather, it is always mutually, si- multaneously, and co-constitutively in the head and in the world. Certainly, at critical points in development, language may seem to "come in- side"-but if one end of language, so to speak, is embedded in cognitive space, the other end is just as strongly embedded in social space.

In actual fact, this use of spatial and object-ori- ented metaphors to describe language hardly suf- fices, but I hope at least to have indicated what I believe is a basic difference-certainly at least in terms of emphasis-between what I propose here and what many neo-Vygotkians assume or are proposing in their SLA work. There are other differences-for instance, the artificial tasks and conditions that have historically obtained in Vy- gotskian research, and the need in such research to break behavior down into component parts while at the same time professing holism (e.g., Wertsch, 1998; see also Kirshner & Whitson, 1997). But the first-mentioned difference is the most important one, and from it many of the other differences proceed. This is not to say that I do not value or respect research being done in this framework in the field, nor that it has not contributed significantly to my own thinking on SLA.

CONCLUSION

What, then, are some of the implications of a sociocognitive view of SLA? Here I will speculate because, as I have already pointed out, no such coherent view yet exists. In the interim, I will take my cues largely from pedagogically-oriented L1i research on situated cognition, social linguistics, and learning-as-participation (e.g., Gee, 1990, 1992; Kirshner & Whitson, 1997; Lave & Wenger, 1991; Rogoff, 1990, 1998; Wenger, 1998; cf. Atkin- son, 1997). I should also note that although sev- eral of the implications described below are in areas that are already receiving attention in sec-

ond language education, they have not yet in most cases been closely linked to SLA theory.

One implication of a sociocognitive approach to SLA is that teaching is valuable, and that learn- ing and teaching go hand-in-hand (a view that mainstream SLA, incidently, has yet to agree on-Crookes, 1997; R. Ellis, 1997). But teaching in this view is also often incidental: If one learns by participating in specific and meaningful social activity, then co-participants are often one's teachers. The expert-novice (or master-appren- tice) metaphor emanating from studies of situ- ated cognition is a useful thinking tool in this context, exactly because it emphasizes learning through active and increasingly knowledgeable participation in a particular "community of prac- tice." But this metaphor should not be taken to imply that learners and those they learn from are profoundly separated. As already noted, peers can be teachers, depending on the situation, and the same is true for all others with whom we have social relationships. If we consider that most of the additional language learning going on in the world today is of this nonformal variety, then we have a more realistic notion of teaching, and how teaching and learning interact. If, as second lan- guage teachers, we can harness more of the range of teaching situations that actually take place in the world outside the classroom (e.g., Atkinson, 1997, 1998; Hawkins, 1998), then we will be able to utilize more fully the teaching and learning potential of all human beings.

A second implication of a sociocognitive ap- proach to SLA is intimately related to the view that language and its acquisition are not radically disconnected from the rest of the world. Lan- guage-in-the-world suggests a richness and power for it that extends well beyond the transfer of information from brain to brain. A sociocognitive approach to SLA promotes and reinforces many connections to other realms of inquiry and prac- tice, such as: culture (e.g., Atkinson, 1999; Kramsch, 1993); schooling (e.g., Poole, 1992); identity (e.g., Peirce, 1995); power, politics, and ideology (e.g., Fairclough, 1992; Gee, 1990, 1992; Pennycook, 1994); discourse (e.g., Firth & Wag- ner, 1997); social ecology (e.g., Capra, 1996; Schumacher, 1997); and embodied action-taking (e.g., Goodwin, 2000). When one considers the deep involvement of second/additional lan- guages in world politics, exploitative capitalism, and globalization (e.g., Pennycook, 1994, 1998; Phillipson, 1992), then a very real gain is realized in the intrinsic consequentiality of studying, learning, and teaching them. We need and can have a SLA-not to mention approaches to sec-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 16: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 539

ond language teaching--with real potential for changing the world, rather than being radically separated from it.

A third implication of the sociocognitive study of SLA concerns research methods for studying the learning and teaching of second/additional languages. Although individual-aggregating sta- tistical and experimental methods have a place in SLA, studying real humans in real human con- texts and interactions, including classrooms, en- tails methodologies that do not denature phe- nomena by removing them from their natural environments and breaking them down into countable component parts. Qualitative research approaches that attempt to honor the profound wholeness and situatedness of social scenes and individuals-in-the-world, such as ethnographic methods (e.g., Holliday, 1996; Lazaraton & Davis, 1995; Ramanathan & Atkinson, 1999), will have a central place in this endeavor. One further im- portant advantage of such methodologies is that they are less likely to reproduce the theory-prac- tice divide-the asymmetrical division of labor between (classroom) teachers and researchers. In the suggestive phrasing of Holliday (1994), "the teacher cannot afford to be anything but a re- searcher" (p. 31) where broad sociocognitive connections are acknowledged between the class- room and the outside world. Likewise, class- rooms, among other kinds of learning situations, can be studied via these methods as complex so- ciocognitive activity systems in their own right (Breen, 1985; Holliday, 1996).

Fourth and finally, sociocognitive approaches to SLA will provide a means by which second language learners can be seen as real people, doing something they naturally do-not as mere research subjects, or mere students, or mere sites for language acquisition. Perhaps the theme I have emphasized above others in this article is that thought, feeling, and activity in the social world are brought together in the form of human beings actively operating as part of that world. It is therefore fitting to give the last word to Lave and Wenger (1991), two scholars who have done much to promote this view:

Participation in social practice . . . suggests a very explicit focus on the person, but person-in-the-world, as member of a sociocultural community. This focus in turn promotes a view of knowing as activity by specific people in specific circumstances. As an aspect of social practice, learning involves the

whole person: it implies not only a relation to specific activities, but a relation to social communities-it im- plies becoming a full participant, a member, a kind of person. .. . Activities, tasks, functions, and under-

standings do not exist in isolation; they are part of broader systems of relations in which they have mean- ing. These systems of relations arise out of and are reproduced and developed within social communi- ties, which are in part systems of relations among persons. The person is defined by as well as defines these relations. Learning thus implies becoming a different person with respect to the possibilities en- abled by these systems of relations. To ignore this aspect of learning is to overlook the fact that learning involves the construction of identities. (pp. 52-53)

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

James Paul Gee first introduced me to many of the ideas developed in this article. I would like to thank him, as well as A. Vishnu Bhat, Michelle Burnham, Joan Carson, John Hedgcock, Hiroko Itakura, Robert B. Kaplan, Wakako Kobayashi, Claire Kramsch, Ilona Leki, Takako Nishino, and Nirmal Selvamony, for their critical comments and encouragement in what has been a drawn- out writing/publishing process. David Beglar, Suresh Canagarajah, George Kamberelis, Genevieve Patthey-Chavez, and Vai Ramanathan also generously read and commented on earlier drafts. I would further like to thank the MLJedi- tor, Sally Sieloff Magnan, and the four anony- mous reviewers for their thoughtful editing and comments. This article is dedicated to the mem- ory of Matha Bean.

NOTES

1 The sociocognitive approach developed here takes its lead from a wide variety of disciplines and ap- proaches: cognitive and cultural anthropology (e.g., Hanks, 1996; Shore, 1996; Strauss & Quinn, 1997); soci- ology (e.g., Berger & Luckmann, 1966; Goffman, 1959; Sacks et al., 1974); social linguistics (Gee, 1990, 1992); sociolinguistics and language socialization studies (e.g., Hymes, 1972; Ochs, 1988a, 1988b, 1990, 1992, 1996; Schieffelin & Ochs, 1986); neo-Vygotskian sociocultural theory (e.g., Lantolf, 2000; Lantolf & Appel, 1994; Vy- gotsky, 1981; Wertsch, 1985, 1998); studies of situated cognition/learning and communities of practice (e.g., Brown, Collins, & Duguid, 1989; Kirshner & Whitson, 1997; Lave & Wenger, 1991; Rogoff, 1990; Wenger, 1998); cognitive science and connectionism (e.g., Churchland, 1996; A. Clark, 1997; Elman et al., 1996; Rumelhart & McClellan, 1986; Seidenberg, 1996); L1 acquisition (e.g., Bates et al., 1995; Foster, 1990; Plunkett, 1995); SLA (e.g., Breen, 1985; Firth & Wagner, 1997; Peirce, 1995); and studies of conversation and interaction (e.g., Goodwin, 1986, 1987, 2000; Lerner, 1993, 1996; Ochs et al., 1996).

The term sociocognitive has been used in a variety of

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 17: Atkinson 2002

540 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

contexts in a number of different disciplines, some of which are listed above. My own first exposure to the term came in a graduate class in sociolinguistics taught by Elinor Ochs, one of the main proponents of some of the views I develop here (e.g., Ochs, 1988a; Ochs et al., 1996).

2 As this is a historical description, I do not refer to more recent Chomskyan formalisms. In fact, however, Chomsky's basic theory of language (as opposed to its ever-changing formal realizations) has remained re- markably stable over the years (e.g., Chomsky, 2000).

3 This same basic point is at least implicit in Hymes's (1972) original conceptualization of communicative competence, which I regard as foundational to a socio- cognitive view of language.

4 The point has even been made (e.g., Goffman, 1959) that, given an utterance in which the proposi- tional content and the nonpropositional content are in conflict, the latter is usually taken as the final arbiter of meaning.

5 Implicit in most definitions of connectionism is the notion of parallel distributed processing-often taken to be its virtual synonym. Parallel (vs. serial) processing in- volves the simultaneous carrying out of large numbers of computational events (vs. the step-by-step nature of serial processing), whereas distributed (versus central) processing indicates that cognitive computational activ- ity is spread out over a large number of neurons/neural connections, rather than having to depend on any one or a small number of them.

6 This approach is part of a broader critique across the social sciences of mainstream psychology as the study of "lonely cognition," instead of self-in-context (e.g., Gergen, 1985; Hutchins, 1995; Lave & Wenger, 1991; Rogoff, 1990, 1998). A deeper and more philo- sophical critique of the self is a major theme in post- modernist and poststructuralist thought (see, e.g., At- kinson, 1999) but is beyond the scope of this article.

7 At the same time, participants hew closely to the conventional story structure and register of narratives, or if they do not are usually brought into line.

8 Deixis is perhaps the paradigm example here, but the same basic claim can be made across linguistic do- mains and systems (Hanks, 1996; Ochs, 1992).

9 In general, the descriptions given in this section are incomplete as they stand in that they do not sufficiently capture the bidirectionality of influence and interpene- tration of social and cognitive processes. Because I am partly focusing on cognition here-specifically as it con- cerns the issue of "decontextualized language"-I have necessarily had to downplay the reciprocal influence of the cognitive on the social, as well as the continuous and integrated nature of feedback between them. To give two examples by way of atonement and the restoration of holistic bidirectionality: (a) The design of our cogni- tive apparatus fundamentally influences the way we per- ceive things, so that social practices and products must be preadapted to our cognitive-sensory capabilities; and (b) Gee's (1992) description of the sociocognitive sche- mas of cities demonstrates profound sociocognitive in- terpenetration and interaction. In fact, although I will

not seek to articulate them here, substantial areas of the interpenetration of cognitive and social phenomena must operate much more dynamically and dialecti- cally-perhaps along the lines of Giddens' (1979) no- tion of structuration (see also Atkinson, 1999). Thus, it can be said that individuals and social groups not only progressively adapt to their environments, but that they also actively construct those environments in many and varied ways. Larsen-Freeman's (1997) third meaning of the term "dynamic" (p. 148) in describing language from a chaos/complexity perspective-although it still seems to depend in some senses on the much-ques- tioned notion of linguistic rules-captures something of the interactivity, feedback-sensitivity, and constructed- ness of "languaging" (Larsen-Freeman herself uses the term grammaring) I am trying to get at here. In general, I find Larsen-Freeman's discussion of chaos/complexity theory vis-4-vis SLA inspirational in its potential for refo- cusing the field.

10 This view seems problematic if one is to define language more broadly than a set of grammatical forms and rules. How would one account for the acquisition of norms of politeness (e.g., Brown & Levinson, 1987; Tan- nen, 1986), for instance, other than by appealing to the direct effect of social factors? Tannen has shown in various publications that politeness is an aspect of lan- guage that is central to its use and functionality-every bit as important as the grammatical features more stan- dardly studied in SLA.

11 Two SLA researchers whose work has been largely within the cognitivist tradition seem recently to have realized the reductionism inherent in that tradition. R. Ellis (1997)-partly cited at the beginning of this arti- cle-and Crookes (1997), respectively, state: "SLA in general has paid little attention to the social context of L2 acquisition, particularly where context is viewed non- deterministically (i.e., as something learners construct for themselves). SLA has been essentially a psycholin- guistic enterprise, dominated by the computational metaphor of acquisition" (R. Ellis, 1997, p. 87). "Though cognitive psychology [as a source discipline for SLA research] was to be preferred to its dominant predecessor [i.e., behaviorism] because it was (purport- edly, at least) about people (rather than rats), it was a long time before I began to understand that it ... could be seen as a sociocultural construct ... that reflected at least to some extent the presumptions of the societies in which it developed. That was why it was fundamentally an individualist psychology that treats people as isolates" (Crookes, 1997, p. 98).

It is noteworthy that both of these statements were made in articles discussing the relevance of SLA to sec- ond language teaching.

12 Although any claim that participation in interac- tion between familiars is not constrained by institutional roles is highly questionable (e.g., Bourdieu, 1984), Lid- dicoat is clearly making a distinction here between what conversation analysts call "ordinary conversation" and what they call "institutional interaction" (for more on this distinction, see Drew & Heritage, 1992).

13 If this is not an understanding of language shared

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 18: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 541

by all neo-Vygotskians (e.g., Rogoff, 1998; Wertsch, 1998), it still seems a dominant emphasis among neo-Vy- gotskians who study SLA, as seen in the Lantolf quota- tions given earlier in this section. To me, this emphasis represents a particularly literalistic interpretation of Vy- gotsky's original thought.

REFERENCES

Atkinson, D. (1997). A critical approach to critical thinking in TESOL. TESOL Quarterly, 31, 71-94.

Atkinson, D. (1998). Forum response to comments on "A critical approach to critical thinking in TESOL." TESOL Quarterly, 32, 133-137.

Atkinson, D. (1999). TESOL and culture. TESOL Quar- terly, 33, 625-654.

Bakhtin, M. M. (1990). Marxism and the philosophy of language. In P. Bizzell & B. Herzberg (Eds.), The rhetorical tradition: Readings from classical times to the present (pp. 928-944). New York: St. Martins.

Barrett, M. (1995). Early lexical development. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhinney (Eds.), The handbook of child language (pp. 362-392). Oxford, UK: Black- well.

Bates, E., Dale, P. S., & Thal, D. (1995). Individual dif- ferences and their implications for theories of lan- guage development. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhin- ney (Eds.), The handbook of child language (pp. 96-151). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Becker, A. L. (1979). Text-building, epistemology, and aesthetics in Javanese shadow theatre. In A. L. Becker & A. A. Yengoyan (Eds.), The imagination of reality: Essays in southeast Asian coherence systems (pp. 211-243). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Becker, A. L. (1988). Language in particular: A lecture. In D. Tannen (Ed.), Linguistics in context: Connect- ing observation and understanding. Advances in dis- course processes (Vol. 29, pp. 17-35). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Beretta, A. (Ed.). (1993). Theory construction in SLA [Special issue]. Applied Linguistics, 14(3).

Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social construc- tion of reality. New York: Doubleday.

Block, D. (1996). Not so fast: Some thoughts on theory culling, relativism, accepted findings and the heart and soul of SLA. Applied Linguistics, 17, 63-83.

Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A social critique of the judgement of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni- versity Press.

Bourdieu, P. (1991). Language and symbolic power Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Bower, T. G. R., & Wishart, J. G. (1979). Towards a unitary theory of development. In E. B. Thoman (Ed.), Origins of the infant's social responsiveness (pp. 65-93). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Breen, M. P. (1985). The social context of language learning-A neglected situation? Studies in Second Language Acquisition, 7, 135-158.

Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Situated

cognition and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18, 32-42.

Brown, P., & Levinson, S. C. (1987). Politeness: Some uni- versals of language usage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Brown, R. (1973). A first language: The early stages. Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Capra, E (1996). The web of life: A new scientific under- standing of living systems. New York: Doubleday.

Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Churchland, P. M. (1996). The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: A philosophical journey into the brain. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press.

Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Clark, E. V. (1983). Meanings and concepts. In P. Mussen (Series Ed.) & J. H. Flavell & E. M. Mark- man (Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 3. Cognitive development (4th ed., pp. 687-782). New York: Wiley.

Clark, H. H., & Marshall, C. R. (1981). Definite refer- ence and mutual knowledge. In A. K. Joshi, B. Webber, & I. Sag (Eds.), Elements of discourse under- standing (pp. 10-63). Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press.

Clark, H. H., & Wilkes-Gibbs, D. (1986). Referring as a collaborative process. Cognition, 22, 1-39.

Cole, M. (1985). The zone of proximal development: Where culture and cognition create each other. In J. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication and cogni- tion: Vygotskian perspectives (pp. 146-161). Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Cole, M. (1993, April). Vygotsky and writing: Reflections on a distant discipline. Paper presented at Conference on College Composition and Communication, San Diego, CA.

Collins, H. M. (1985). Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. London: Sage.

Corder, H. P. (1967). The significance of learners' er- rors. International Review of Applied Linguistics, 5, 161-169.

Crick, F. (1988). What mad pursuit: A personal view of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.

Crookes, G. (1997). SLA and language pedagogy: A socioeducational perspective. Studies in Second Language Acquisition, 19, 93-116.

Daston, L. (1995). The moral economy of science. Osiris, 10, 3-24.

Davis, K. (1995). Qualitative theory and methods in applied linguistic research. TESOL Quarterly, 29, 427-454.

Drew, P., & Heritage, J. (1992). Analyzing talk at work: An introduction. In P. Drew & J. Heritage (Eds.), Talk at work: Interaction in institutional settings (pp. 3-65). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Edelsky, C. (1981). Who's got the floor? Language in Society, 10, 383-421.

Eimas, P. D. (1975). Speech perception in early infancy. In L. B. Cohen & P. Salapatek (Eds.), Infant percep-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 19: Atkinson 2002

542 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

tion: From sensation to cognition (Vol. 2, pp. 193-231). New York: Academic Press.

Ellis, N. C. (1998). Emergentism, connectionism, and language learning. Language Learning, 48, 631-664.

Ellis, R. (1994). The study of second language acquisition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Ellis, R. (1997). SLA and language pedagogy: An educa- tional perspective. Studies in Second LanguageAcqui- sition, 19, 69-92.

Elman, J. L. (1992). Learning and development in neu- ral networks: The importance of starting small. In C. Umilta & M. Moscovitch (Eds.), Attention and performance IX: Conscious and nonconscious informa- tion processing (pp. 861-889). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff- Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Re- thinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on de- velopment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Fairclough, N. (1992). Discourse and social change. Cam- bridge, UK Polity.

Fillmore, C. J. (1975). An alternative to checklist theo- ries of meaning. In Proceedings of the First Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (pp. 123-131). Berkeley, CA: University of California.

Fillmore, C. J. (1985). Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica, 6, 222-253.

Fillmore, C.J., Kay, P., & O'Connor, M. C. (1988). Regu- larity and idiomaticity in grammatical construc- tions. Language, 64, 501-538.

Fillmore, L. W. (1979). Individual differences in second language acquisition. In C. J. Fillmore (Ed.), Indi- vidual differences in language ability and language be- havior (pp. 203-228). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

Firth, A., & Wagner, J. (1997). On discourse, commu- nication, and (some) fundamental concepts in SLA research. Modern Language Journal, 81, 285-300.

Foster, S. H. (1990). The communicative competence of young children. London: Longman.

Gass, S. (1998). Apples and oranges: Or, why apples are not orange and don't need to be: A response to Firth and Wagner. Modern Language Journal, 82, 83-90.

Gee, J. P. (1990). Social linguistics and literacies: Ideology in discourses. London: Falmer Press.

Gee, J. P. (1992). The social mind. London: Bergin & Garvey.

Gee, J. P. (1995). First language acquisition as a guide for theories of learning and pedagogy. Linguistics and Education, 6, 331-354.

Gergen, K. (1985). The social constructionist move- ment in modern psychology. American Psychologist, 40, 266-275.

Giddens, A. (1979). Central problems in social theory: Ac- tion, structure and contradiction in social analysis. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Gilbert, G. N., & Mulkay, M. (1984). Opening Pandora's

box: A sociological analysis of scientific discourse. Cam-

bridge: Cambridge University Press. Goffman, E. (1959). The presentation of self in everyday life.

New York: Anchor/Doubleday. Goodwin, C. (1981). Conversational organization: Interac-

tion between speakers and hearers. New York: Aca- demic Press.

Goodwin, C. (1986). Audience diversity, participation and interpretation. Text, 6, 283-316.

Goodwin, C. (1987). Unilateral departure. In G. Button & J. R. E. Lee (Eds.), Talk and social organization (pp. 206-216). Clevedon, UK- Multilingual Mat- ters.

Goodwin, C. (2000). Action and embodiment within situated human interaction. Journal of Pragmatics, 32, 1489-1522.

Goodwin, C., & Goodwin, M. H. (1992). Assessments and the construction of context. In A. Duranti & C. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language as an interactive phenomenon (pp. 147-189). Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gould, S. J. (1981). The mismeasure of man. New York: Norton.

Gregg, K. (1988). Second language acquisition theory: The case for a generative perspective. In S. M. Gass & J. Schachter (Eds.), Linguistic perspectives on second language acquisition (pp. 15-40). New York:

Cambridge University Press. Gruendel, J. (1977). Referential extension in early lan-

guage development. Child Language, 48, 567-576. Gumperz, J. J. (1982). Discourse strategies. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press. Hacking, I. (1981). Representing and intervening. Cam-

bridge: Cambridge University Press. Hall, J. K. (1997). A consideration of SLA as a theory of

practice: A response to Firth and Wagner. Modern Language Journal, 81, 301-306.

Halliday, M. A. K. (1978). Language as social semiotic: The social interpretation of language and meaning. Lon- don: Edward Arnold.

Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1989). Language, context, and text: Aspects of language in a social-semioticperspec- tive. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hanks, W. F. (1996). Language form and communica- tive practices. In J. J. Gumperz & S. C. Levinson (Eds.), Rethinking linguistic relativity (pp. 232-270). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hawkins, M. (1998). Forum response to Dwight Atkin- son's "A critical approach to critical thinking in TESOL." TESOL Quarterly, 32, 127-132.

Holland, D., & Quinn, N. (1987). Cultural models in language and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press.

Holliday, A. (1994). Appropriate methodology in social con- text. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Holliday, A. (1996). Developing a sociological imagina- tion: Expanding ethnography in international English language education. Applied Linguistics, 17, 234-255.

Hopper, P. (1988). Emergent grammar and the a priori grammatical postulate. In D. Tannen (Ed.), Lin-

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 20: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 543

guistics in context: Connecting observation and under- standing. Advances in discourse processes (Vol. 29, pp. 117-134). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Hymes, D. (1972). On communicative competence. In J. B. Pride & J. Holmes (Eds.), Sociolinguistics: Se- lected readings (pp. 269-293). Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.

Kasper, G. (1997). "A" stands for acquisition: A response to Firth and Wagner. Modern LanguageJournal, 81, 307-312.

Kemper, S. (1987). Life-span changes in syntactic com- plexity. Journal of Gerontology, 42, 323-328.

Kendon, A. (1992). The negotiation of context in face- to-face interaction. In A. Duranti & C. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language as an interactive phenomenon (pp. 323-334). Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press.

Kirshner, D., & Whitson, J. A. (Eds.). (1997). Situated cognition theory: Social, neurological, and semiotic per- spectives. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Kramsch, C. (1993). Context and culture in language teach- ing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Langacker, R. W. (1987). Foundations of cognitive gram- mar,

Vol. 1. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Lantolf, J. P. (1996). SLA theory building: "Letting all the flowers bloom!" Language Learning, 46, 713-749.

Lantolf, J. P. (Ed.). (2000). Sociocultural theory and second language learning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lantolf,J. P., & Appel, G. (1994). Vygotskian approaches to second language research. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Lantolf,J. P. (with Pavlenko, A.). (1995). Sociocultural theory and second language acquisition. Annual Review of Applied Linguistics, 15, 108-124.

Larsen-Freeman, D. (1991). Second language acquisi- tion research: Staking out the territory. TESOL Quarterly, 25, 315-350.

Larsen-Freeman, D. (1997). Chaos/complexity science and second language acquisition. Applied Linguis- tics, 18, 141-165.

Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts (2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Lave,J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lazaraton, A., & Davis, K. (Eds.). (1995). Qualitative research in ESOL [Special issue]. TESOL Quar- terly, 29 (4).

Leonard, L. B. (1995). Phonological impairment. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhinney (Eds.), The handbook of child language (pp. 573-602). Oxford, UK: Black- well.

Lerner, G. (1993). Collectivities in action: Establishing the relevance of conjoined participation in con- versation. Text, 13, 213-245.

Lerner, G. (1996). On the "semi-permeable" character

of grammatical units in conversation: Conditional entry into the turn space of another speaker. In E. Ochs, E. A. Schegloff, & S. A. Thompson (Eds.), Interaction and grammar (pp. 238-276). Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Liddicoat, A. (1997). Interaction, social structure, and second language use: A response to Firth and Wagner. Modern Language Journal, 81, 313-317.

Locke, J. L. (1993). The child's path to spoken language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Locke, J. L. (1995). Development of the capacity for spoken language. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhinney (Eds.), The handbook of child language (pp. 278-302). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Long, M. L. (1997). Construct validity in SLA research: A response to Firth and Wagner. Modern Language Journal, 81, 318-323.

Malinowski, B. (1923). The problem of meaning in primitive languages. In C. A. Ogden & I. A. Richards (Eds.), The meaning of meaning: A study of the influence of language upon thought and of the sci- ence of symbolism (pp. 296-336). New York: Har- court, Brace & World.

Mandelbaum,J. (1987). Recipient-driven storytelling in con- versation. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Uni- versity of Texas, Austin.

Marchman, V., & Bates, E. (1994). Continuity in lexical and morphological development: A test of the critical mass hypothesis. Journal of Child Language, 21, 339-366.

McDermott, R. (1988). Inarticulateness. In D. Tannen (Ed.), Linguistics in context: Connecting observation and understanding. Advances in discourse processes (Vol. 29, pp. 37-68). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

McLaughlin, B. (1987). Theories of second-language learn- ing. London: Arnold.

McNeill, D. (Ed.). (2000). Language and gesture. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Mitchell, R., & Myles, F. (1998). Second language learning theories. London: Arnold.

Nelson, K. (1973). Structure and strategy in learning to talk [Monograph]. Monographs of the Society for Re- search in Child Development, 38.

Nelson, K. (Ed.). (1986). Event knowledge: Structure and function in development. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Newson, J. (1979). The growth of shared under- standings between infant and caregiver. In M. Bul- Iowa (Ed.), Before speech: The beginning of interper- sonal communication (pp. 207-222). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ninio, A., & Bruner, J. (1978). The achievements and antecedents of labelling. Journal of Child Language, 5, 1-15.

Ochs, E. (1988a). Culture and language development: Lan- guage acquisition and language socialization in a Sa- moan village. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ochs, E. (1988b, Fall). Introduction to sociolinguistics [classroom lecture]. Linguistics 510. University of Southern California Linguistics Department.

Ochs, E. (1990). Indexicality and socialization. In G.

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 21: Atkinson 2002

544 The Modern Language Journal 86 (2002)

Herdt, R. Shweder, & J. Stigler (Eds.), Cultural psychology: Essays on comparative human development (pp. 287-308). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ochs, E. (1992). Indexing gender. In A. Duranti & C. Goodwin (Eds.), Rethinking context: Language as an interactive phenomenon (pp. 335-358). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ochs, E. (1996). Linguistic resources for socializing hu- manity. In J. J. Gumperz & S. C. Levinson (Eds.), Rethinking linguistic relativity (pp. 407-437). Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ochs, E., Schegloff, E. A., & Thompson, S. A. (Eds.). (1996). Interaction and grammar Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press.

Ochs, E., Schieffelin, B. B., & Platt, M. L. (1979). Propo- sitions across utterances and speakers. In E. Ochs & B. B. Schieffelin (Eds.), Developmental pragmatics (pp. 251-268). New York: Academic Press.

Peirce, B. N. (1995). Social identity, investment, and language learning. TESOL Quarterly, 29, 9-31.

Pennycook, A. (1994). The cultural politics of English as an international language. London: Longman.

Pennycook, A. (1997). Cultural alternatives and auton- omy. In P. Benson & P. Voller (Eds.), Autonomy and independence in language learning (pp. 35-53). Lon- don: Longman.

Pennycook, A. (1998). English and the discourses of coloni- alism. London: Routledge.

Philips, S. U. (1983). The invisible culture: Communication in classroom and community on the Warm Springs In- dian Reservation. New York: Longman.

Phillipson, R. (1992). Linguistic imperialism. Oxford: Ox- ford University Press.

Plunkett, K. (1995). Connectionist approaches to lan- guage acquisition. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhin- ney (Eds.), The handbook of child language (pp. 36--72). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Plunkett, K, & Marchman, V. (1993). From rote learn- ing to system building: Acquiring verb morphol- ogy in children and connectionist nets. Cognition, 48, 21-69.

Poole, D. (1992). Language socialization in the second language classroom. Language Learning, 42, 593-616.

Porter, T. M. (1995). Trust in numbers: The pursuit of objectivity in science and public life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Quirk, R., Greenbaum, S., Leech, G., & Svartvik, J. (1985). A comprehensive grammar of the English lan- guage. London: Longman.

Ramanathan, V., & Atkinson, D. (1999). Ethnographic approaches and methods in L2 writing research: A critical guide and review. Applied Linguistics, 20, 44-70.

Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking: Cognitive development in social context. New York: Oxford Uni- versity Press.

Rogoff, B. (1998). Cognition as a collaborative process. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook of child

psychology, 5th ed., Vol 2: Cognition, perception, and language (pp. 679-744). New York: Wiley.

Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). On learn- ing the past tense of English verbs. InJ. L. McClel- land, D. E. Rumelhart, & the PDP Research Group (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition: Vol. 2: Psychological and biological models (pp. 216-271). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A., & Jefferson, G. (1974). A simplest systematics for the organization of turn- taking for conversation. Language, 50, 696-735.

Saffran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., & Newport, E. L. (1996). Statistical learning by 8-month old infants. Science, 274, 1926-1928.

Saville-Troike, M. (1988). Private speech: Evidence for second language learning strategies during the silent period. Journal of Child Language, 15, 567-590.

Schachter, J. (1993). SLA: Perceptions and possibilities. Second Language Research, 9, 173-187.

Schieffelin, B. B., & Ochs, E. (1986). Language sociali- zation. Annual Review of Anthropology, 15, 163-191.

Schmidt, R. W. (1983). Interaction, acculturation, and the acquisition of communicative competence. In N. Wolfson & E. Judd (Eds.), Sociolinguistics and language acquisition (pp. 137-174). Rowley, MA: Newbury House.

Schmidt, R. W., & Frota, S. N. (1986). Developing basic conversational ability in a second language: A case study of an adult learner of Portuguese. In D. Day (Ed.), Talking to learn: Conversation in second lan- guage acquisition (pp. 237-326). Rowley, MA: New- bury House.

Schumacher, E. F. (1997). This I believe, and other essays. Foxhole, UK: Green Books.

Scollon, R. (1976). Conversations with a one year old. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawai'i Press.

Scribner, S., & Cole, M. (1981). The psychology of literacy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Seidenberg, M. S. (1996). Language acquisition and use: Learning and applying probabilistic con- straints. Science, 275, 1599-1603.

Shore, B. (1996). Culture in mind: Cognition, culture, and theproblem of meaning. New York: Oxford University Press.

Smith, F. (1988).Joining the literacy club: Further essays into education. Portsmouth, NH: Heinemann.

Snow, C. E. (1995). Issues in the study of input: Finetun- ing, universality, individual and developmental differences, and necessary causes. In P. Fletcher & B. MacWhinney (Eds.), The handbook of child lan- guage (pp. 180-193). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Stemberger, J. (1992). A connectionist view of child phonology: Phonological processing without phonological processes. In C. Ferguson, L. Menn, & C. Stoel-Gammon (Eds.), Phonological develop- ment: Models, research, implications (pp. 165-189). Timonium, MD: York Press.

Strauss, C., & Quinn, N. (1997). A cognitive theory of

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 22: Atkinson 2002

Dwight Atkinson 545

cultural meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- sity Press.

Street, B. (1984). Literacy in theory and practice. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Street, B. (Ed.). (1993). Cross-cultural approaches to liter- acy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Stubbs, M. (1996). Text and corpus analysis. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Tannen, D. (1986). That's not what I meant: How conversa- tional style makes or breaks your relationships with oth- ers. New York: Ballantine.

Tannen, D. (Ed.). (1993). Gender and conversational inter- action. New York: Oxford University Press.

Tannen, D., & Saville-Troike, M. (Eds.). (1985). Perspec- tives on silence. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Traweek, S. (1988). Beamtimes and lifetimes: The world of high energy physicists. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge, MA: Har- vard University Press.

Vygostky, L. S. (1981). The genesis of higher mental fuctions. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed. & Trans.), The con-

cept of activity in Soviet psychology (pp. 144-188). Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.

Wenger, E. (1998). Communities of practice: Learning, meaning, and identity. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press.

Wertsch, J. V. (Ed.). (1985). Culture, communication and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press.

Wertsch, J. V. (1998). Mind as action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wertsch, J. V., & Stone, C. A. (1985). The concept of internalization in Vygotsky's account of the gene- sis of higher mental functions. InJ. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication and cognition: Vygotskian per- spectives (pp. 162-179). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Zukow-Goldring, P., & Ferko, K R. (1994). An ecologi- cal approach to the emergence of the lexicon: Socializing attention. In V.John-Steiner, C. P. Pan- ofsky, & L. W. Smith (Eds.), Sociocultural approaches to language and literacy: An interactionist perspective (pp. 170-190). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Modern Language Association Publication Prizes: Biennial Competitions 2003

The MLA announces deadlines for submissions for its 2003 Biennial Prizes Competitions. For more information contact the Office of Special Projects: (646) 576-5141; [email protected].

MLA Prize for a Distinguished Scholarly Edition: For single or multiple volumes. At least one volume must have been published in 2001 or 2002. 1 May 2003

Morton N. Cohen Award for a Distinguished Edition of Letters. For single or multiple volumes; at least one volume published in 2001 or 2002. 1 May 2003

Aldo and Jeanne Scaglione Prize for Studies in Slavic Languages and Literatures: For a book on the linguistics or literatures of the Slavic Languages. 1 May 2003.

Aldo and Jeanne Scaglione Prize for a Translation of a Scholarly Study of Literature: For a translation into English of a book-length work of literary history, criticism, theory, or philology. 1 May 2003.

Lois Roth Award for a Translation of a Work of Literature: For a translation into English of a book- length literary work. 1 April 2003.

Aldo and Jeanne Scaglione Prize for Italian Studies: For a work on any phase of Italian literature or culture or comparative literature involving Italian. 1 May 2003.

This content downloaded from 152.92.111.9 on Wed, 30 Oct 2013 13:50:28 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions