988s

252
A COMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF NALYSIS OF NALYSIS OF NALYSIS OF THE THE THE THE COSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL DOCTRINES OCTRINES OCTRINES OCTRINES OF OF OF OF ERIUGENA AND RIUGENA AND RIUGENA AND RIUGENA AND IBN BN BN BN ‘A ‘A ‘A ‘ARABI RABI RABI RABI> A THESIS HESIS HESIS HESIS SUBMITTE UBMITTE UBMITTE UBMITTED TO THE TO THE TO THE TO THE UNIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF PUNJAB IN UNJAB IN UNJAB IN UNJAB IN THE HE HE HE FULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF REQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF EGREE OF EGREE OF EGREE OF DOCTOR OF OCTOR OF OCTOR OF OCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY HILOSOPHY HILOSOPHY HILOSOPHY BY BY BY BY QAISER SHAHZAD QAISER SHAHZAD QAISER SHAHZAD QAISER SHAHZAD DEPARTMENT O DEPARTMENT O DEPARTMENT O DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY F PHILOSOPHY F PHILOSOPHY F PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY NIVERSITY NIVERSITY NIVERSITY OF THE OF THE OF THE OF THE PUNJAB UNJAB UNJAB UNJAB, LAHORE AHORE AHORE AHORE- PAKISTAN AKISTAN AKISTAN AKISTAN APRIL PRIL PRIL PRIL-2010 2010 2010 2010

Upload: lillian-barrett

Post on 26-Oct-2015

39 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Shahzad Eriugena & Ibn Arabi

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 988S

AAAA CCCCOMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE OMPARATIVE AAAANALYSIS OFNALYSIS OFNALYSIS OFNALYSIS OF THE THE THE THE CCCCOSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL OSMOLOGICAL DDDDOCTRINES OCTRINES OCTRINES OCTRINES OFOFOFOF

EEEERIUGENA ANDRIUGENA ANDRIUGENA ANDRIUGENA AND IIIIBN BN BN BN ‘A‘A‘A‘ARABIRABIRABIRABI >> >>

AAAA TTTTHESIS HESIS HESIS HESIS SSSSUBMITTEUBMITTEUBMITTEUBMITTEDDDD TO THE TO THE TO THE TO THE UUUUNIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF NIVERSITY OF PPPPUNJAB IN UNJAB IN UNJAB IN UNJAB IN TTTTHE HE HE HE FFFFULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF ULFILLMENT OF RRRREQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE EQUIREMENTS FOR THE DDDDEGREE OF EGREE OF EGREE OF EGREE OF

DDDDOCTOR OF OCTOR OF OCTOR OF OCTOR OF PPPPHILOSOPHYHILOSOPHYHILOSOPHYHILOSOPHY

BYBYBYBY

QAISER SHAHZADQAISER SHAHZADQAISER SHAHZADQAISER SHAHZAD

DEPARTMENT ODEPARTMENT ODEPARTMENT ODEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHYF PHILOSOPHYF PHILOSOPHYF PHILOSOPHY UUUUNIVERSITY NIVERSITY NIVERSITY NIVERSITY OF THE OF THE OF THE OF THE PPPPUNJABUNJABUNJABUNJAB,,,,

LLLLAHOREAHOREAHOREAHORE---- PPPPAKISTANAKISTANAKISTANAKISTAN AAAAPRILPRILPRILPRIL----2010201020102010

Page 2: 988S

ii

CertificateCertificateCertificateCertificate

This is to certify that the research work described in this thesis is the original work of

the author and has been carried out under my direct supervision. I have personally gone

through all the data/results/materials reported in the manuscript and certify their

correctness/authenticity. I further certify that the material included in this thesis has not

been used in part or in full in a manuscript already submitted or in the process of

submission in partial complete fulfillment of the award of another degree from any other

institution. I also certify that the thesis has been prepared under my supervision

according to the prescribed format and I endorse its evaluation for the award of PhD

degree through the official procedures of the University.

SignatureSignatureSignatureSignature_________________

NameNameNameName: Prof. Dr. Sajid Ali

DesignationDesignationDesignationDesignation: Chairman,

Department of Philosophy

University of the Punjab

Lahore

Page 3: 988S

iii

ContentsContentsContentsContents

Abstract viii

Acknowledgements x

Abbreviations xi

List of Tables and Figures xii

A Note on Sources xiii

ONE ONE ONE ONE

IntroductionIntroductionIntroductionIntroduction

1111

1.1 Preliminary

1.2 Review of Literature

1.3 Methodological Considerations

1.3.1 The Method of Comparison

1.3.2 Critique of Socio-Historical Method

1.4 Theoretical Framework

1.4.1 Pre-modern- modern Break

1.4.2 Metaphysics-Religion Dichotomy

1.4.3 Reason- Intellect

TWO TWO TWO TWO

The Ontological FoundationsThe Ontological FoundationsThe Ontological FoundationsThe Ontological Foundations

17171717

2.1 Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on Totality

2.1.1 Eriugena’s Concept of Totality

2.1.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Concept of Totality

2.2 Ontology-Intelligibility Connection and Perspectival Ontology in Eriugena

2.3 Ontology-Intelligibility Connection and Perspectival Ontology in Ibn ‘Arabi>

2.3.1 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ontology and Intelligibility

2.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Perspectival Ontology

Page 4: 988S

iv

THREE THREE THREE THREE

Metacosm Metacosm Metacosm Metacosm ––––I: GodI: GodI: GodI: God

38383838

3.1 Defining God

3.1.1 Eriugena on the Definition of “God.”

3.1.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on the Definition of “God.”

3.2 Divine Self-Creation

3.2.1 Eriugena’s Standpoint

3.2.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Standpoint

3.3 Divine Knowability

3.3.1 Eriugena on Divine Knowability

3.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Divine Knowability

3.4 Divine Unity and Trinity

3.4.1 Eriugena on Trinity

3.4.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Unity, Trinity and Multiplicity

3.5 Talking About God

3.5.1 Eriugena’s Affirmative, Negative and Superlative Theologies

3.5.2 Incomparability, Similarity and their Synthesis in Ibn ‘Arabi>

3.6 Divine Nothingness

3.6.1 Nihil as a Divine Name in Eriugena

3.6.2 God and Nothingness according to Ibn ‘Arabi>

3.7 Divine Darkness

3.7.1 Eriugena on Divine Self-Knowledge

3.7.1 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Divine Self-Knowledge

FOURFOURFOURFOUR

MetacosmMetacosmMetacosmMetacosm----II: The Primordial CausesII: The Primordial CausesII: The Primordial CausesII: The Primordial Causes

73737373

4.1 The Nature of Primordial Causes and their Functions in Eriugenian Cosmology

4.1.1 The Scriptural Basis of Primordial Causes

4.1.2 Causes as the Origin of Intelligible and Sensible Creatures

4.1.3 Primordial Causes and Materia Prima

4.1.4 Immutable Perfection of the Causes

4.1.5 Questions of Knowability

Page 5: 988S

v

4.1.6 Primordial Causes and Evil

4.1.7 Timeless Creation of Primordial Causes

4.1.8 No Nature between God and Primordial Causes

4.1.9 Hierarchy of Primordial Causes

4.1.10 Infinity of Primordial Causes

4.1.11 Simplicity and Unity of Causes

4.1.12 Priority of Goodness and Objectivity of Hierarchy

4.2 Fixed entities in Comparison with Primordial Causes

4.2.1 Scriptural Foundation of the Concept

4.2.2 Ontological Status

4.2.3 Fixed Entities and Material Prima

4.2.4 Entities and Knowledge

4.2.5 Entities Created or Eternal?

4.2.6 Order and Hierarchy in Entities

4.2.7 Intermediate Status of Entities

4.2.8 Essence, Names and Entities

4.2.9 The Highest Fixed Entity

4.2.10 Unity and Multiplicity

4.2.11 Entities and the Word

4.2.12 Infinity of Entities

4.2.13 Fixed Entities and Evil

FIVEFIVEFIVEFIVE

MacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosm----I: Participation and I: Participation and I: Participation and I: Participation and DivineDivineDivineDivine RootsRootsRootsRoots

120120120120

5.1 Eriugena on “Participation”

5.1.1 Participation: History and Context

5.1.2 Participation and All that is (omne quod est)

5.1.3 Participation: Literal and Metaphorical Explications

5.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on the “Divine Roots.”

5.2.1 Divine Roots and omne quod est

5.2.2 Divine Roots and “Participation” Literally Understood

5.2.3 Divine Roots and Metaphors of Participation

5.3 God and Categoriae Decem

Page 6: 988S

vi

5.3.1 Eriugena on God and Categories

5.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on God and Categories

SIX SIX SIX SIX

MacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosm----II: Theophany and II: Theophany and II: Theophany and II: Theophany and alalalal----TajalliTajalliTajalliTajalli >> >>

151151151151

6.1 Eriugena on Theophany

6.1.1 Etymology and Importance of the Concept

6.1.2 Dionysian Influences: Form-assuming, Illumination and Elitism

6.1.3 Epistemological Theophany and Unknowability

6.1.4 Ontological Theophany and Transcendence

6.1.5 Functions of “Theophany” in Eriugena’s Thought

6.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on al-Tajalli>

6.2.1 Centrality of the Concept

6.2.2 Etymology and the Qur’a>nic usage of the term

6.2.3 Al-Tajalli>: Ontological and Epistemological

6.2.4 Form-Assuming, Illumination and Elitism

6.2.5 Al-Tajalli> and Divine Transcendence

SEVENSEVENSEVENSEVEN

Microcosm: Man, GMicrocosm: Man, GMicrocosm: Man, GMicrocosm: Man, God and Nature od and Nature od and Nature od and Nature

173173173173

7.1 Containment: Man and Nature in Eriugena

7.1.1 Theory of Universal Human Containment

7.1.2 Containment and Human Self-Knowledge

7.1.3 Containment in the Light of Holy Scripture

7.1.4 Containment and Six Days of Creation

7.1.5 Unity and Trinity: Divine and Human

7.2 Man as Microcosm in Ibn ‘Arabi>

7.2.1 The Scriptural Basis

7.2.2 How is Man a Microcosm?

7.2.3 Man as Intermediary

7.2.4 Man: the Final Creature

7.2.5 Microcosm: Problems of Labeling

Page 7: 988S

vii

7.3 Deiformity: God and Man in Eriugena

7.3.1 Preliminary: Scriptural Basis

7.3.2 Body and the Divine Image

7.3.3 Which Man was Created upon Divine Image?

7.3.4 Why and How Man was Created upon Divine Image?

7.3.5 The Metaphysical Principle of Deiformity

7.4 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Al-S}u>rah al-Ila>hiyyah

7.4.1 Islamic Foundations of the Concept in Ibn ‘Arabi>

7.4.2 The Meaning of Deiformity

7.4.3 Does the Divine Image Extend to the whole of Humanity?

7.4.4 The Cosmic Deiformity

7.4.5 Human Body and Deiformity

7.4.6 The Ethical Dimensions of Deiformity

7.4.7 Why Deiformity: Metaphysical Explanations

EIGHTEIGHTEIGHTEIGHT

Conclusion: Summary, Interpretation and Implications 212

Works Cited 234

Appendix: Published Research Work 241

Page 8: 988S

AbstractAbstractAbstractAbstract

In this dissertation we propose to undertake a comparative analysis of the cosmological

doctrines of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> in order to show that in spite of belonging to

different religious, historical and geographical contexts, their views show remarkable

similarities on the concept of God, nature and man and their correlation. Their

conceptions of totality and its division are similar, while Ibn ‘Arabi>’s picture is more

comprehensive in view of his accommodating absolute not-being. Both connect

ontology with intelligibility and present perspectival ontologies. Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> alike extend the term “God” to include “theophanies.” They are agreed on Divine

unknowability, self-creation and they both synthesize negative and affirmative

theologies. However, in view of their different conceptions of “knowledge” they

disagree on the possibility of Divine Self-knowledge. Eriugena's “primordial causes”

which mediate God and creation, are shown to be functionally similar to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

“fixed entities” and the ontological status of both is similar. However, the former are

contained within the Logos while the latter are not contained within the Perfect Man.

We argue that the way Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> relate the world to God is similar by

showing resonance between Eriugena’s notion of “participation” and the doctrine of

“Divine roots” we reconstruct from scattered passages of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s magnum opus.

We also show that Eriugena’s understanding of “theophany” is completely in line with

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s view of the nature of al-tajalli>. Our exposition of the Divine roots theory

also includes a discussion of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s views on the relationship between God and ten

categories which he, unlike, Eriugena, connects ontologically to the Divine nature.

Finally, we show how, on the one hand, Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> alike relate man to God

Page 9: 988S

ix

via the notion of imago dei, on the other, they relate man to the created nature by

viewing nature to be contained by man. It is shown that Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> agree

not only on broader outlines but in certain important details as well, for instance, the

way they understand the meaning of human deiformity is same. On the methodological

side, the most prominent feature that is shared by these two philosophers is their

keenness to relate philosophical doctrines and notions to their respective Scriptures. We

observe, however, that whereas Eriugena’s interpretation of the Bible seems in most of

the cases to be allegorical and arbitrary, when Ibn ‘Arabi> interprets the Qur’a>n he is

extremely careful regarding its letter and offers his creative interpretation more often

than not within the interpretational space allowed by the text itself. Another

methodological insight that is common to both is that instead of aligning themselves

with extreme positions on most of the important questions, they usually prefer midway

house standpoints which enable us to see the pros and cons of all options. We conclude

by making a case for the importance and practical relevance of the results of our

comparative analysis. We argue that by considering the world to be a theophany and

contained within man who is created upon Divine image Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> give

us the conceptual keys to reconstruct a worldview that is based on perfect harmony

between God, man and created nature and it is this view that is really needed to come to

terms with the environmental crisis our world is facing. Moreover, their tendency to

take middle positions and indeed the way they situate the world between absolute

goodness and absolute evil offers us a cosmology of tolerance. This cosmology requires

that instead of having recourse to “either/or” logic of the sword we see everything as

consisting of elements of goodness and imperfection.

Page 10: 988S

x

AcknowlAcknowlAcknowlAcknowledgmentsedgmentsedgmentsedgments

I am grateful first of all to my supervisor Dr. Sajid Ali for all his encouragement,

guidance and help. I would like to thank my mentor Dr. Zafar Ishaq Ansari, Director

Islamic Research Institute International Islamic University, for making it possible for

me to work on this dissertation by granting me study leave and supporting me in every

manner. I am grateful to my friend Syed Rizwan Zamir for making me think about the

subject of present dissertation in pragmatic terms. Finally, I would like to express my

gratitude to all those who helped me in using the Bodleian Library Oxford and John

Rylands Library University of Manchester in September 2005.

Page 11: 988S

xi

AbbreviationsAbbreviationsAbbreviationsAbbreviations

Most commonly used works are abbreviated as under.Most commonly used works are abbreviated as under.Most commonly used works are abbreviated as under.Most commonly used works are abbreviated as under.

DDNDDNDDNDDN Eriugena: De Diuisione Naturae

HomHomHomHom. Eriugena: Homilia in prologum Evangelii Secundum Joannem

PraedPraedPraedPraed. Eriugena: De Divina Praedestinatione

Fut.Fut.Fut.Fut. Ibn ‘Arabi>: Al-Futu>h}a>t al-Makkiyah

FusFusFusFus. Ibn ‘Arabi>: Fus}u>s} al-H}ikam

Insha>’Insha>’Insha>’Insha>’ Ibn ‘Arabi>: Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir

SPKSPKSPKSPK William C. Chittick: Sufi Path of Knowledge

SDGSDGSDGSDG William C. Chittick: Self Disclosure of God

RingstonesRingstonesRingstonesRingstones Caner Dagli: Ringstones of Wisdom

JMIASJMIASJMIASJMIAS Journal of the Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> Society, Oxford

NoteNoteNoteNotessss: : : :

1. Except for the last title abbreviated here, we have cited all other sources within within within within

the text in the text in the text in the text in parenthesesparenthesesparenthesesparentheses. . . . The footnotes refer only to secondary material or consist

of comments.

2. The verses from the Holy Qur’a>n are cited within parentheses, number of Su>rah

followed by verse number. For example ((((2:132:132:132:13)))) means the second su>rah and the

thirteenth verse.

Page 12: 988S

xii

List of Tables and FiguresList of Tables and FiguresList of Tables and FiguresList of Tables and Figures 1. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Division of Totality: Synthesis I ……………………… Page 23

2. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Division of Totality: Synthesis II ……………………... Page 23

3. Eriugena on Knowing God from Creatures …………………………. Page 45

4. Principle and Manifestations of Primordial Causes in hierarchy …… Page 86

5. Fixed Entities in Hierarchy ………………………………………….. Page 110

6. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s circle of Categoriae Decem ……………………………. Page 141

7. Divine Roots of Categoriae Decem …………………………………. Page 143

Page 13: 988S

xiii

A Note on SourcesA Note on SourcesA Note on SourcesA Note on Sources

Editions Editions Editions Editions of the primary sources used. of the primary sources used. of the primary sources used. of the primary sources used.

For the Latin text and English translation of the first three books of Eriugena's De

Diuisione Naturae we use I.P Sheldon-William’s parallel Latin-English edition (Dublin:

Institute of Advanced Studies, 1968, 1970, 1981). For the necessary references to Latin

text of fourth and fifth books we refer to the text in volume 121 of J.P Migne’s

Patrologia Latina (CD- ROM). For the English translation of these two books we refer

to the complete translation by J O’Meara Periphyseon (Dumbarton Oaks/Montreal:

Bellarmin, 1987).

For Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Al-Futu>h}a>t al-Makkiyah we use the undated Dār S}ādir, Beirut Edition.

TranslationTranslationTranslationTranslationssss

We do not undertake to translate passages from this work until we do not find them

already translated by William Chittick or in rare occasions when we find justification to

differ from his translation.

Page 14: 988S

OneOneOneOne

IntroIntroIntroIntroductionductionductionduction 1.11.11.11.1 PreliminaryPreliminaryPreliminaryPreliminary

This is a comparative analysis of textual parallels from John Scottus Eriugena (810-

870)1, the Irish philosopher and translator of the works of Greek authorities, and the

great Muslim mystic-philosopher Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> (1165-1240) as far as their

cosmological doctrines are concerned. However concern with “cosmological doctrines”

does not mean that we are going to be exclusively focussed on that part of Eriugena’s

work which is related to nature and origin of the physical universe. It is not possible to

compartmentalize the work of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> into theology, cosmology and

anthropology. These two authors consider cosmos as a totality of theophanies, the

greatest of which is human being. Instead of trying to slice some cosmological part from

the work of Eriugena we focus on his De Diuisione Naturae as a whole and then consider

its textual parallels in the writings of Ibn ‘Arabi>, especially but not exclusively, in his

major work al-Futu>h}a>t al-Makkiyah. Since the world is prefigured in the Divine, man is

created upon Divine image and the world is contained within human nature it does not

matter whether we call Eriugena’s system theology, cosmology or anthropology. Thus

after comparative study of ontological foundations in the second chapter we analyze the

nature of God and primordial causes as metacosm, of the created world as macrocosm

1In addition to being the author of De Praedestinatione, De Diuisione Naturae and Homily Eriugena is the

translator of Ambigua of St. Maximus the Confessor (d. 662), De Hominis Opificio of St. Gregory of

Nyssa (d. post 394) and of works of Pseudo-Dionysius. He also wrote commentaries on St. John’s Gospel,

Consolatio Philosophiae of Boethius (d. 524/5) and on De Coelesti Hierarchia by Ps. Dionysius.

Page 15: 988S

2

and the relation of man as imago dei to God and as microcosm to nature in the seven

chapters that follow. A summary is presented in the final chapter as well as some points

related to interpretation and significance.

1.21.21.21.2 Review of LiteratureReview of LiteratureReview of LiteratureReview of Literature

Studies of the thought of both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> abound in many languages of the

world. At least two major organizations are devoted to the promotion of the study of

these two thinkers, Society for the Promotion of Eriugenian Studies (SPES) and

Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> Society (MIAS) which is also publishing a Journal. Countless

conferences have been organized on aspects of their thought. In case of Eriugena so

much work has been accomplished that numerous surveys of studies can be found. Mary

Brennan has produced a survey of 523 writings from 1930 to 19872 which presents

summaries of books and articles in various European languages by classifying them into

writings of Eriugena’s life, works and thought including his sources doctrine and

influence. Before this work Brennan had already published a bibliography of works in

the field of Eriugenian studies from 1800 to 1975.3 Brennan’s work has been

complemented by Gerd van Reel who has published bibliographical surveys of

publications ranging from 1987-19954 and from 1995-2000.5 Although many recent

studies of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought contain detailed bibliographies, it seems that apart from

2 A Guide to Eriugenian Studies: A Survey of Publications 1930-1987 (Fribourg: Editions du Cerf, 1989)

3 “Bibliography of Publications in the Field of Eriugenian Studies” in Studi Medievali, XVIII (1977), 401-

407. 4 “A Bibliographical Survey of Eriugenian Studies 1987-1995,” in Iohannes Scottus Eriugena: the Bible

and Hermeneutics (Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1996), 367-400. 5 “Eriugenian Studies 1995-2000” in History and Eschatology in John Scottus Eriugena and His Time

(Leuven: Leuven University Press, 2002), 611-636.

Page 16: 988S

3

Martin Notcutt’s 1985 handlist of printed materials6 no full scale survey of publications

in the field of Ibn ‘Arabi> studies has been made. This is not to deny that many major

studies do contain selected bibliographies annexed to them.

Since we are concerned in the present work with the comparison of Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> we are not supposed to enumerate or discuss studies that deal with either of

them. We would like, however, to make one exception by mentioning and briefly

discussing one particular study of the thought of Eriugena in view firstly of our

numerous references to it and of our disagreement with it at certain important points of

reading and interpreting Eriugena. This is Dermot Moran’s book The Philosophy of John

Scottus Eriugena: A Study of Idealism in the Middle Ages.7 The major themes that are

discussed in this book range from Eriugena’s sources, his understanding of dialectic, and

his position on meaning of nature, human knowledge and not-being. Moran interprets

Eriugena’s philosophy as a meontology (from the Greek words me on i.e. not-being)

rather than ontology, arguing that the concept of not-being is more central and

characteristic of Eriugena than “being.” Against this Deirdre Carabine has observed that

this reading of Eriugena would be anachronistic since the primacy of being was not

established until St. Thomas Aquinas in the thirteenth century.8 Some nineteenth

century German commentators saw Eriugena as a predecessor of the idealism that ruled

the German academia at that time.9 Moran agrees with these interpretations of Eriugena

6 “Ibn ‘Arabi: A Handlist of Printed Materials: Part II,” in JMIAS, IV (1985), 65-74.

7 Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. Henceforth abbreviated as “The Philosophy.”

8 See Carabine, John Scottus Eriugena, (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), 41. 9 For example G.B. Jäche, Der Pantheismus (Berlin: Reimer, 1828), Band II: 128 and J Huber Johannes

Scotus Eirgena (Munich, 1861, repr., Hildesheim: Olms, 1960), xi. Both these works are discussed by

Werner Beierwaltes, “The Revaluation of John Scottus Eriugena in German Idealism,” in Dominic J.

O’Meara, ed., The Mind of Eriugena: Papers of a Dublin Colloquium, 14-18 July 1970 (Dublin: Irish

University Press, 1973), 192-193.

Page 17: 988S

4

in the main and throughout his work one finds him interpreting Eriugena as an idealist.

However, Moran claims that he has tried also to look at Eriugena in the historical

context in which the latter lived and wrote specially the intellectual resources that were

available to him and were assimilated by him. One of the reasons Moran mentions for

making an idealist out of Eriugena is that he dissolves all hierarchy into the self-

expression of subjectivity10 and that the four divisions “receive form only by being

contemplated.”11 So Eriugena is an idealist because he subjectivises. Ironically, Hegel’s

follower Baur criticized Eriugena as not being an idealist precisely because he

subjectivised notions like creation, resurrection and incarnation etc.12 It is strange that

one and same characteristic is being interpreted by two scholars as implying contrary

philosophical affiliation. Moran writes about Eriugena’s four divisions of Nature that

they receive form only by being contemplated. This is the true nature of the four

divisions of nature. They are not substances or realities but are manifestations which

appear to the perceiving mind. The word “but” indicates that the interpretation is

reductionist. Is there any justification to think that “manifestation” cannot be “reality”?

The interpreter is in fact trying to read “idealism” into a text that does not necessarily

imply it. This is one of the perils of modernist approaches to pre-modern thought that

concepts like manifestation are subjectivised and relativised.13 Inclining more to the

10 Moran, The Philosophy, 262. 11 Ibid. 266. 12 F. Ch. Baur Die Christliche Lehre van der Versöhnung (Tübingen, 1838), 132-134, quoted in

Beiewaltes, Revaluation, 196. 13 Similar reductionism is apparent in John Marenbon’s statement in connection with Eriugena’s theory of

return: “And the return to God becomes neither a moment in the metaphysical analysis of nature, nor the

mystical goal of the sage but rather – in a way which reflects the thought of Gregory of Nyssa-a physical

process, involving all things and bringing them, at the end of time, back to God.” John Marenbon, Early

Medieval Philosophy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983) 64. Emphasis added.

Page 18: 988S

5

opinion of Miles Burnyeat that there is no possibility of idealism in ancient philosophy14

we argue in our dissertation that Eriugena cannot straightforwardly be labeled as an

Idealist since his position is a complex one with many indications of realist tendencies.

Another point where we disagree with Moran’s reading of Eriugena is the former’s

claim that the modes of distinguishing being from not-being given by Eriugena at the

beginning of his DDN are not central to the work.

Do we find any comparative studies of the thought of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>?

The only Muslim philosopher to whom Eriugena has been compared is Al-Kindi> (d.

873c.) Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought has been studied in comparison with that of Albertus

Magnus (d. 1280),15 St. Thomas Aquinas (d. 1274),16 Meister Eckhart (d. 1328c.),17

Nicholas of Cusa (d. 1464),18 St. John of the Cross (d. 1591)19 and Derrida (d. 2004),20

while Peter Coates has produced a study of Ibn ‘Arabi> in context of modern Western

thought titled Ibn ‘Arabi and Modern Thought.21 To the extent of our information no

comparative study of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> has been undertaken. The only work that

might be presented as an exception to this statement is Michael Sells’ The Mystical 14 Miles Burnyeat, “Idealism in Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,” in

Idealism: Past and Present, ed., G. Vassey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 19-50. 15 See Adam Dupré, “Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> and St. Albertus Magnus of Cologne,” in JMIAS, I (1982),

12-26. 16 T.L. Suttor, “Thomas of Aquino and Ibn al-‘Arabi>,” Hamdard Islamicus, VI (1983). 17 Reza Shah Kazemi, Paths to Transcendence: According to Shankara, Ibn ‘Arabi> and Meister Eckhart

(Bloomington: World Wisdom Books, 2006). 18 A. V. Smirnov, “Nicholas of Cusa and Ibn ‘Arabi>: Two Philosophies of Mysticism,” in Philosophy East

and West, XLIII (1993) 65-85. 19 Luce López-Baralt, “Saint John of the Cross and Ibn ‘Arabi>: The Heart or Qalb as the Translucid and

Ever-Changing Mirror of God,” JMIAS, XXVIII (2000), 57-90. 20 Ian Almond, Sufism and Deconstruction: A Comparative Study of Derrida and Ibn ‘Arabi>, (London:

Routledge, 2004). 21 Peter Coates, Ibn ‘Arabi and Modern Thought: The History of Taking Metaphysics Seriously. (Oxford:

Anqa Publishing, 2002).

Page 19: 988S

6

Languages of Unsaying.22 This fascinating work is a study of apophasis or negative

theology “as cross-cultural mode of discourse, emerging out of a variety of religious and

cultural traditions and sharing key semantic features.”23 In addition to Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> this work is based also on readings of Plotinus (270c.), Marguerite Porete (d.

1310) and Meister Eckhart. Rather than blocking the way of further inquiry regarding

comparison of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> this work opens the way for it and is an

indication of the feasibility of such a project. Although this work provides important

insights for the task before us, its focus is not the overall cosmological doctrines of

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> and it is not as such a comparative analysis of these two

writers. Our proposed research differs from the work of Sells in being focused only on

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> and in not being exclusively concerned with the issue of

negative theology. Although we deal with this issue, our major concern is to see where

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> agree or disagree in their views regarding the nature of God,

man and universe and the relation between these three.

1.31.31.31.3 Methodological ConsiderationsMethodological ConsiderationsMethodological ConsiderationsMethodological Considerations

1.3.11.3.11.3.11.3.1 The Method of Comparison The Method of Comparison The Method of Comparison The Method of Comparison

In the wake of postmodernism “comparison” as a scholarly method has come under

attack. In an important essay Jonathan Z. Smith isolated four basic models of

comparison, ethnographic, encyclopedic, morphological and evolutionary.24 He attempts

22 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). 23

Ibid. 206. 24 The ethnographic approach is the one in which comparison functions primarily as a means of

overcoming strangeness.” The encyclopedic approach presents “topical arrangement of cross-cultural

material” without providing any clue as to how comparison might be undertaken. The morphological

approach “allows the arrangement of individual items in a hierarchical series of increased complexity and

organization.” The evolutionary approach is the one “which factors in the dynamics of change and

Page 20: 988S

7

to show that the first two are entirely inadequate, no instance of satisfactory application

of the fourth exists while the third model inspite of being better than others is not

attractive in view of the Romantic, Neoplatonic Idealism of its presuppositions. Smith

concludes that the only option appears to be no option at all.25 Smith thinks that

comparison, like magic, is a “confusion of a subjective relationship with an objective

one.”26 According to him, from a déjà vu feeling that what the scholar is reading he has

come across already, he goes on to assert that “similarity and contiguity have causal

effects.” In the words of Simth, this is a process of working from psychological

association to a historical one.27 In the task of comparative analysis that we have set

befor us, we admit the presence of déjà vu feeling, but Smith’s objection does not apply

to our project since we are not concerned with asserting any objective association

between the ideas of two thinkers whom we are going to compare so we are not drawing

any conclusions of historical nature from a subjective feeling. This subjective feeling

provided simply a motivation for further study and investigation of the matter. The

purpose of our comparative analysis is pragmatic rather than exclusively theoretical. It

consists in an attempt to find out certain concepts that are shown to be useful to reassert

a worlview based on harmony between God, man and nature.

Barbara A. Holdrege has highlighted three objections to the method of

comparison in an essay written in response to Smith’s aforementioned work and has

persistence over time in response to adaptation to a given environment.” Jonathan Z. Smith “In

Comparison a Magic Dwells,” in A Magic Still Dwells: Comparative Religion in the Post-modern Age,

eds. Kimberley C. Patton and Benjamin C. Ray (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000), 27-29. 25 See ibid. 26

Ibid. 25>. 27

Ibid. 26.

Page 21: 988S

8

described how her own method has been able to evade those objections.28 The first

objection is that comparison pays insufficient attention to differences. We intend the

expression “comparative analysis” in the title of our dissertation to be understood as an

exercise which reveals differences as well as similarities. In order to avoid the first

objection we pay attention to differences between the thought of Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> at every step, attempting to explain them and reconcile them with reference to

underlying unity wherever such unity can be found.Where such unity cannot be

objectively found we do not attempt to invent artificial unities between the two

thinkers. Thus at one point within our comparative analysis we disagree with a reading

of Eriugena put forward by one of the most prominent contemporary Eriugena scholars

although her interpretation would have brought Eriugenian position closer to that of Ibn

‘Arabi> on an issue of central importance.29 We do not discard non-reducible gaps

between them, rather we highlight them within the chapters and also when we

summarize the results of the whole project at the end.

The second objection asserts that the comparative method neglects the

diachronic dimension and the third points out that this method pays insufficient

attention to context. In order to avoid these imperfections the first of three phases of

Barbara’s own methodology consisted in “analyzing each network of symbols

separately, within the context of its respective tradition.”30 In conducting comparative

analysis here we have followed this suggestion of Barbara Holdrege. Thus we do not

juxtapose the positions of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> but deal with them separately,

28

See “What’s beyond the Post? Comparative Analysis as Critical Method” in A Magic Still Dwells, 77-83. 29

See 6.1.5 where we discuss the function of “theophany” in relation to Eriugenian synthesis of negative

and affirmative theologies. 30

“What’s beyond the Post? 79.

Page 22: 988S

9

placing each within his own context. For instance while comparing primordial causes

and fixed entities we first discuss the historical background, meaning and usage of the

former in Eriugena by connecting them to his sources which have been established

either on the basis of internal textual evidence (e.g. Eriugena’s citing some of the Greek

fathers) or on the basis of independent historical research. We then proceed to analyze

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s notion within the context of the intellectual tradition in which he worked.

However the results of comparison are not given separately in independent sections

rather they are mentioned after or alongwith our discussion of Ibn ‘Arabi>. While

explaining certain differences we also refer to the difference of contexts to which our

two philosophers belonged.

Having dicussed certain points regarding the particular method of comparison

we are employing, we proceed now to describe some of our theoretical presuppositions

and demonstrate how they relate to comparative analysis of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>.

1.3.21.3.21.3.21.3.2 Critique of SocioCritique of SocioCritique of SocioCritique of Socio----Historical MethodHistorical MethodHistorical MethodHistorical Method

In the work at hand we do not apply the historical method of comparative study which

focuses on finding out origins of ideas, something that was criticized by Smith as

confusing subjective connections with objective ones. Nor do we attempt to reduce the

meaning and worth of every intellectual phenomenon to the social context in which it is

presented. In spite of the popularity of these methods nowadays, we think that there are

serious problems with them. Instead of the socio-historical method we have chosen the

analytical method based on the careful study of textual parallels in the writings of

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabī. The comparative philosophical studies undertaken under spell

of the historical method, especially by the European or American writers, more often

than not contain what René Guenon calls “the classical prejudice” namely, the tendency

Page 23: 988S

10

on the part of occidental scholars to “find all over the world pure and simple equivalent

modes of thought that are peculiar to themselves.”31 This of course does not mean that

Orientals can legitimately find all over the world equivalent modes of thought that are

peculiar to themselves. Secondly, a research that concludes at pointing out that certain

idea originated with a certain thinker living at certain time in a particular society tells

us nothing why such person should have thought in that way at all.32 When this

objection is raised against the historical method the so called “sociology of knowledge”

comes to its aid. Having traced the origin of an idea to some thinker prior to whom none

of its traces can be found, it is claimed that this idea owes itself to the sociopolitical

context of the thinker in which he lived. This combination of historical with

sociological method can be symbolized as a (┬) the vertical part representing the tracing

of ideas from one thinker to a previous one while the horizontal part representing the

tendency to see the origin of philosophical and religious ideas in the contemporaneous

circumstances of the society. Both these methods have been convincingly criticized by

many writers. We feel affinity in particular with the argument presented by the

Mediaevalist Etienne Gilson that what is wrong with the effort to “account for the rise

of philosophical ideas by historical, sociological and economic factors” is not that it

does not work but that it always works. Gilson has argued that contrary to what should

have been the case in the light of socio-historical method, we find one and same idea,

e.g. Aristotelianism among people living in societies ranging from slavery-based society

31 Rene Guenon, Introduction to the Study of Hindu Doctrine (London: Luzac & Co., 1945), 124. 32

In the words of Frithjof Schuon, People are relieved when they recall that the usage in question dates

from the middle ages or perhaps that it is “Byzantine.”… They forget completely that there is only one

question that must always be asked, namely, why the Byzantines did such a thing; more often than not

one finds that the answer to this why is situated outside time.” Light on the Ancient Worlds (London:

Perennial Books, 1965), 125.

Page 24: 988S

11

of Greece, feudal and bourgeoisie. On the other hand we find people belonging to same

socio-historical context flatly contradicting Aristotelian philosophy. He concludes by

saying that the ultimate explanation of philosophy has to be philosophy itself.” 33

Finally, with Karl R. Popper,34 it can be asserted that the sociological method of

explaining philosophical ideas away can be shown to be self-refuting. If all ideas

originate in the socio-economic conditions and this reduces their philosophical and

objective worth then this idea itself has little philosophical and objective worth to its

since it has origins itself in social settings.

1.41.41.41.4 Theoretical Framework Theoretical Framework Theoretical Framework Theoretical Framework

Our theoretical framework for comparative analysis consists of some concepts,

distinctions and principles derived from the works of Rene Guenon (d. 1951), Frithjof

Schuon (d. 1998) and Nasr (b. 1933). These principles include an emphasis upon the pre-

modern/modern break based on the loss of vertical dimension and exclusive emphasis

upon the horizontal, a distinction between revelation/intellect and reason and the one

between religion and metaphysics. Let us explain these and see some instances of their

application in our comparative analysis of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>.

1111....4444....1111 PrePrePrePre----modernmodernmodernmodern----Modern BreakModern BreakModern BreakModern Break

“The whole movement of thought in the West from Renaissance to Hegel” writes

Seyyed Hossein Nasr, “is a movement toward ‘anti-metaphysics’ and an even greater

33 Etienne Gilson, The Unity of Philosophical Experience (New York: Charles Scribner and Sons, 1965),

304. 34 See Sir Karl R. Popper’s devastating critique of the sociology of knowledge in his The Open Society

and its Enemies (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1950), 401-409.

Page 25: 988S

12

alienation from all that constitutes the very basis of all true ‘philosophy’.”35 An

emphasis upon pre-modern/modern break gives us one additional reason for not applying

the historicist method. This method presupposes that explanation of ideas, and for that

matter, of everything, can be afforded only upon horizontal axis, it is unscientific to

appeal to vertical, meta-historical sources, metaphysical principles. Both writers whom

we seek to compare here present their own work primarily as exegesis of the Scripture

and one of them further claims that most of what he says is based on spiritual unveiling.

An attempt to locate their thought in socio-economic circumstances or historical source

would be first of all an unjustified falsification of their self-understanding. Moreover, a

consistent application of the historicist method would also demand that we assign a

horizontal origin and socio-economic explanation for the Scriptures in question,

something we are not ready to undertake. Obviously, if a method cannot be applied

consistently, it is pointless to apply it to arbitrarily isolated areas, texts, notions, beliefs

and practices. We do not endorse the attempts to compare our both thinkers to any

modern or post-modern writer. In particular we do not endorse the attempt to see in

Eriugena a predecessor of Descartes,36 of German idealism or Marxist centuries before

Marx.37 Our approach also excludes the endeavor to find in Ibn ‘Arabī germs of

Derrida’s deconstruction or anything like that.

35

Seyyed Hossein Nasr, “Conditions for Meaningful Comparative Philosophy,” in Philosophy East and

West, XXII (1972), 57-58. 36 Brian Stock argued with reference to DDN IV: 776B that Eriugena’s cogito was a link between

Augustine’s affirmation of individual existence and Descartes’ cogito. Stock, “Intelligo me esse:

Eriugena’s Cogito:” in Jean Scot Erigene et l’histoire de la philosophie, ed., R. Roques (Paris: CNRS,

1977), 327. 37 This opinion of J. Kabaj, from his article “Homme et nature dans la Cosmologie de Jean Scot Erigena,”

Studia Mediewistyczne 18, i (1977), 3-50 is cited here via its summary given by Mary Brennan’s Guide to

Eriugenian Studies.

Page 26: 988S

13

1111....4444....2222 MetaphysicsMetaphysicsMetaphysicsMetaphysics----Religion DReligion DReligion DReligion Dichotomyichotomyichotomyichotomy

The way we distinguish between metaphysics and religion is based on the ideas of Rene

Guenon who has emphasized that while comparing Eastern and Western religious

systems attention must be paid to the difference between metaphysical and theologico-

religious elements on the one hand and metaphysical and philosophical on the other.38 A

metaphysical doctrine stands apart from the religious in the former’s being purely

intellectual, unlike the latter in which there is an additional element of sentimentality

and concern with personal salvation.39 A metaphysical doctrine is not a philosophical

doctrine because, unlike the latter, it pertains to the intellectual level and not merely to

the rational level.

The distinction between metaphysics and religion finds many interesting

applications in the comparative analysis of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. Let us mention one

by way of example. While discussing the philosophy of Eriugena, John Marenbon has

observed about sacred history of creation which includes fall, redemption and

resurrection that “It is a counterpart on a historical level, to the scheme of permanence,

procession and return, advanced on the plane of metaphysics.”40 Here the metaphysical

plane could have been contrasted with the religious level instead of the historical one.

Similarly, Eriugena suggests at one place that the affirmative way of talking about God

is for the simple minded believers while the negative way that of spiritually more

advanced. (DDN I: 511C) Here again we can equate the former with metaphysics while

the latter with religion.

38 Guenon, Hindu Doctrine, 41. 39 Ibid. 124. 40 John Marenbon, Early Medieval Philosophy, 64.

Page 27: 988S

14

In the beginning of his Al-Futu}h}a>t Ibn ‘Arabi> states his credo which is

completely in line with the orthodoxy. The modern editions of his works usually like to

cite this credo in order to prove his orthodoxy. But the credo terminates at the strange

claim, never quoted in those editions, that “this is the belief of ordinary members of

Muslim community” which implies that he professes two sets of belief, one of which is

in line with orthodoxy, while the other not necessarily so. Latter Sufism developed this

as a dichotomy between the Tawh}i>d of Ordinary Folk and Tawh}i>d of the Elect and this

eventually misled some critics to consider Sufism “as a religion parallel with Islam.” 41

Now if we identify the latter tawh}i>d with metaphysics while the former with religion

then they appear as belonging to two different levels and consequently no conflict

occurs between them. Using this terminology we can say that the Doctrine of oneness of

God is a religious Doctrine while the doctrine of Oneness of Being is a metaphysical

doctrine. A religious doctrine is to be evaluated in religious terms while a metaphysical

doctrine is to be treated as such, the religious, theological and legal, categories when

applied to metaphysics cause serious confusions. During our comparative analysis of

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> we will find more occasions to apply this distinction.

1111....4444....3333 IntellectIntellectIntellectIntellect----Reason DReason DReason DReason Dichotomyichotomyichotomyichotomy

The difference between intellect and reason is explained by Schuon who characterizes

the former as being “contemplative power, receptivity in respect of the Uncreated Light,

the opening of the Eye of the Heart, which distinguishes transcendent intelligence from

41 A case in point of such confusion is the opinion of contemporary Pakistani scholar Javaid Ah}mad

Gha>midi>, in view of such dichotomy within Ibn ‘Arabi>, that Sufism is a religion parallel with Islam. This

opinion expresses a half truth. Sufism consists of metaphysical dimension of Islam which parallels its

purely religious dimensions.

Page 28: 988S

15

reason” while the latter as “perceiving the general and proceeding by logical

operations.”42

This distinction between intellect and reason is relevant in the present context.

Apparently, Eriugena seems to be a rationalist theologian-philosopher since he always

praises and upholds reason while Ibn ‘Arabi> is more of a mystic because he is critical of

reason and attaches more value to religious experience. But when we look into this

matter a little deeper, a different picture emerges. Firstly, as Dermot Moran has noted,

“[t]he dialogue [i.e. DDN] is not merely written to instruct and impart knowledge but

also to provide a vehicle for traveling on the roads towards spiritual enlightenment and

ultimately unity with the Truth itself.”43 Secondly, and more importantly, Eriugena

seldom mentions reason alone and he often uses the expression “reason and intellect”

(ratio et intellectus) and the identification of intellect with discursive reason is a

typically modern phenomenon. Michael Sells recognizes this point:

By reason the Nutritor has in mind something other than the respect for rules of

logic and argumentation that is sometimes called discursive reason. Elsewhere

he characterizes reason as a being-in-constant-motion, a continual movement of

the mind, an infinitely deepening exploration of a reality that itself has no end.44

Likewise, Ibn ‘Arabi> differentiates discursive reason and intellectual intuition by

analyzing the etymology of ‘aql and qalb and notes that the former tends to be static and

binding but the latter is dynamic and never stopping. (Fut. II: 114) If we keep this in

mind then Eriugena’s usage of reason, as explained by Sells, is closer to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

heart than it is to mind.

42 Schuon, “Vicissitudes of Different Spiritual Temperaments,” in Gnosis Divine Wisdom (London: John

Murray, 1959), 49. 43 That this is correct might be seen with reference to DDN IV: 784A, IV: 858B, V: 864B and V: 1010C. 44 Michael Sells, The Mystical Languages of Unsaying, 49. The reference here is to DDN III: 643 B-D.

Page 29: 988S

16

In the same context, Michael Sells has also raised a pertinent and relevant

question, “Is Periphyseon (DDN) a Mystical text?” He answers that “[i]f we define

mystical writing as the autobiographical account of personal, subjective experience,

then the answer is no. Eriugena is explicit in his devotion to dialectical reason as the

method of exploring nature.”45 This is how it appears from Eriugena’s own writings

about reason but it is unlikely that Eriugena, who transforms the meaning of key terms,

when praises reason, has in mind only its discursive sense. We have just seen Sells

himself explaining that Eriugena does not use reason in sense of discursive reason which

supposedly is the key in differentiating philosophy from mysticism. But Sells does pay

attention to the other possibility by saying that the “mystery of being, of life and of

consciousness is unfathomable. Reason is led by its own reasoning beyond itself

continually without arriving at a final entity or conclusion. In that particular sense of

allowing reason to lead beyond itself, Eriugena can be considered a mystic.”46 Thus the

distinction between intellect shows that the project of comparing Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> cannot be criticized by claiming that the former is rationalist philosopher while

the latter is a mystic.

45 Ibid 59. 46 Ibid. 60.

Page 30: 988S

TwoTwoTwoTwo

The Ontological FoundatiThe Ontological FoundatiThe Ontological FoundatiThe Ontological Foundations ons ons ons Prior to comparing Eriugena’s first division of nature, namely God as the first cause,

with the teachings of Ibn ‘Arabi>, it seems necessary to pay attention to the prologue to

De Diuisione Naturae in which the ontological foundations of cosmology are laid down.

This comparison is purported to reveal points where the two philosophers agree or

disagree as far as their conceptions of totality and criteria of differentiating being from

not-being are concerned. This chapter consists of three sections. In the first section we

present and compare conceptions of totality. The second section discusses Eriugena’s

modes of demarcating being and not-being as he puts them forward in the prologue. This

discussion purports to demonstrate firstly that Eriugena connects being with knowing

and secondly that his ontology is a perspectival one according to which the concepts of

being and not-being are relative. In the third and final section of this chapter which

consists of two subsections, we demonstrate that like that of Eriugena Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

ontology is also connected with intelligibility and is perspectival.

2.12.12.12.1 Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on TotalityEriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on TotalityEriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on TotalityEriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on Totality

2.1.12.1.12.1.12.1.1 Eriugena’s Concept of Totality:Eriugena’s Concept of Totality:Eriugena’s Concept of Totality:Eriugena’s Concept of Totality:

Eriugena’s De Diuisione Naturae commences with presenting a division of totality. The

name Eriugena prefers to give to totality there is “nature (natura)” which is said to be

the “general name for all things, those that are (ea quae sunt) and those that are not (ea

Page 31: 988S

18

quae non sunt).” (DDN I: 441A). As has been noted by Dermot Moran,47 Eriugena does

not stick to this definition of “nature” but also uses it to imply ineffable nature of God,

His creative nature, realm of incorporeal, cosmic hierarchies, and objects found in the

spatiotemporal world and laws of nature.

Now this is the most fundamental division one can make between things that can

be grasped by the mind or lie beyond its grasp. (Ibid) If we take into account the fact

that in the former division the reference point was being or not-being while now it is the

grasp of mind, we can see that Eriugena has added epistemological categorization to the

ontological one. This addition heralds the fact that Eriugena is going to connect these

two levels. It is however not obvious at this stage how these two levels correlate in the

context of division of totality.

There seem to be two ways of interpreting the preliminary division of nature.

First, there are two categories of things: those which can be grasped by the mind and

those which lie beyond its grasp. Each of these is further divided into things that are and

thing that are not. Second, things which can be grasped by the mind correspond to

things which are while those that lie beyond its grasp are not. In the light of first

interpretation the epistemic division becomes more basic than the ontological.

According to this division both knowable and unknowable are divided into things that

are and those that are not. Consequently “to be” will not be necessarily synonymous to

“to be known” since among the unknowables there is one class of things which are said

to be. While on the latter interpretation, the epistemic level is not only more basic than

the ontological but is its paradigm.48 Probably, the second interpretation will be favored

47

See The Philosophy, 249. 48 It is strange that Moran who is always anxious to prove Eriugena's idealism does not refer to this point

even where he is concentrating on the opening of De Diuisione Naturae. See Moran, “Natura

Page 32: 988S

19

by those who are fond of making an Idealist out of Eriugena, while the former would go

against such attempts.

Eriugena divides nature into four species, viz., the cause of all things that are and

that are not, who is God, primordial causes, things that become manifest through

coming into being in times and places (DDN, I: 442B) and God as the end of all things.49

Nature as such is comparable to universitas, a term Eriugena has coined to denote

totality of God and creatures. (Ibid. II: 528B) However, although Eriugena has taken the

steps of joining God and creature under one head, he was careful to point out that the

God world relationship is neither that of genus-species nor that of part-whole. (See ibid.

II: 525B)

In Eriugena there is an ultimate reduction of four divisions of nature to one

division. This reduction takes place in three steps. Firstly he collapses the second and

third divisions by suggesting that cause and effect have the same meaning and thus

should be considered identical and not as two things. (See ibid. III: 693A-B.) Secondly,

first and fourth divisions are unified since they both denote God, the former as first

cause and the latter as final cause. (Ibid. II: 526C.) Hence we are left with created nature

and uncreated nature. The most drastic step is the third one where these two are reduced

to one. The reason for this reduction is that there is nothing in creature “save Him who

alone truly is –for nothing apart from Him is truly called essential since all things that

are are nothing else, in so far as they are, but the participation in Him who alone

subsists from and through Himself.” (Ibid)

Quadriformata and the beginnings of the Physiologia in the Philosophy of Johannes Scottus Eriugena,” in

Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale, XXI (1979), 41-46. 49

This explanation of the fourth division is not provided until the second book (526D) where the Nutritor

speaks in some detail about it.

Page 33: 988S

20

After mentioning the four divisions of nature, Eriugena proceeds towards

describing their mutual logical connections in the light of the square of oppositions and

says that the first [uncreated creator] is opposed to the third [created-uncreating] while

the second[created creator] is opposed to the fourth [uncreated-uncreating]. (Ibid. I:

442A)

2.1.22.1.22.1.22.1.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Concept of TotalityIbn ‘Arabi>’s Concept of TotalityIbn ‘Arabi>’s Concept of TotalityIbn ‘Arabi>’s Concept of Totality

Instead of using “nature” to denote totality that should include God, cosmos and non-

existence, like Eriugena has done, Ibn ‘Arabi> understands by the ‘Arabic counterpart of

this word t}abi>‘ah something that can become receptacle for Divine imprint or activity.

This understanding alludes to the inherent passivity of created nature. (See Fut. I: 94)

Though we do find in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s work divisions of totality he does not identify them

with diuisione naturae as does Eriugena. Since we can equate nature and totality, a

comparison of the opening lines of De Diuisione Naturae to this aspect of Ibn ‘Arabi> is

plausible.

In Ibn ‘Arabi>’s opinion a circle is the perfect representation of totality and he

finds in the Qur’a>n something which he takes to be a reference to the most

comprehensive of circles, one which encompasses both creator and the creature. In the

context of Prophet Muh}ammad’s proximity to the Divine that he attained during his

Night Journey (معراج) the Qur’a>n says: “Then he drew close, so He came down and he

was two bows’ length (قاب قوسين) away or closer.” (53:8-9) “Two bows” according to Ibn

‘Arabi> are two arcs of the circle which is “what he often calls the ‘totality’ (المجموع).”50

50

William Chittick, Self Disclosure of God, 233.

Page 34: 988S

21

There are two divisions in Ibn ‘Arabi> that should be compared with Eriugenian

division of totality. In Al-Futu>h}a>t al-Makkiyah he presents a division of “objects of

knowledge” (المعلومات) and in Insha’> al-Dawa>’ir a division of “things.”

In Futu>h}a>t Ibn ‘Arabi> speaks of “three objects of knowledge without a fourth,”

non-delimited being (الوجود المطلق), which does not become delimited (يتقيد �) equated by

him with God, non-delimited nothingness (العدم المطلق) which is non existence in itself

and finally something which shares the characteristics of both. (Fut. III: 46)

Ibn ‘Arabi> introduces another division in Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir :

Know that things exist solely according to three modes, and that knowledge

depends solely upon these three modes. … These three modes comprise: 1. that

which is qualified by existence itself… it is unlimited absolute being. … such is

God. 2. That which is existent through God and is limited being. The latter

includes the world… 3. that which is qualified neither by existence nor by non-

existence… call it the reality of realities, hylé, Primordial matter or the root of

roots.(15-19) 51

Notice that the former division includes “absolute non-existence” while the

latter excludes it. Also notice that the latter includes the spatio-temporal world while

the former does not mention it but gives its place to the third thing. Before we try to

synthesize these two divisions let us mention one difficulty. In the former division by

calling three categories “objects of knowledge” Ibn ‘Arabi> seems to imply that absolute

non-existence can be known. But the reason that he excludes absolute non-existence

from the second division is precisely that “that which is other than these three modes is

pure non-being, neither known, unknown nor function of another thing.” (Ibid)

51

The translation into English is by Paul Fenton and Maurice Gloton, “The Book of the Description of

Encompassing Circles,” in Muh}yiddi>n ibn ‘Arabi>: A Commemorative Volume, ed. Stephen Hirtenstein

and Michael Tiernen (Shaftsbury: Element Books, 1993), 24-27.

Page 35: 988S

22

Moreover, in the former division the “third thing” is said both to be and not to be while

in the in the latter we are told that it can be said neither to be nor not to be.

Having observed these ambiguities, we can attempt to synthesize the two

divisions mentioned above. It appears that there can be two, not entirely different, ways

of accomplishing this task. Firstly, we can have one division consisting of four terms:

God, the world, absolute non-existence and the third thing. Secondly, by collapsing

second and third terms into the category of intermediary realm, isthmus (برزخ), , , , we can

have a division though consisting of three terms but still synthesizing the two divisions

Ibn ‘Arabi> gave.

Hence, we have four basic concepts: Absolute Existence, Relative existence,

third-thing and Absolute non-existence. From the viewpoint of

transcendence/immanence Ibn ‘Arabi> also calls the first and the fourth poles

respectively “He” (ھو) and “not-He” (ھو �) i.e. the former identical and the latter non-

identical with the Divine. While what comes in between accepts both properties,

existence and non-existence, and is at once identical and non-identical to the Divine.

Therefore it is called “He/Not-He” ( �ھو|ھو ). This station belongs to the cosmos and the

third thing which Ibn ‘Arabi> calls “Reality of realities” (حقيقة الحقائق) in Insha>’ al-Dawa>‘ir

and identifies with locus of the immutable entities in Al-Futu>h}a>t. This is the

comprehensive reality which comprises all the intelligible and universal realities and is

thus called reality of realities.52 It is equidistant from the other two poles. (See Fut. III:

46) The other part of barzakh, which happens to be cosmos, however, is nearer to non-

existence than to existence, that is, it is more “not-He” than “He”: “We have a reality

52

See Masataka Takeshita, “An Analysis of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Insha>’ al-dawa>’ir with Particular Reference to

the Doctrine of the ‘Third Entity’,” in Journal of Near Eastern Studies, XLI (1982), 245.

Page 36: 988S

23

that receives both descriptions, but we are closer to non-existence.” (Ibid. II: 248; trans.

SPK: 87)

GodGodGodGod Pure Existence

ImpossibleImpossibleImpossibleImpossible Pure Nonexistence

The WorldThe WorldThe WorldThe World Existence/ Nonexistence

Third ThingThird ThingThird ThingThird Thing Existence

Nonexistence

TotalityTotalityTotalityTotality

Ibn 'ArabIbn 'ArabIbn 'ArabIbn 'Arabi>’i>’i>’i>’s Division of s Division of s Division of s Division of Totality: Synthesis ITotality: Synthesis ITotality: Synthesis ITotality: Synthesis I

GodGodGodGod Pure Existence

IntermediaryIntermediaryIntermediaryIntermediary Existence/Nonexistence

ImpossibleImpossibleImpossibleImpossible Pure Non-existence

Third ThingThird ThingThird ThingThird Thing The WorldThe WorldThe WorldThe World

Totality

Ibn 'ArabIbn 'ArabIbn 'ArabIbn 'Arabi>’i>’i>’i>’s Division of s Division of s Division of s Division of Totality: Totality: Totality: Totality: SynthesisSynthesisSynthesisSynthesis IIIIIIII

Page 37: 988S

24

Although Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> include both esse and non esse in their

divisions of totality, we see that Ibn ‘Arabi> goes a little farther than Eriugena. Eriugena

does not understand by his quae non sunt absolute non-existents so he has not included

them in his division of nature. He asks rhetorically, “For how can that which absolutely

is not, and cannot be, and which does not surpass the intellect because of the pre-

eminence of its existence, be included in the division of things.” (DDN I: 443C) Ibn

‘Arabi>’s concept of totality is more inclusive since it encompasses absolute nothingness

and places relative existence/nonexistence between absolute being and absolute

nonexistence. Although this is a step forward, it seems that Eriugena had made room for

this step in a qualification that he inserted within the remark just quoted by granting the

possibility of awarding some sort of ontological status to absences and privations and

thus including them in the division of things (in rerum diuisionibus). At another place he

even seems ready to welcome the impossible by making an allowance for reckoning the

possible and impossible in the number of things. (See DDN II: 597B) Hence the

difference between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> is somewhat reduced.

2222....2222 Eriugena’s Modes of Being: Ontology Eriugena’s Modes of Being: Ontology Eriugena’s Modes of Being: Ontology Eriugena’s Modes of Being: Ontology ---- IntelligiIntelligiIntelligiIntelligibility bility bility bility

Connection and Perspectival Ontology Connection and Perspectival Ontology Connection and Perspectival Ontology Connection and Perspectival Ontology

After defining totality and mentioning the four divisions of nature, Eriugena discusses

what differentiates ea quae sunt from ea quae non sunt and presents what he calls five

modes of interpretation (modos interpretationis), or perspectives.

There is some dispute regarding the place of these five modes of being and not-

being in Eriugena’s thought. Dermot Moran has tried to underestimate their importance

by pointing to the fact that Eriugena never returns again to these modes in the course of

Page 38: 988S

25

De Diuisione Naturae.53 Dierdre Carabine is of the opinion that through his discussion

of the modes, Eriugena shows that “being and non-being, while being contradictory, are

dissolved, not only in God… but also at every level of reality depending on one’s

starting point.”54 At this point we think that Carabine’s opinion depicts a truer picture

of the case and we will demonstrate at various points in the following chapters that

these ontological discussions especially the modes of differentiating being from not-

being are very important for the elaboration of four divisions of nature.

Anyway the welding together of the ontological with the epistemic which was

indicated in the opening lines of Eriugena’s work is reasserted here in the first

perspective on being and nothingness.55Accordingly, things which fall within the scope

of sense perception or intellect are “truly and reasonably said to be, while those which

elude, because of the excellence of their nature, not only all sense but also all intellect

and reason” are said not to be. A number of important points are worth noticing in the

passage that discusses this perspective. First, not-being is here considered more

excellent than being and God is mentioned as instantiating things that are said not to be,

as they elude sense perception and intellect due to the excellence of their essence (per

excellentiam), not due to some lack or imperfection on their part. This concept is a

distinctive mark of Eriugena’s thought and we will say more on it in the next chapter. In

that chapter on the nature of God we shall also discuss the perspective from which God

can be said not to exist according to Ibn ‘Arabi> as well. Eriugena emphasizes

53 See The Philosophy, 226. 54

Dierdre Carabine, John Scottus Eriugena, 40. 55

This way hints at a relationship between the twofold division of natura and the first of the five modes.

The connection, thus seems to be the reference to comprehensibility. Anyway Dominic O’Meara grapples

at length with the problem of relating five modes to the concept of natura. He thinks that the former

explains and clarifies the latter. See his article “The Concept of Nature in John Scottus Eriugena,” in

Vivarium XIX(1981), 134.

Page 39: 988S

26

incomprehensibility of God by intellect and instead of limiting this incomprehensibility

to “God as He is in Himself beyond every creature” extends it to God “when considered

in the innermost depths of the creature which was made by Him and which exists in

Him.” (DDN I: 443B) The second mode is based on hierarchy and differences within

created nature. Here we find two sided perspectival approach to being and non-being.

Hence each order, excluding the highest and the lowest ones can be said both to be and

not to be depending on whether we are considering it in contrast with higher orders or

the lower ones. The lowest order according to Eriugena is that of bodies while the

highest is God. God as the highest member of the order will be said not to be, since

unknown by the lower order, there being nothing above to know Him. The lowest order

will be said only to be, since known by higher orders but having no order lower than it

which could be stopped from knowing it. Just before explaining the third mode Eriugena

adds another formulation of the second mode which also hinges upon knowability

relative to orders lower or higher than a given ordo rationalis et intellectualis

creaturae.(DDN I: 444C) In its dependence upon knowability this last formulation

brings second mode close to the first one, and thus to the twofold division of natura.

Although Eriugena does not give an example of this sense it is easy to find one. For

instance the soul that is higher than the body but lower to God can be said both to be

and not to be. It can be said to be in so far as it is known to God but it is not in so far as

it does not permit itself to be known by the bodies.

According to the third perspective only those things can be said to be which have

proceeded out of their primordial causes into the spatiotemporal world. Before their

manifestation, when they are still hidden in the secret folds of nature, they are not. This

perspective is described as based on human convention (humana consuetudine).

Page 40: 988S

27

Eriugena mentions as example the creation of all human beings at once in that first and

one human being whom God made in his image. They are, obviously, not brought into

the visible world simultaneously with the creation of the first man. Conventionally,

human beings can be said to be once they are brought in the visible world but before

that they are not. As Eriugena puts it, “those who have already become visibly manifest

in the world are said to be while those who are as yet hidden, though are destined to be

are said not to be.” (DDN I: 445A) Although Eriugena also mentions the more familiar

example of nature latent in seeds and manifest in form of trees and flowers, the

mentioning of first human being as one of the primordial causes is a little curious.

Firstly because this concept does not coincide with type of things that Eriugena gives as

instances of primordial causes.56 Second, it gives rise to the question regarding the

nature of creation of first human being, whether or not it was tantamount to bringing

him into the visible world. How to differentiate between making and producing in the

context of creation of human being?

According to the fourth perspective, which is said to be those of the

philosophers, things that can be said to be are those which are knowable by intellect.

Asymmetrically, Eriugena names corruptible things as those which are said not to be.

This perspective can be rendered thus: immutable and incorruptible things which are

intelligible are while the corruptible and mutable ones that are known by sense

perception are not.

The fifth perspective is applicable to the two human natures, fallen and

redeemed through Christ. Man is created upon Divine image but “through sin renounced

56 See DDN II: 616C; III: 622B-623C. The list includes only attributes like justice, truth, eternity and does

not mention persons.

Page 41: 988S

28

the honour of the Divine image.” In this state man is said not to be. But he begins to be

when he is brought back to his former condition, restored by the grace of Christ.

Eriugena quotes here the words of Apostle and presents two interpretations. The

Apostle says, “[a]nd He calls things that are not as things that are.” Firstly, this would

imply God’s calling through faith, those who had fallen into a kind of non-subsistence,

to be those who are already reborn. The second possible interpretation is, unlike the first

religious one, metaphysical in character. Eriugena writes:

But this too may be understood of those whom God daily calls forth from the

secret folds of nature in which they are considered not to be, to become visibly

manifest in form and matter and in the other conditions in which hidden things

are able to become manifest. (DDN I. 445D )

Here the “secret folds of nature” clearly refer to the state of things in their

primordial causes before spatiotemporal manifestation. This is also consistent with the

third mode of being and not-being. Let us notice, in passing, a similarity between this

mode of demarcation given by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s ontology. One definition of

existence Ibn ‘Arabi> gives is: “Wuju>d is the manifestation of the existent in its entity

According to this definition something can be said to be only (Fut. III: 31) \”.(في عينه)

after it has become manifest in the spatio-temporal world. As we shall discuss in the

third chapter, prior to manifestation in concreto, everything is an object of Divine

knowledge, a fixed entity (عين ثابت) and it is well known that Ibn ‘Arabi> calls these non-

existents. (See ibid. I: 702; II: 392; III: 296; IV: 136) Moreover, God’s “calling things

daily to be” resonates with Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine of perpetual creation which he founds

upon the Qur’a>nic words, “Each day He is upon some task,” (55:29)

Although in Book I Eriugena mentions only five perspectives for marking off

what is from what is not, he admits that his list here is not meant to be exhaustive since

Page 42: 988S

29

“keener reasoning can discover some modes besides these.” (DDN I: 446A.) Dermot

Moran has tried to extract some further modes of being and not-being from various

places of De Diuisione Naturae.57 This he does with a view to support the opinion that

these five modes are not very important in the overall scheme of DDN and Eriugena

abandons them soon after introducing them. According to him, Eriugena uses at III:

646B a sixth mode of being whereby God possesses all being and the creature is mere

nothingness.58 The way Eriugena introduces the five modes into the discussion shows

that he is concerned with the connotation or sense of existence and non existence and

not primarily with enumerating what kind of things there are, that is with the denotation

or reference of existence and nonexistence. On the other hand what Moran has

mentioned here is in fact not the mode itself (that is, connotation) but only the result of

its application (that is denotation). It is not clear what the criterion of distinction itself

would be. At III: 646 the underlying mode itself seems to depend on whether we are

considering creatures in themselves or as participating in God. They can be said not to

be in the former sense but to the extent of the latter they are said to be. All this, of

course, implies that in a complete and real sense only God can be said to possess being.59

Even if this is a criterion or mode, it would be quite unlike the previous ones, since it is

applicable to creatures only. It makes no sense to ask whether God participates in God.

We can look at the creatures from the perspective of participation

57

See Moran, The Philosophy, 226-227.

58 See ibid. 226. The exclusive attribution of being to God belongs to the early Augustinian period of

Eriugena’s thought (in his De Praedestinatione), before his embarking upon the translations of Greek

sources. See Bernard J. McGinn, “Negative Theology in John the Scot,” in Studia Patristica: Papers

Presented to the Sixth International Conference on Patristic Studies, XIII (1975), 233-234.

59 Cf. DDN I: 454A viz.: “everything which is said to exist exists not in itself but by participation in the

Nature which truly exists.”

Page 43: 988S

30

or otherwise. Therefore, we cannot say that according to the sixth mode only God is but

creatures are not rather that God absolutely is while creatures can either said to be or

not to be depending upon whether we are looking upon them as participating in God or

not.

Whatever be the criterion behind the so called sixth mode of being the result of

its application is perfectly in line with the central tenet of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine of

oneness of being. Ibn ‘Arabi> writes after formulating this tenet as “there is nothing in

Being/existence but God,” (See Fut. I: 279; trans. SPK, 94) that although creatures exist

their existence is through Him and “He whose existence is through other-than-himself is

non-existent.” (See ibid.)

As the seventh mode Moran mentions Eriugena’s saying that substance alone

exists and those things which are accidents and relations do not have being and

comments that this is an Aristotelian concept of being and not-being.60 Eriugena holds

that “everything has being only in so far as it subsists essentially, but other things

understood in reference to essence or substance are not to be reckoned in the number of

the universe of things.” (DDN IV:764C) In our opinion this, although relevant to the

modes of being and not- being, does not amount to a separate mode in itself. This is just

an application of the fourth mode since substances are said to be because they are

immutable and accidents are not so because they undergo change and corruption. In

view of this analysis of additional modes it would be incorrect to say that Eriugena

abandons the five modes of being in the main body of his DDN.

60

Moran, op cit.

Page 44: 988S

31

2.32.32.32.3 Ontology Ontology Ontology Ontology ---- Intelligibility Connection Intelligibility Connection Intelligibility Connection Intelligibility Connection and Perspectival and Perspectival and Perspectival and Perspectival

OntologyOntologyOntologyOntology inininin Ibn ‘Arabi>Ibn ‘Arabi>Ibn ‘Arabi>Ibn ‘Arabi>

2.3.12.3.12.3.12.3.1 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ontology and IntelligibilityIbn ‘Arabi> on Ontology and IntelligibilityIbn ‘Arabi> on Ontology and IntelligibilityIbn ‘Arabi> on Ontology and Intelligibility

The definition of nature presented by Eriugena as well as the first and fourth modes of

demarcating being from not-being have shown us that he connects ontology with

intelligibility and the overall nature of his ontology is perspectival. Although we have

already made a couple of remarks regarding some points of comparison with Ibn ‘Arabi>,

in the present section and the subsequent ones we are going to dwell more fully on the

latter in order to see whether his ontology shares these two general characteristics with

Eriugena or not.

The Arabic word for existence/being is wuju>d. Another derivative from this same

root, w j d, is wijda>n or “finding.” Since Ibn ‘Arabi> draws philosophical conclusions

from the co-relation of various derivatives from single root he defines existence, wuju>d

as finding: “In the view of the Tribe wuju>d is finding the Real (وجدان الحق) in ecstasy.”

(Fut. II: 538; trans. SPK: 212). 61 God exists as He is found, in fact nothing is found but

Him as He is the Manifest. Other than Him exist since these are found by Him. The

elect who have reached the stage of mystical verification are given the title of “people

of unveiling and finding (ahl al-Kashf wa al-wuju>d).” This welding of existing with

finding is apparently a bringing together of the ontological with the epistemic which is

very close to the Eriugenian repeated references to things that can or cannot be grasped

by mind in the context of ontology, to the extent that it has lead certain commentators

to deem him an idealist of sorts.62

61

In view of its dual meaning William Chittick translates this word at various places as

“existence/finding.” 62

Having noted that the Arabic word for “perception” is translated into Persian also as “finding” Chittick

Page 45: 988S

32

Commenting on a Qur’a>nic verse “No! I swear by what you see and by what you

do not see.” (69:38-39) Ibn ‘Arabi> says that within this swear fall all kinds of existent

things and also non-existence (العدم) and non-existents (المعدومات), which is (denoted by)

His saying “what you do not see.” (See Fut. II: 672) At another place he has further

commented upon the same words thus: “God says, No! I swear by what you see which is

what becomes manifest to us and by what you do not see (69:38-39), which is what is

hidden from us.” (Fut. III: 108; trans., SDG: 334). Here Ibn ‘Arabi> is considering the

division of totality into epistemic categories (what we see/what we do not) as more

basic and subsumes the ontological division (existent/non-existent) under it. This

corresponds to second interpretation of Eriugena’s considering natura to be a name of

things graspable and ungraspable by the mind. It should not be objected that Eriugena

refers to mind while Ibn ‘Arabi> is mentioning “seeing.” Although the Arabic word بصر

is used to denote only the outward eye and the word بصيرة is reserved for the inward eye

or insight and Ibn ‘Arabi> follows this custom (E.g. Fut. IV: 30), he does use the former

to denote both, for instance when he says that “man possesses sight (بصر) in his hidden

(Ibid. I: 405) ”.(ظاھر) as well as his manifest part (باطن)

We submit, however, that just as Eriugena does not always subjugate the

ontological to the epistemic but at times shows the opposite, realist tendency, as he

does when he implies that only that can be understood which has being, so does Ibn

‘Arabi>. Eriugena says “For everything which is not from God cannot be understood in

any way since it has no being in any way.” (DDN IV: 765A)63 Just as God is being and

writes, “the perception which takes place through the light is the finding that takes place through wuju>d.”

Sufi Path of Knowledge, 214. 63 This statement, if our reading of it is adequate, poses serious challenge to Idealist interpretation of

Eriugena. The causal dependence of epistemic upon ontological is incompatible with Idealism. See what

Page 46: 988S

33

everything else mere not-being, so whatever is from God can be said to be and

consequently can be understood, while whatever is not from him is not and cannot be

understood in anyway. In one passage Ibn ‘Arabi> presents a division of totality in terms

of light, darkness and shadow according to which God is sheer light and the impossible

is sheer darkness while creation is in between these two extremes. He remarks that the

difference between light and darkness consists in the fact that the former is perceived

and through it perception takes place while the latter is perceived but through it no

perception takes place. (See Fut. III: 274; trans., SPK, 213-214) If we take into account

the identification of God with Absolute Being and of the Impossible with Absolute non-

existence we can discern here a connection between epistemic and the ontological, but

their co-relation here is not tilted towards idealism because it is implied here that what

is found is found due to existence. The metaphor of light makes this abundantly clear:

“were it not for the light, nothing whatsoever would be perceived, neither object of

knowledge nor sensory object, nor imaginal object.” (Ibid. III: 276, SPK: 214)

When Ibn ‘Arabi> attempts to solve the problem of free will and predestination,

he once again refers to the dependence of knowledge upon reality and this time extends

it to include God: “Knowledge follows the object of knowledge… And the Real does not

know except that (condition) upon which the object of knowledge itself is.” (Ibid.

IV: 18)

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> maintain similar, though complex, position regarding

the relationship between ontology and intellectuality. In the face of this one must be as

careful in declaring Ibn ‘Arabi> a ‘firm empiricist’ with Masataka Takeshita, as one

Frederick Copleston points out against Berkeley’s analysis of existence. A History of Philosophy (New

Jersey: Paulist Press, 1950), V: 220.

Page 47: 988S

34

should be in making Eriugena an Idealist with Dermot Moran and others.64

2.3.22.3.22.3.22.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Perspectival OntoloIbn ‘Arabi>’s Perspectival OntoloIbn ‘Arabi>’s Perspectival OntoloIbn ‘Arabi>’s Perspectival Ontologygygygy

As has been noticed by many commentators, Eriugena’s five modes of demarcation give

us a “perspectival” conception of existence. The denotation and status of existence and

non-existence depend upon the perspective from which one looks at them. Depending

upon perspective, non existence may denote Divine Essence, primordial causes,

unknowability of the higher to the lower and post-fall human condition. From one

perspective non-existence is more eminent than existence while from another, opposite

is the case. The interpretational significance of such approach to ontology is that it

helps us understand the consistency of Eriugena’s view regarding Divine nothingness.

That is to say, there is no contradiction between saying that “God is non-existent” and

that “only God truly is and everything else is not” as his sixth mode provides, since

different perspectives are involved.

Though Ibn ‘Arabi>’s writings are replete with insightful comments upon the

nature of existence and non-existence, it is in his short treatise Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir that he

treats the subject in some detail. Let us examine the salient features of his conception in

comparison with Eriugena’s.

1. According to Ibn ‘Arabi>, existence and non-existence are relative concepts and

this relativity comes from the fact that they are nothing additional to existent

and nonexistent entities.

64

Takeshita writes: “… Ibn ‘Arabi> is a firm empiricist. According to him existence in concreto is

independent from existence in knowledge, and the former is the source of the latter.” See “The Homo

Imago Dei Motif and the Anthropocentric Metaphysics of Ibn ‘Arabī in the Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir,” in Orient:

Report of the Society for Near Eastern Studies in Japan, XVIII (1982), 113.

Page 48: 988S

35

Know that existence and non-existence are not realities superadded to

an existent (موجود) ) ) ) or non-existent (معدوم) but are inherent in these.

Thought however deems that existence and non-existence are two

attributes applying to the existent or non-existent thing, like a dwelling

which the existent and non-existent enter. (Insha>‘, 6) (ظرف)

For the exclusive purpose of clarification one could compare this comment to the

opinion of those critics of ontological argument like Kant, who argued that

existence is not an attribute. It is recommended that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s views on the

nature of existence in his other works should always be read in the light of what

the above quoted passage provides. Hence whenever one finds him saying about

an existent that it ‘is qualified with existence’ or about non-existent that it ‘is

qualified with non-existence’, one should understand that Ibn ‘Arabi> is just

speaking the ordinary language the logical pitfalls of which he has already

recognized and laid bare elsewhere.

2. The identification of existence and non-existence with existent and nonexistent

things implies their relativity and mutual compatibility.

When, then, the individuality of a thing is affirmed or denied, it is

possible to qualify it simultaneously by non-existence and existence.

But this is so by virtue of relation and correlation ( سبة وا8ضافةالن ). For

example an individual named Zayd is existent at the market and non-

existent in the house. If existence and non existence were qualifications

referring to the existent like black and white it would be impossible to

attribute these qualities to Zayd simultaneously. … It is then well

established that this is absolutely a matter of relations and correlations

like east-west, right-left and front-behind. (Ibid. 7)

3. Ibn ‘Arabi> responds to the question whether it is possible for a thing to be non-

existent in itself and still qualified by existence in another world ( عالم( or by

another consideration?” in affirmative and adds that everything other than God

Page 49: 988S

36

can be said to exist in one or more of four senses (or as he calls them, “degrees”)

of existence: “First, existence of a thing in its concrete essence, … second, its

existence in knowledge,… third, its existence in speech. The fourth is the

existence of a thing in script.” (Ibid.)

So these are the perspectives, additional to the spatio-temporal one mentioned

above in the example of Zayd, from which we can look at existence and non-existence.

Ibn ‘Arabi> applies this perspectival approach in the passage just cited and also in Al-

Futu>h}a>t. In the former place he says that “existence of Allah, the Real, the Exalted, with

reference to our knowledge has these degrees except that of (existence in) knowledge.”65

In Al-Futu>h}a>t he explains this: “the third mode is mental existence and it is the object of

knowledge’s being conceived as it is in itself in its reality. In case the concept is not in

accordance with the reality, which will not be its existence in mind.” (Fut. IV: 300)

However he mentions that the application of second mode depends on our understanding

of the nature of Beatific vision whether it entails positive knowledge of God (ا8ثبات),

that is attainment of a picture in mind or not. (Insha>’ 8) He also discusses the

relationship between mental existence and concrete existence and draws a boundary

between Divine and human realm in this regard. In case of human beings something has

to exist in its entity before it could become an object of knowledge while the opposite

holds in respect of God. Here knowledge is ontologically, not temporally, prior to a

thing’s existence in its entity. (See ibid.) The qualification of priority as non-temporal

allows him to consistently add what he calls “a mystery” to this view. Ibn ‘Arabi> has

65

Ibid. مووجودهللا الحق تعالى بالنظر إلى علمنا على ھذه المراتب ما عدا مرتبة العل . Fenton and Gloton have translated this

sentence as: “Our present knowledge of the existence of God the Real, may He be exalted, presents itself

according to these modes…” Encompassing Circles, 18. This translation is not entirely adequate, since it

makes the four degrees qualify “our knowledge of God’s existence” while they in fact qualify “God’s

existence,” since they are modes of existence not of knowledge, knowledge being one of them.

Page 50: 988S

37

mentioned in Al-Futu>h}a>t that the third and fourth modes of existence are the most

comprehensive ones since they encompass “all objects of knowledge even impossible

and non-existence.” (Fut. IV: 300) Hence, we could speak of “existence of non-

existence” if we mean by “existent” something in the form of marks on a paper and

words spoken. We have already discussed at length that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s canvas of “what

there is” is as comprehensive as Eriugena’s. However, what gives his ontology a little

more clarity is his explication of the senses in which something can be said to be.

Thanks to these, one is saved from understanding by existence only spatio-temporal

existence (like the post-positivism epistemology does) and consequently there remains

no need to remark that Ibn ‘Arabi> seems to assign some sort of reality to thing that do

not exist, remarks that one comes across in Eriugena scholarship.66

Having compared the ontologies of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> and noticed the

common ground between them we are now about to begin with the comparative analysis

of Eriugena’s first division of nature, namely, that which is not created but creates with

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s view on similar matters.

66

For instance see Moran, The Philosophy, 231.

Page 51: 988S

ThreeThreeThreeThree

MetacosmMetacosmMetacosmMetacosm----I: GodI: GodI: GodI: God The present chapter investigates similarities and dissimilarities between the way

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> envisage Divine nature. We shall pay attention in particular to

Eriugenian view that God is created in His effects, Divine unknowability, non-existence,

darkness, affirmative, negative and superlative theologies in comparison with Ibn

‘Arabi.

It might be thought that a work devoted to analysis of cosmology should not

include discussion of Divine nature, a subject that belongs properly to theology or

philosophy of religion. This objection would have been valid had we been concerned

here with modern cosmology. It is not possible in traditional cosmologies to discuss the

nature of tangible world without reference to Divine nature. This impossibility is

reflected in the very definitions Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> provide for “God.”

3.13.13.13.1 Defining “God”Defining “God”Defining “God”Defining “God”

3.1.13.1.13.1.13.1.1 Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on the the the the Definition of “God.”Definition of “God.”Definition of “God.”Definition of “God.”

Eriugena identifies the first division of nature with God as origin of being and the fourth

division with God as the end. He goes on however, to imply that all the four divisions

should be considered as both from God and in God, (DDN III: 690A) which means that

these are theophanies.67 Now while it is easy to consider the second and third divisions,

namely primordial causes and the world, as theophanies it is a little difficult to consider

67

Ibid. 252.

Page 52: 988S

39

God Himself a theophany, i.e., revelation or manifestation of God. Perhaps this

difficulty can be removed by inquiring into the meaning of the word “God.” Eriugena

explains this while introducing the concept of theophany for the very first time in DDN.

According to this explanation not only Divine essence is indicated by “God” but “also

that mode by which God reveals himself in a certain way to intellectual and rational

creatures according to the capacity of each.” (DDN I: 446C-D) Again while

summarizing an earlier discussion Eriugena states clearly that “not only the Divine

essence which exists in itself without change [is] called God but … also the theophanies

which are reproduced out of it and by it in the intellectual nature are themselves given

the name God.” (Ibid. I. 448B)

3.1.23.1.23.1.23.1.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on the Definition of “God.”Ibn ‘Arabi> on the Definition of “God.”Ibn ‘Arabi> on the Definition of “God.”Ibn ‘Arabi> on the Definition of “God.”

As we saw, for Eriugena “God” gives a multi-layered meaning, something by which Ibn

‘Arabi>'s understanding of Divinity is also characterized. While referring to God Ibn

Arabi> uses the word “the Divine presence” (لھيةEالحضرة ا) which he defines by saying

that “There is nothing in existence save Divine presence which is His essence (ذاته), His

attributes (صفاته) and His Actions (أفعاله). (Fut. II: 114)

The first thing to be observed here is a similarity with the so called sixth

Eriugenian mode of being discussed in the previous chapter. This definition reiterates

that real being belongs only to God. Second, obviously, the definition does not limit

divinity to Divine essence but includes Divine attributes, signified by so many Divine

names and Divine actions by which Ibn ‘Arabi> understands nothing but creatures. While

Eriugena has clearly extended the meaning of God to include Divine manifestations

what about attributes/names and actions that Ibn ‘Arabi> includes in his definition of

God? According to Ibn ‘Arabi>, Divine Essence is absolutely unknowable and

Page 53: 988S

40

transcendent. The only connection creatures have with It is through attributes/names

which are declared to be so many veils ( لحجبا ) upon Divine essence, simultaneously

covering and uncovering it. Ibn ‘Arabi> adopts the Mu‘tazilite stance that attributes are

identical with the Divine essence. The creatures are manifestations of the names of God,

what Eriugena calls theophanies. Ibn ‘Arabi> has expressed this in a characteristic

manner, “there is nothing in existence but His names.” (Ibid. II: 303) It is not merely

that God has manifested Himself to human intellects in creatures, rather human being is

the greatest of Divine self-manifestations. Ibn ‘Arabi> thinks that things are

manifestations of the Real in which He revealed Himself for them, even in their own

entities… and it is His saying “We shall show them Our signs upon the horizons and

within their own souls until it is clear to them that it is the Real” (Qur’ān, 41:53).

Therefore, Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> are united in the way they define “God.”

3.23.23.23.2 God as Uncreated and CreatedGod as Uncreated and CreatedGod as Uncreated and CreatedGod as Uncreated and Created

3.2.13.2.13.2.13.2.1 Eriugena’s Standpoint Eriugena’s Standpoint Eriugena’s Standpoint Eriugena’s Standpoint

Eriugena declares that God “is understood to be anarchos i.e., “without beginning,”

because He alone is the Principle cause of all things which are made from Him and

through Him.” (DDN I: 451C-D) In addition to being the beginning and the End God is

also the Middle, “the Beginning because from Him are all things that participate in His

essence; the Middle because in Him and through him they subsist; the End, because it is

towards Him that they move in seeking rest from their movement and stability of their

perfections.” (Ibid. I: 451D)

On the other hand, Eriugena also asserts that the Divine nature not only creates

but is created. (Ibid. I: 452B) The Alumnus expresses his perplexity since Divine nature

has been maintained to be “creative and not created.” (Ibid. I: 454D) Though the

Page 54: 988S

41

Nutritor recognizes that this is hard to swallow he digresses into analysis of the

etymology of the Greek word for God and comes back to the issue only after having

followed his line of thought a little farther than the etymology of theos.

Certainly the notion that “God is made in creatures” should not be taken at its

face value. At a later place in DDN Eriugena implies that he does not want God to be

included in the number of all things that are created. (Ibid. I: 468C) According to him

the statement only means that the Divine nature “is establishing the nature of things.

For the creation of itself, that is, the manifestation of itself in something is surely that

by which all things subsist.” (Ibid.I: 455B) This identification of “creation” as “self-

manifestation” is the key to resolve the perplexity. Divine nature can be understood as

being created because “that which is invisible in itself becomes manifest in all things

that are.” (Ibid. I: 454 A) Eriugena also says that it is said to be created since “nothing

except itself exists as an essence since it itself is the essence of all things.”(Ibid.) To

bring the point home he establishes an analogy with intelligence’s being created in its

effects and says that the Divine Essence is created in those things which are made by

itself, through itself and in itself just “as the intelligence of the mind or its purpose or its

intention or however this first and innermost motion of ours may be called, having

entered upon thought and received the forms of certain fantasies and having then

proceeded into the symbols of sounds or the signs of sensible motions it is not

inappropriately said to become.” (Ibid. I: 454C) The claim that God is made in all things

remains a figure of speech,68 a metaphor, although not arbitrary but grounded in reality

but still a metaphor which provides a single expressive form for the coordinate themes

of theophany, procession, division of nature and God’s essential inherence within the

68

Eriugena writes: “when … God is said to be made, this is obviously by a figure of speech” DDN I:

516C.

Page 55: 988S

42

created order.69 In sum, then, to say that God makes himself in creatures is to say that

He manifests himself in them and that their subsistence is dependent upon God.

3.2.23.2.23.2.23.2.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s StandpointIbn ‘Arabi>’s StandpointIbn ‘Arabi>’s StandpointIbn ‘Arabi>’s Standpoint

Like Eriugena Ibn ‘Arabi> calls the Divine reality “The Middle.” “‘He is the first and the

Last’ (57:3) and He is what is between these two.” (Fut. I: 642) He also considers God

to be the intermediary between two other Divine names while explaining the degrees of

Divine presence: “there are three degrees in the Divine presence, the hidden, the

manifest and the middle.” (Ibid. II: 391) Also noteworthy is Ibn ‘Arabi>’s explication of

the Divine Name, the First and the Last:

God possesses Firstness (وليةEا) because He brings everything into existence. He

also possesses lastness (خريةEا) for He says “To Him the whole affair is

returned” (11: 123) and “To him you will be returned” (2: 245) and “Surely unto

God all affairs come home” (42:53), so He is the Last just as He is the first and

between the first and the last appear the degrees of Divine names. (Ibid. IV:

299; trans. SDG, 204)

Notice how completely this resonates with Eriugena’s statement at I: 451D cited

above. In addition to this Ibn ‘Arabi> maintains that God is the middle between

nonexistence and existence. Things pass through this middle path and are colored in His

color, which is none other than existence. (See Fut. IV: 108, trans. SDG, 46)

That Ibn ‘Arabi> can indeed agree with Eriugena in the concept of Divine self-

creation is signaled by the fact that he makes some reservations to talking about God-

world relationship in terms of cause and effect (see Fut. I: 720). Since according to Ibn

‘Arabi> all creatures are nothing but Divine manifestations, he would have no problems

with Eriugena’s “God creates himself” so long as “creates” stands for “manifests

69

See Donald F. Duclow, “Divine Nothingness and Self-Creation in John Scottus Eriugena,” in Journal of

Religion 57 (1977), 109-3.

Page 56: 988S

43

Himself.” We find Ibn ‘Arabi>> explicitly saying “He made nothing manifest in

endangered existence save what He is in Himself. It is as if He were non-manifest and

became manifest through the cosmos.” (Ibid. II: 399; trans. SDG, 70). So Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> are in complete harmony as far as the former’s concept of Divine self-

creation is concerned.

As for the usage of the expression“being created” for God, we find Ibn ‘Arabi>

doing that in a different context, namely, that “the upholder of every doctrine about

God imagines in his mind a particular thing and worships it saying: “this is Allah!” and

indeed it is Allah no one else and at that particular locus only Allah has created it.”

(Ibid. IV: 211)70 Here Ibn ‘Arabi> explains the meaning of God’s creating himself in the

heart of the believer by sticking to the ordinary meaning of creating as making. But then

he attributes the act of creation to the believer rather than God, he, just like Eriugena,

equates creating with self-manifesting. There is a clear parallel between the example of

intelligence creating its object by contemplating and imagination creating God by

particularizing Him in a specific form.

In sum, Ibn ‘Arabi> does accept what Eriugena means by the expression “God

creates himself,” the expression itself with a different meaning and finally, relates both

the expression and meaning by saying that in creating Himself in the heart of a believer

God manifests Himself to the believer. This diversity of Divine manifestation for

different objects is an idea that is also dear to Eriugena who has written, speaking about

the ineffable Divine essence that it is “One and the same and remains unchanging, it will

be multiple to the sight of those whom it shall be given to dwell in it. (DDN I: 448C) He

70 The first rather long sentence is my own translation. The rest has been taken from William Chittick,

Imaginal Worlds: Ibn al-‘Arabi> and the Problem of Religious Diversity, (New York: State University of

New York Press, 1994), 164.

Page 57: 988S

44

shows similar spirit while expressing his views on the multiplicity of the interpretations

of Scripture which he tries to explain with the help of the image of peacock’s feather

(penna pavonis), unity and diversity all in one. (See ibid. IV: 749C)

3.33.33.33.3 DivineDivineDivineDivine KnowabilityKnowabilityKnowabilityKnowability

3.3.13.3.13.3.13.3.1 Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on DivineDivineDivineDivine KnowabilityKnowabilityKnowabilityKnowability

The theology of self-manifestation of transcendent God includes the issue of Divine

comprehensibility. This is an issue regarding which there is remarkable correspondence

between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. For the former the “Divine Essence, is in itself

comprehensible to no bodily sense, to no reason, to no intellect, whether of man or of

angel.” (Ibid. I: 447C) Though this incomprehensibility is inherent in the Divine

transcendence, it is also metaphysically grounded71 in the principle propounded by the

second mode of differentiating what is from what is not. As every order of nature can be

said to be since it is known by the orders above it and it can be said not to be since it

cannot be known to the orders below it, therefore reason or intellect being on a lower

order than God, cannot understand the latter. Moreover, that which has the capacity to

define something must be greater than that something. (DDN I: 485B)

However, “the Divine essence is incomprehensible in itself but when it is joined

to an intellectual creature it becomes manifest after a wondrous fashion (mirabili modo):

so that the former, I mean the Divine essence, is seen alone in the latter, namely the

intellectual creature” (DDN I: 450B), “God who is incomprehensible in Himself is after

a certain mode comprehended in creature.” (Ibid. I: 451B) Eriugena makes it clear that

from the existence of creature what can be discovered about Divine Essence is only

71

See Deirdre Carabine, The Unknown God: Negative Theology in the Platonic Tradition: Plato to

Eriugena (Louvain: Peeters Press, 1994), 304-305.

Page 58: 988S

45

“that it is” not “what it is.” (Ibid. I: 455B) Fortunately, a few facts about Divine nature

can be deduced from the nature of what exists.

Facts about CreatureFacts about CreatureFacts about CreatureFacts about Creature Facts deducible about GodFacts deducible about GodFacts deducible about GodFacts deducible about God

EssenceEssenceEssenceEssence: That the creatures exist EssenceEssenceEssenceEssence: That Divine Essence is

OrderOrderOrderOrder: That these are divided into essences,

genera, species and individuals

WisdomWisdomWisdomWisdom: That it is Wise

MotionMotionMotionMotion: That all things have stable motion

and moving rest

LifeLifeLifeLife: That It lives

While being manifest in His creatures, God remains incomprehensible at the

same time and this incomprehensibility is not the same as that of his essence as

contrasted to its manifestation rather it is His incomprehensibility in His very

manifestation. Eriugena says:

“For just as God as He is in Himself beyond every creature is comprehended by

no intellect, so is He equally incomprehensible when considered in the

innermost depths of the creature which was made by Him and which exists in

Him.” (Ibid. I: 443B)

This two-sidedness is in fact involved in the very logic of principle-manifestation

metaphysics, as is made beautifully clear by Schuon:

[T]here is always a certain element of inversion in the relationship between

subject and object, that is, the subject which reflects inverts the object reflected.

A tree reflected in water is inverted, and so is “false” in relation to the real tree,

but it is still a tree — even “this” tree — and never anything else: consequently

the reflected tree is perfectly “true,” despite its illusory character.72

72

Frithjof Schuon, “Orthodoxy and Intellectuality” in Stations of Wisdom (Lahore: Suhail Academy,

2001), 22.

Page 59: 988S

46

As Deirdre Carabine has summed up Eriugena’s views in this connection, “the

reality of the Divine nature is that it both can and cannot be understood when

contemplated in its effects.”73 According to her, the whole focus of Eriugena’s thought

can be stated in terms of the Dionysian problematic of how God is understood to be

transcendent and immanent, similar and different, hidden and revealed.74 In Eriugena’s

words, “nothing is more hidden than it (i.e. Divine essence), nothing more present,

difficult as to where it is, more difficult as to where it is not.” (DDN III: 668C)

3.3.23.3.23.3.23.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on DivineDivineDivineDivine KnowabilityKnowabilityKnowabilityKnowability

Ibn ‘Arabi> says that that “Engendered existence has no connection whatever to

knowledge of the Essence.” (Ibid. II: 597; trans. SPK, 60) He also presents a poly-

syllogistic reductio of the knowability of Divine Essence:

Were it known It would be encompassed. Were It encompassed it would be

limited. Were it limited It would be confined. Were It confined, It would be

owned. But the Essence of the Real is High above all this. (Fut. I: 160; tans.

SPK, 62)

However this is incomplete story. The absolutely incomprehensible Divine

essence manifests itself first in Divine names, attributes and then in Divine actions in

the forms of the cosmos, and it is through these theophanies that certain things can be

known about God. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine of Divine names bestows some clarity upon the

mode in which the essence manifests itself, so here the position is more systematic and

less ambiguous than Eriugena’s “wondrous mode” (mirabilis modo): All the cosmos is a

word that has come with a meaning, and its meaning is God, so that He may make His

properties manifest within it” (Ibid. III: 148; trans. SDG, 5)

73

Deirdre Carabine¸ John Scotus Eriugena, 46. 74 Carabine, The Unknown God, 306.

Page 60: 988S

47

The last sentence points out that the Divine names are transitive in nature, they

logically demand their objects, in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s terminology “loci of manifestation.”

For instance one of the Divine names is “All-Merciful” which demands an object (مظاھر)

of Divine mercy and obviously this has to be something other than God because he

cannot become object of his own mercy, hence the cosmos is created as locus of

manifestation of the Divine mercy.75 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of Divine names as

constituting an intermediary realm between Essence and cosmos can be considered an

important unpacking of what Eriugena calls the “wondrous fashion” in which Essence

manifests itself.

Now Ibn ‘Arabi> explains the epistemological function of theophanic cosmos

within the framework of the Qur’a>nic concept of the signs of God within our souls and

upon the horizons and declares that these constitute the only path to the knowledge of

God: “Hence the Real turned us over to the horizons, which is everything outside of us,

and to ourselves, which is everything we are upon and in. When we come to understand

these two affairs together, we come to know Him.” (Ibid. II. 298; trans. SDG, 8)

It must be remembered that the transcendence and unknowability of the Divine

Essence is not compromised by Divine self-disclosure (theophania) within the souls and

the cosmos but is only complemented. This is again something upon which we find

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> in perfect agreement. Eriugena has written, “The ineffable

excellence of the former (i.e. Divine Essence) surpasses (superat) every nature which

participates in it, so that in all things nothing else but itself is presented to those who

have understanding, while in itself… it is not manifest in any fashion.” (DDN I: 450B)

Ibn ‘Arabi> is more emphatic as he thinks that it is as if God is saying, “I did not bring

75

For an excellent elaboration of this doctrine see Fut. I: 322 and III: 316.

Page 61: 988S

48

the cosmos into existence to signify Me … The cosmos is a mark of the realities of the

names, not of Me.” (Fut. II: 541; trans. SDG, 11) This reminds one of Eriugena’s

distinction between knowing “what He is” and “that He is.”

If for Eriugena the unknowability of Essence was a repercussion of one his

modes being and not-being, for Ibn ‘Arabi> ultimate non-manifestation of Divine essence

is implied by his parallel to Eriugena’s sixth mode of being.76Since being exclusively

belongs to God there is no possible subject for having knowledge of God: “The Real

says, “There is no thing to which I manifest Myself, because I am identical with each

thing.” (Fut. IV: 8)

Ibn ‘Arabi> believes, like Eriugena and St. Gregory of Nyssa before him (DDN III:

637C), that God is the coincidence of the opposites (coincidentia oppositorum) and one

of his favorite examples to illustrate this is the Qur’a>nic pair of Divine names

“Manifest-Nonmanifest” (الظاھر والباطن) (Qur’a>n, 54:2). He thinks that God is Manifest

to Himself and Nonmanifest with respect to His creatures. (Fut. IV: 326; trans. SDG,

206)

Hence, Divine Essence is unknowable in itself, manifests itself and remains

unknowable even in its manifestation. Thus we are taught both by Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi>.

76

He writes in a short poem that inaugurates chapter 402 of Fut.:

Were we to become manifest to the thing,

It would be other than We

But there is no “other than We”

So where is manifestation?

أين الظھور،لو ظھرنا للشئي كان سوانا و سوانا ما ثم Ibid. IV: 8; trans. SDG, 41.

Page 62: 988S

49

3.43.43.43.4 DivineDivineDivineDivine Unity and TrinityUnity and TrinityUnity and TrinityUnity and Trinity

3.4.13.4.13.4.13.4.1 Eriugena on TrinityEriugena on TrinityEriugena on TrinityEriugena on Trinity

In the account of Trinity in the first book of De Diuisione Naturae Eriugena takes his

position appealing to the authority of Dionysius and Gregory Nazianzus. He appeals to

former to warn the readers that in view of its absolute transcendence, the Divine essence

cannot be described either by unity or by trinity and adds that the triune nature of God

was “discovered only in the light of spiritual understanding and rational investigation”

so that “the religious inclinations of pious minds may have something to think and

something to say concerning that which is ineffable and incomprehensible.” (DDN I:

456 A-B) Perhaps it was this statement that has led some scholars to maintain that for

Eriugena the Trinity has merely “a subjective-meaning” and “merely in human

consciousness.”77

There is one point where Eriugena’s understanding of Trinity seems to differ

from that of Pseudo Dionysius. Eriugena connects the three known facts about God

namely essence, wisdom and life to His triune nature and maintains that by “God” “in

its essence is understood the Father, in its wisdom the Son, in its life the Holy Ghost.”

(Ibid. I: 455C)

Referring to Gregory Nazianzus as his authority, Eriugena presents a relational

concept of Divine trinity according to which the relation or condition (habitum) of the

Unbegotten Substance to the begotten substance was called Father, the condition of

Proceeding Substance to the Unbegotten and to the Begotten Substance Holy Spirit.

77

F.C Baur. and Th. Christlieb held these positions while L. Scheffczyk and Beierwaltes have disagreed.

See Beierwaltes, “Unity and Trinity in Dionysius and Eriugena,” in Hermathena: Proceedings of the

Dublin Conference on Neoplatonism, 1992, (Dublin: University of Dublin, 1994), 10, 17 notes 46-47.

Page 63: 988S

50

(DDN, I. 456 B-C.)78 Justifying the Gregorian position Eriugena makes the following

remark: “For in one and the same nature, there cannot be two names, differing the one

from the other.”(Ibid. I: 457A) As against this principle, the Alumnus points out the

counter example of the names “Abraham” and “Isaac”, which though “differing in sound

but not in sense” are both names of the same nature which is there in the father and his

son. (See ibid. I: 457B) Eriugena denies this by maintaining that the meaning of

“Abraham” is different from “Father” and the meaning of “Isaac” is different from

“son.” Hence, the names Abraham and Isaac refer to the individual substances while the

names “father” and “son” refer not to substances but to relations. (See ibid. I: 457B-C)

The conclusion, as stated by the Alumnus, is that “whether in the Divine Nature or the

human, the name of a relation cannot be applied to a substance or essence.” (Ibid. I:

457D) Anyway, Eriugena’s statement that God transcends both Unity and Trinity is

perfectly in line with his negative theology to be discussed more fully below, according

to which no positive descriptions by way of names and attributes can apply to God who

is beyond them and this concept as we shall show after comparison with Ibn ‘Arabi> goes

a long way towards bridging the Muslim and Christian theologies otherwise radically

separated due to the doctrine of Trinity. Same can be said about his relationalist or non-

substantialist remarks on the meaning of “Father” and “Son” in the Trinity.

3.4.23.4.23.4.23.4.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Views on Trinity Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Views on Trinity Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Views on Trinity Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Views on Trinity

Let us now turn to Ibn ‘Arabi> and attempt to find out what implications the doctrine of

Trinity has for our comparative study of Eriugena with Ibn ‘Arabi> as the latter belongs

to a religious background which does not accept this doctrine but is based upon the

78

St. Gregory had said, in his reply to the Eunomians, regarding whether the name “Father” signified a

nature or a function, that it signified neither of these but rather “the relation of the Son.”

Page 64: 988S

51

doctrine of pure oneness of God. We shall take up this issue at two levels, firstly on

theological or religious level where the Christian Trinity itself is discussed, secondly on

the metaphysical level where instead of trinity we discuss the issue in terms of

multiplicity.

Although a univeralist in his approach towards religious diversity, 79 Ibn ‘Arabi>

does not usually deal with particular dogmas of other religions. There are, however,

some exceptions and the doctrine of Holy Trinity seems to be one of these as Ibn ‘Arabi>

has applied his pluralistic principles to this particular case.

The triadic systematization is one of the structural principles of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

thought just as it is of Eriugena’s.80 This is obvious from his reflections upon the triadic

structure of the letters of the Basmalah, (Fut. I: 103)81 three presence of three Divine

names in it (Ibid. III: 126), the triadic appearance in the first sight of Ka‘bah (Ibid. I:

696)82, triadic nature of reality behind three names of the Qur’a>n, (Ibid. III: 129)

dependence of creation upon the number three which Ibn ‘Arabi> considers to be the first

compound number,83 three dimensional nature of bodies and the bestowal of existence

79

An excellent study of this aspect of Ibn ‘Arabi> is William Chittick’s Imaginal Worlds referred to above.

The work of Frithjof Schuon, especially his Transcendent Unity of Religions can be taken as a

contemporary and practical application of principles propounded by Ibn ‘Arabi>. 80

This feature of Eriugena’s thought has been pointed out by Werner Beierwaltes, “Unity and Trinity,” 6. 81

“[E]very letter of the Basmalah is triadic corresponding to the levels of the worlds.” Also see Ibn

‘Arabi>, Fus}u>s} al-H}ikam, 115-117: “The origin of the cosmos is trinity.” 82 At Fut. IV: 32 Ibn ‘Arabi> writes that the actual structure of Ka‘bah including حجر is itself triadic, the

cube emerges only if we consider the building as it stands presently. 83

“The first of numbers is ‘two’ and nothing at all comes forth from two unless the three conjugates them

and connects them with each other and that (third) brings them together, only then comes forth from them

whatever comes forth from them. … ‘Three’ is the first of odd numbers, from this name (الفرد the odd)

became manifest whatever has become manifest from amongst the entities of the possibles. No possible

thing has become existent from the one but has become existent from plural and the smallest compound

number is three and it is the odd.” Fut. III: 126.

Page 65: 988S

52

through three realities namely His He-ness (ھويّة), attentiveness (tawwajjuh) and word84,

to the triadic nature of rational arguments and repercussions for knowing God. (Fut. IV:

32)

Ibn ‘Arabi> is perhaps the only Muslim mystic-philosopher to have given Trinity

such a sympathetic treatment.85 One might become astonished at this but there is

nothing to warrant the conclusion that “he borrowed Trinity from Christianity” 86 to

weld it with his mystical doctrines, since he knew that patches from Christianity were

not going to help legitimize his views. This is moreover the case since Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

apparent source regarding trinity is the Qur’ān and Arabic language and he does not

refer to any Christian authority.

Anyway, Ibn ‘Arabi> attempts to analyze the aspects of truth and falsehood in

this doctrine and finds excuses for its upholders, even ways of ultimate salvation. The

springboard for his discussion of the Christian doctrine of Trinity is Qur’ān 5:73: “They

are unbelievers (لقد كفر) who say ‘God is the third of the three.’” The first important

move Ibn ‘Arabi> makes in his interpretation of this verse is emphasizing that the label

that the Qur’ān is applying to the Trinitarians, namely unbelievers (كافرون) and not the 84

Ibid. III: 276. Chittick explains “He-ness:” “It is God in as much as He is designated by the name ‘He’

.which is a pronoun designating absence and therefore nonmanifestation.” SPK, 964 note 15 ,(ھو)85

Frithjof Schuon, whose work can be considered an extension of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s in many respects, has

explained the Qur’ānic opposition to Christian trinity by bringing to light various shades of its meaning.

He envisages trinity according to a “vertical” perspective or according to either of two “horizontal”

perspectives, the former of them being supreme and the other not. The “vertical” perspective—Beyond-

Being, Being and Existence, the supreme horizontal perspective corresponds to the Vedantic triad Sat,

Chit and Ānanda, the non-supreme horizontal perspective is ontological and represents the three

fundamental aspects or modes of Pure Being, whence the triad: Being, Wisdom, Will (Father, Son,

Spirit). According to Schuon what is opposed to Islam is solely the ontological Trinity alone, as it is

envisaged exoterically. See his Understanding Islam (Lahore: Suhail Academy, 1999), 54. 86

This rather hasty conclusion is drawn by A.E. ‘Affi>fi> in his commentary on Fus}u>s}. See his comments,

132-133.

Page 66: 988S

53

polytheists (مشركون) (See Fut. III: 126), who according to it deserve eternal damnation

in hell. Second, he interprets the word كافر literally as meaning “the one who covers” so

the Trinitarians are so since they cover the first with the second and the second with the

third. Third, he points out that something is wrong with the expression “He is third of

three” “Rather it is said that He is “the third of two…” After all He is not of the same

kind as that to which He is being ascribed in any sense for nothing is as His likeness and

He is the Hearing, the Seeing (42:11). (Fut. IV: 306; trans., SDG, 179) So what is

problematic is God’s inclusion with a group as one of its members. This last remark is

not very different from orthodox Muslim theological stance and Ibn ‘Arabi> considers

this specific formulation of Trinity a violation of Divine transcendence.

The most explicit defense of trinity Ibn ‘Arabi> presents is in its connection with

his discussion of kinds of tawh}i>d. The profession of three gods, according to Ibn ‘Arabi>,

is clearly an instance of polytheism but he does not equate trinity with polytheism.

(Ibid. III: 126) According to him, it is rather another kind of tawh}i>d, namely the

“oneness of composition.” (Ibid. III: 173)

While committing trinity to the profession of oneness of composition and

presence of oddness and thereby making room for it, Ibn ‘Arabi>> has in the corner of his

mind the Divine saying: “He is odd and He loves the odd.”87 Accordingly the profession

of oneness is also of two kinds or in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s terminology, belong to either of two

presences: the presence of oneness (حضرة الوحدانية) and the presence of oddness ( حضرة

That is to say that there are two possible ways to profess Divine oneness, pure .(الفردانية

oneness and composed oneness. The Muslim tawh}i>d, so to speak, belongs to the former

one, while the Christian Trinity belongs to the latter. Even though the latter is not the

87

Muslim, S}ah}i>h}, Kita>b al-Dhikr wa al-Du‘a>’: Ba>b fi> Asma> Alla>h.

Page 67: 988S

54

pure oneness, it is still a profession of oneness, since the number three is the first odd

number (See Fut. IV: 32), a believer in Trinity has still the advantage of deviating only

one degree from pure oneness. Anyway this explanation does not exhaust the meaning

of توحيدالفردية. In one of his shorter treatises Ibn ‘Arabi> goes to the extent of identifying it

as the tawh}i>d of Moses, Muh}ammad and all the prophets while calling the other tawh}i>d

that of the disobedient followers of Muslim community.88

It is necessary to have a look at how Ibn ‘Arabi> views multiplicity and unity as

far as the nature of God is concerned because this is one of the core issues in the

Muslim-Christian discussion of unity and trinity. There is no doubt that the cornerstone

of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought is the Islamic doctrine of oneness of God (توحيد). His doctrine

that has become famous as “oneness of being” ((((وحدة الوجود) is but a mystical version or

the esoteric core of this same doctrine. A unique feature of Ibn ‘Arabi> is that instead of

considering multiplicity an illusion he relates it to the Divine reality. His guiding

metaphysical principle is that “nothing appears in existence that does not have a root in

the Divine reality.” (Ibid. II: 508) Since multiplicity is a feature of existence as it

appears to us it must also have a Divine root.

According to the first principle of Islam, God is one. Ibn ‘Arabi> takes the very

bold step of adding that God is One/Many (الواحد الكثير).89 He applies this term in the

framework of Essence-Attributes discourse. Essentially, God is one but He has many

88

See Ibn ‘Arabi>, Al-Tadbi>ra>t al-ila>hiyyah fi> Is}la>h} al-Mamlakah al-Insa>niyyah (Beirut: Da>r al-Kutub al-

‘Ilmiyyah, 2003), 90. Some other Sufis, before and after Ibn ‘Arabi>, also consider this as the higher level

of tawh}i>d. See Abu> Ha>mid Al-Ghaza>li, Mishka>t al-Anwa>r, Ed. Abul ‘Ala>’ al-‘Affi>fi> (Cairo: Al-Da>r al-

Qayyu>miyyah, 1964), 60 and Mah}mu>d al-Farka>wi>, Sharh} Mana>zil al-Sa>’iri>n (Cairo: Ma‘had al-‘ilmi> al-

faransi> li al-a>tha>r al-Sharqiyyah, 1953), 36. 89

Ibn ‘Arabi> applies this term in other contexts as well. In Fus}u>s}, he seems to be applying this term to

anything having organic unity like one person having many bodily organs. He also applies it to the world

as a whole and then to God in view of the endless multiplicity of His theophanies. See Fus}. 183-184.

Page 68: 988S

55

names and these names require the objects in which their properties or meanings should

be manifested, hence, the plurality of created objects. “There is nothing but Allah, the

necessary of existence, the one in as much as His Essence, the Many in as much as His

names and His rulings.” (Fut. I: 703) Still, these names are not substances, but only

relations between God and the world. Therefore the entities of the created nature do not

multiply the Divine Essence, so we must not say that He is one or many but that He is

One/many. (Ibid. III: 276)

In order to separate the Divine essence from this attribution of relational

multiplicity Ibn ‘Arabi> at one place equates One/many to Manifest/non-manifest ( الظاھر

This shows again that multiplicity pertains to God inasmuch as He manifest .(والباطن

Himself and not as He remains Non-Manifest. Hence multiplicity belongs to the

names/attributes aspect of the Divine Side (الجانب ا8لھي). ). ). ).

This discussion gives us at least two features of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought that he

shares with Eriugena. Apart from the correspondence of the term one-many to

Eriugena’s unum multiplex, utilizing the essence-attributes apparatus also brings

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> interestingly close. Eriugena’s identification of the three

persons of trinity as essence, life and wisdom has already been given by Wolfson an

important place in the discussion of trinity as origin of Muslim doctrine of attributes.90

In his discussion of trinity or multiplicity Ibn ‘Arabi> does not refer normally to life and

wisdom because these are intransitive so do not require objects, which makes them

irrelevant from the point of view of cosmogony. Although this particular feature moves

him a bit away from Eriugena it brings him close to the latter in another regard. From

the historical point of view, like that in which Wolfson is discussing the subject in this

90

Philosophy of Kalam, 123.

Page 69: 988S

56

particular place, the former fact will seem more serious, since it would emphasize the

difference between them, while the latter fact from the thematic-analytical standpoint

that we have taken here, bridges such gap. This is because even if the attributes

mentioned by Ibn ‘Arabi> are not exactly like the members of Eriugenian, or for that

matter, of previous Platonic triads, they still are attributes. Moreover, Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

reference to the transitive attributes, unlike those mentioned by Eriugena, allows him to

introduce the concept of relation. We have seen above that Eriugena followed the Greek

fathers and presented a relational concept of the three persons of trinity. We see

presently that Ibn ‘Arabi> emphasizes time and again the relational nature of Divine

attributes and Divine names, the seedbed of multiplicity in the Divine presence and in

the world, and he does this apparently to forestall reified Divine multiplicity.

Though it is difficult to say that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s interpretation of trinity would be

acceptable to the Christian authorities, however, as far as the Muslim-Christian debate

on Trinity is concerned, there is no doubt that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s position is a breakthrough.91

3.53.53.53.5 Affirmative, Negative and Superlative TheologiesAffirmative, Negative and Superlative TheologiesAffirmative, Negative and Superlative TheologiesAffirmative, Negative and Superlative Theologies

3.5.13.5.13.5.13.5.1 Apophasis in Eriugena Apophasis in Eriugena Apophasis in Eriugena Apophasis in Eriugena

One of the major issues that Eriugena discusses in Book I of De Diuisione Naturae is

that of the applicability of Categoriae Decem to God. Eriugena believes that this

question can be discussed in terms of two theologies, that is, ways of talking about

God:92 the negative theology, via negativa (apophasis) and affirmative theology, via

91

That this indeed is the case can be seen by placing it in the debate from Mu‘tazilites through Al-Kindi>,

a debate which has been presented and studied by Wolfson. Cf. Philosophy of Kalam, Chapter IV: II-III,

310-337. 92

On the place of this discussion and the meaning of term “theology” by Eriugena see Bernard J. McGinn,

“Negative Theology in John the Scot,” in Studia Patristica: Papers Presented to the Sixth International

Page 70: 988S

57

affirmativa (cataphasis). Though Eriugena takes this from Pseudo-Dionysius,93 he also

names Boethius and Augustine among those who alluded to the negative theology. Still

Eriugena is believed to be the first Latin theologian to have made it a systematic part of

his thought.94 Negative theology is defined as denying that the Divine Essence is any of

the things that are. Eriugena, after briefly presenting how Pseudo-Dionysius has

emphasized Divine transcendence, says that “Nothing can be said properly about God,

since He surpasses every intellect and all sensible and intelligible meanings, who is

better known by not knowing Him” (DDN I: 510C-D)

Affirmative theology is defined as that which predicates all the things that are,

of the Divine Essence or Substance. It does not say that It is those things but that “all

things take their being from it.” (Ibid. I: 458B)95 According to this way the Divine

Essence can be said to be not only those things “which accord with nature” like truth,

goodness, essence, light, justice, sun, star, spirit, water, lion, bear and worm but also the

things which are contrary to nature, like being drunken and mad. (See ibid.)96 Obviously

the reason for the viability of this continuity is everything’s “taking being from God.”

Eriugena makes this explicit by providing the principle: “that which is the cause can be

expressed in terms of the things that are caused,” the same principle using which he

reduces the last two divisions of nature to the first and second. He writes, “all things

Conference on Patristic Studies, XIII (1975), 234-235. 93

See Pseudo Dionysius, The Mystical Theology, in Pseudo-Dionysius: Complete Works, (Mahwah:

Paulist Press, 1987), Chapter III: 1032D-1033D. 94

See Bernard McGinn, “Negative Theology,” 237. 95

Here the connection of God-world identity with the causality is obvious. In case of Ibn ‘Arabi> this was

not so clear, so it fell upon the shoulders of his defenders to point this out. 96

At 511C-512B, Eriugena gives a more extensive list of names dividing them into “glorious and exalted

names such as life or Virtue, intermediate names such as Sun and Light, those taken from lower motions

of the visible creature like breath and Cloud and lastly those which are taken from the created nature and

applied to creative nature by a kind of metaphor like man, lion, ox etc.”

Page 71: 988S

58

that are, from the highest to the lowest, can be spoken of Him…since He is the source of

all things that can be predicated of Him.” (Ibid. I: 510D) Following Saint Augustine,

Eriugena maintains that positive Divine names used in the Scripture signify the simple

and immutable Divine essence and there is no difference, as far as God is concerned,

between loving, desiring and willing etc. (Ibid. I: 518 B-C) Names like Truth, Goodness,

Essence, Light, Justice and others of the sort are said to apply to Him metaphorically,

“that is to have been transferred from creatures to the Creator.” (Ibid. I: 458C)97

To show the inadequacy of affirmative theology Eriugena appeals to the

principle that “anything which has an opposite cannot properly be predicated to God,”

and argues that all the aforesaid Divine names are confronted by other names (e.g. being

by non-being and life by death) therefore they cannot be properly predicated of God.

(Ibid. I: 459 B-C)

In view of this, properly speaking, God is neither Essence nor Goodness, nor

God,98 nor Truth, Life and Light but superessential, more-than-Goodness, more-than-

God, more-than-Truth, more-than-Life and more than-Light. The Divine names included

in this third group, called super-affirmation or hyperphatic theology,99 harmonize via

affirmativa and via negativa as “in outward expression they possess the form of the

affirmative, but in meaning the force of the negative… it is essence, affirmation; it is

non-essence, negation; it is superessential, affirmation and negation together.” (Ibid. I:

97 It seems that Ibn ‘Arabi> would not have agreed to this transference because for him such names

properly apply only to God while they apply to creatures metaphorically. This seeming difference can be

reconciled if we differentiate between the ontological and epistemological contexts of religious language

and hold that Eriugena has in view the epistemic context while Ibn ‘Arabi> speaks in the ontological

context. 98 Eriugena denies the proper applicability of “God” to Divine substance in view of Greek etymology of

the word. Hence God is more-than-seeing and more -than- running. 99

Carabine, The Unknown God, 312.

Page 72: 988S

59

562C) In the final analysis however, this third way remains fully negative way since it

only tells us that God is not essences but it does not reveal “what that is which is more

than essence” (Ibid. I: 562D)

Bernard McGinn believes that it is only in these lines that an answer worthy of

the name is given to the question asked many passages ago by the Alumnus about

proper predication of these terms to God. The answer is, yes and no, depending on the

type of definition one believes to be involved in by these terms. If they provide a

diffinitio quid est, that is “what it is” then, no, since such a definition is a limitation,

inconceivable in case of God. But if the definition involved is only diffinitio quia est

that is of “that it is” then yes these terms are properly applied to God.100 Interestingly,

Ibn ‘Arabi> also denies the possibility of such definition of God in view of its limiting

character. However, according to him, separately taken both affirmative and negative

ways imply a limitation of Divine Substance. One gets rid of this delimitation only by

synthesizing both ways. (See Fus}, 68-69)

Eriugena’s final position on this issue, on the one hand, at least apparently, is

Affirmatio simul et abdicatio, the combination of two ways (with a tilt towards the

second). That is the final message of Eriugena on the issue of religious language and

also, as we shall see in a later chapter, on the question of God-world identity. It is the

negative way that he considers to be the better expression of truth of the matter. For he

says that God is “more truly and faithfully denied in all things than He is affirmed,”

“For whatever negation you make about Him will be a true negation, but not every

affirmation that you make will be a true affirmation.” (Ibid. I: 510C) There is also the

suggestion that the affirmative way is for the simple-minded followers of the religion

100

See McGinn, Negative Theology, 237. McGinn has also observed the close connection between this

question and that of the nature of definition.

Page 73: 988S

60

(“those who are as yet ignorant in the simplicity of the teaching of their faith”) while

the negative way belongs to the more advanced. (Ibid. I: 511C) Still, there are ways in

which the whole negative enterprise can be rendered in positive terms. One of these is

discovered when one looks at Eriugena’s adherence to the Augustinian dictum that God

is better known by not knowing (melius nesciendo scitur). Second, in Eriugena’s

explanation of final theophany Divine essence is described as in assessable light which

blinds the eye and is thus called darkness. Here, as Dierdre Carabine has pointed out “we

find the notion of negation and deprivation linked to the positive idea of plenitude.”101

Hence affirmation points beyond itself to negation and negation, in turn, back to

affirmation. This reflects the dialectic of transcendence and immanence Michael Sells

speaks about as “an open ended process by which the original assertion of transcendence

looks critically upon itself.”102 It reiterates the metaphysical principle, which finds

expression in almost all traditions: “transcendence necessarily comprises immanence,

and immanence just as necessarily comprises transcendence.”103

3.5.23.5.23.5.23.5.2 Incomparability, Similarity and their synthesis in Ibn ‘Arabi>:Incomparability, Similarity and their synthesis in Ibn ‘Arabi>:Incomparability, Similarity and their synthesis in Ibn ‘Arabi>:Incomparability, Similarity and their synthesis in Ibn ‘Arabi>:

In Ibn ‘Arabī’s concepts of incomparability (تنزيه), similarity (تشبيه) and synthesis of both

we have parallels of what Eriugena calls negative, affirmative and superlative ways of

speaking about God. Whereas Eriugena introduces these concepts while treating the 101

Carabine, The Unknown God, 320. Emphasis added. Carabine locates the metaphysical foundation of

the application of both theologies, positive and negative, in the Plotinian dictum “the One is all and no

thing.” See ibid. 324. 102

Mystical Languages of Unsaying, 207 103

Frithjof Schuon, “The Way of Oneness,” in Esoterism as Principle and As Way (Lahore, Suhail

Academy, 2005), 236 and in his “Our Father Who art in Heaven,” in To Have a Centre (Bloomington:

World Wisdom Books, 1990) 127, Schuon says that there is no transcendence without immanence and no

immanence without transcendence which in one way is reminiscent of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s saying, “The assertion

of similarity is not capable of escaping the assertion of incomparability, nor is the assertion of

incomparability capable of escaping the assertion of similarity.” Fus}, 182 trans. Ringstones, 229.

Page 74: 988S

61

question of applicability of categories to God, behind Ibn ‘Arabi>’s use of these terms

stand pre-Mu‘tazilite positions of anthropomorphists (مشبھة) who favored Qur’a>nic

verses ascribing human attributes to God and the early Muslims (السلف) who preferred

verses which emphasize Divine incomparability, as Ibn Khaldūn describes the origin of

Islamic Theology. A third position seeking to harmonize the previous two positions by

interpreting the verses conveying the message of similarity. This third position,

examplified by the saying that God is “a body unlike bodies” is only superficially similar

to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s synthesis as will be obvious from what follows.

Incomparability and similarity are two relationships as possessing which human

beings witness the Real. (Fut. II: 3. SPK, 277) Incomparability (تنزيه) having negative

formal character is the exact parallel of Eriugena’s negative theology since it is “to

describe the Real as having no connection with the attributes of temporally originated

things (المحدثات).” (Ibid. II. 672; trans. SPK, 70) The Qur’a>nic concept of تسبيح i.e.

Glorification is understood by Ibn ‘Arabi> as referring to a declaration of incomparability

and praising God not with positive attributes (Ibid. III: 148; trans. Ibid) 104 in the light of

the Qur’an> 37:180 viz. “Lord of inaccessibility above what they describe” (37:180)

(Ibid. II. 580; trans. SPK, 71) These words were ordinarily interpreted as meaning that

God is free of attributes that are not proper to Him. However Ibn ‘Arabi>’s explication of

tanzi>h goes well beyond this traditional interpretation. In accordance with his broader

concept of it, tanzi>h would demand not attributing to God anything that can also be

attributed to anyone. At one place Ibn ‘Arabi> goes to the extent of claiming that even

104 Ibn Khaldu>n points out that in view of fact that all Qur’a>nic verses speaking about incomparability are

negative in form early Muslims preferred them over the positive anthropomorphic ones. Ibn Khaldu>n, The

Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History, trans. Franz Rosenthal (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,

1986), III: 45.

Page 75: 988S

62

the Divine names given by scripture cannot be considered to be ascribable properly since

they are ascribable to human beings. (Ibid)

The only laudation worthy of God, according to this perspective, then, is his

Glorification, which is as we have seen negative and not positive.

Ibn ‘Arabi> very clearly sees that the doctrine of similarity lies at the very heart

of incomparability attesting thus to the principle that immanence and transcendence are

interdependent. Whereas Eriugena thought that describing God by positive terms would

amount to limiting him, Ibn ‘Arabi> takes the further step of declaring that not only

positive but negative attribution also amounts to the same thing. He expresses this idea

by saying that “God possesses non-delimited being, but no delimitation (تقييد) prevents

Him from delimitation.” (Fut. III: 162)

Consequently Ibn ‘Arabi> declares that neither of these two points of view

presents complete picture of Divine reality therefore these two must be combined. Ibn

‘Arabi> asserts that “Whoever in knowing Him brings together the assertion of

incomparability and that of similarity…knows Him. (Fus}, 68-69; trans. Ringstones, 37-

38) This combination of incomparability and similarity, which is a requirement of

Divine perfection, Ibn ‘Arabi> reads in the words of the Scripture, “There is nothing like

unto Him and He is the Hearing, the Seeing” (42:11). According to Ibn ‘Arabi>, “there is

nothing like unto Him” points to incomparability while the words “He is the Hearing,

the Seeing” point toward similarity. Ibn ‘Arabi> always mentions these Qur’a>nic words

as the combination in one place of incomparability and similarity, although he does not

rule out other ways for understanding these words.

We submit that this synthesis of the formally negative incomparability and

formally affirmative similarity in Ibn ‘Arabi> is comparable to Eriugena’s superlative

Page 76: 988S

63

theology, which combines both by lacking negation in form but being fully negative in

meaning. (DDN I: 462C) However there is one important difference between the two

syntheses which must not be lost sight of but explained. We noticed at closing the

discussion of Eriugena’s superlative theology that he tilts finally towards negative

theology, even though seeking to combine it with affirmative. In case of Ibn ‘Arabi> one

finds an obvious tilt towards the affirmative theology based on the perspective of

similarity. This was most evident from his words quoted above about non-delimitation

being delimitation as far as the Absolute is concerned. This difference in orientation of

the apo-cataphatic synthesis presented by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> stands in need of

explanation.

We submit that this difference can be explained with reference to the religious

traditional background against which the syntheses were presented by Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi>. In regard to their views on immanence and transcendence Christianity and Islam

belong to different religious types according to Frithjof Schuon. In Schuon’s view there

are two ways of approaching the Absolute, the one is founded upon the notion of “God

as such” while the other is based on “God become man.” Christianity belongs to the

latter type while the former is represented by Islam, 105 which “brought God back, so to

speak, to His primary meaning and to His transcendent essentiality.”106 Thus the

explanation of Eriugena’s final tilt toward apophasis and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s toward cataphasis

lies in the fact that each of the two was responding to the background of his tradition.

Christian tradition titled toward affirmative theology and Islamic tradition, as reaction

to Christian over emphasis, toward negative theology.

105 Schuon, “Outline of Religious Typologies,” in Survey of Metaphysics and Esoterism (Bloomington,

Indiana: World Wisdom Books, 1986), 103. 106

Schuon, “The Mystery of the Hypostatic Face,” in ibid. 95.

Page 77: 988S

64

3.63.63.63.6 The Concept of The Concept of The Concept of The Concept of DivineDivineDivineDivine NothingnessNothingnessNothingnessNothingness

3.6.13.6.13.6.13.6.1 Nihil as a Nihil as a Nihil as a Nihil as a DivineDivineDivineDivine Name in EriugenaName in EriugenaName in EriugenaName in Eriugena

Eriugena considers nihil, not-being, to be one of the names of God. Firstly, this

conclusion is entailed by the very first mode for distinguishing being from non-being. If

one starts from the said mode God must be considered amongst those things which

elude all sense, reason and intellect due to excellence of their essence (per excellentiam

suae naturae), hence represent quia non sunt. Secondly, God can also be said not to be in

view of the second mode for differentiating being from not-being. If creatures,

belonging to the lower order of hierarchy, are said to be, God must be said not to be,

since an affirmation of the lower is negation of the higher. It is obvious that this

attribution of nihil to God is relative and unlike the previous one not a requirement of

Divine transcendence. Hence, there is an opposite side to the mode as well according to

which God is said to be while and when the creatures are said not to be. Thirdly,

Eriugena returns in book three of DDN to give a fuller treatment of the concept of non-

existence. Having contested the identification of “nothing” in the phrase “creation out

of nothingness (creatio ex nihilo)” with privation, Eriugena contends that by nihil is

signified “the ineffable and incomprehensible and inaccessible brilliance of the Divine

Goodness.” (DDN, III 680D) Thus Eriugena believes that ex nihilo actually means ex

deo and thinks that this interpretation is entailed by a true understanding of Scripture.

This Eriugenian view of the nature of nihil is subject matter of the so-called Treatise on

nothingness within DDN (634A-690B).

It would be an injustice and misunderstanding to criticize this identification of

nihil as a Divine name as derogatory to the Divine substance. When we emphasize per

excellentiam suae naturae part of Eriugena’s first mode referred to above, it becomes

Page 78: 988S

65

clear that Eriugena is not employing the term “not-being” in privative sense so as to

imply some imperfection or lack. Rather he is interpreting the phrase in the sense of

“more than being.”107 He writes about the Divine nature that “it does not descend

beyond the lowest effects by which it would be seen both to be created and to create.

(DDN III 689B) Therefore Willemien Otten has rightly remarked that “For God the

denial of being does not entail any consequences that should affect His existence in any

negative way” 108 and that “[t]he predication of non-being appears to be the only

appropriate figure of speech aptly to represent God’s transcendence with regard to

creation without comprehending it. Eriugena manifestly rebuts any other interpretation

of non esse.”109 The point being made here can be better understood in the light of a

distinction made by Frithjof Schuon regarding negation of nihil from God and its

ascription to Him. Like Otten, Schuon has highlighted the etymological ground of the

controversy and pointed out two ways of understanding the word nihil, firstly, according

to its proper meaning it means that which is below existence and secondly the esoteric

interpretation according to which it is that which being principial and hence non-

manifested is “above existence.” 110 It goes without saying that it is not in the former

sense that Eriugena applies this word to God. According to this opinion the difference

about the application of nihil to God is in fact a linguistic one and not metaphysical.

107

See DDN III: 634B-C: “I would not easily concede that the Divine superessentiality was nothing [or

could be called by so privative a name]. For, although it is said by theologians not to be, they do not mean

that it is nothing but that it is more than being.” 108

Willemien Otten, The Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1991), 44. 109

Ibid. 37. 110

Schuon, “Creation as a Divine Quality” in Survey of Metaphysics and Esoterism , 51.

Page 79: 988S

66

This is supported by a noted Eriugena scholar Otten’s opinion that the discussion of

nihil reflects a problem of language.111

3.6.23.6.23.6.23.6.2 God and Nothingness in Ibn ‘Arabi>God and Nothingness in Ibn ‘Arabi>God and Nothingness in Ibn ‘Arabi>God and Nothingness in Ibn ‘Arabi>

Let us turn our attention now to Ibn ‘Arabi>. It would appear from a number of texts in

Ibn “Arabi>’s works that he does not favor attribution of nihil to God. He says, for

example, “since the Real rightfully demands wuju>d by His Essence (لذاته), non existence

is impossible for Him.” (Fut. II: 99) In his Kita>b al-‘Azal Ibn ‘Arabī rejects an opinion

because it implicitly qualifies God with nothingness which “is impossible for Him.”112

He also considers nothingness incompatible with eternity and mentions the principle

“the one whose eternity has been established, his nothingness becomes impossible.”(Fut.

II. 99)113 In addition to eternity, Ibn ‘Arabi> also hesitates in applying nothingness to

God in view of his identifying existence with good and nonexistence with evil (See ibid.

I: 213) and because “God is essentially necessary of existence.”(Fut. III: 477)

However, one should consider the fact that in all these places Ibn ‘Arabi> is

talking about عدمas privation, lack or imperfection while Eriugena attributes it to God

not as lack but as super-abundance or being more than being. Eriugena, on the other

hand, while attributing nihil to God, considers it not as privation or lack but as super-

essentiality, that is to say, more than being. Besides Ibn ‘Arabi> counter-balances the

abovementioned view firstly by providing a perspective from which the chasm

between and God can be abridged and secondly, by making explicit ascription of nihil عدم

111

Otten, Anthropology, 44. Dermot Moran had claimed that Eriugena founded a tradition of negative

ontology which runs parallel to that of the primacy of being. See The Philosophy, 100. 112

Ibn ‘Arabi>, “Kitāb al-Azal” in Rasa>’il (Beirut: Da>r al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyah, 1999), 122. Ibid. II: 384. Also see III: 477 where Ibn ‘Arabi> says that since God is being (من ثبت قدمه إستحال عدمه)113

therefore He is free from non-existence.

Page 80: 988S

67

to God. In one place he seems to be implying that God can be said both to be and not to

be from two different perspectives: “In the same manner He is and is not: He is the

manifest so he is but the distinction among the existents is intelligible and perceived by

the senses because of the diversity of the properties of the entities, so “He is not” (Fut.

II: 160; SPK, 95) In that particular place he is in agreement with Eriugena over the issue

of Divine nothingness.

In the second place, we find Ibn ‘Arabi> explicitly granting the application of

nothingness to God in one passage. Discussing glorification (tasbi>h}) he writes:

Glorification is to assert God’s incomparability [tanzi>h]. It is a description by

non-existence. Hence He made absolute non-existence eminent by describing

Himself by it, for He says Glory be to thy Lord, the Lord of exaltation, above

what they describe (37:180). (Ibid. II: 672; trans. SDG, 31)

In this passage Ibn ‘Arabi> comes closest to Eriugena firstly because of obviously

considering nihil to be a Divine quality, but also the context and rationale is the same.

One of the reasons for Eriugena’s doctrine of Divine nothingness is his negative

theology, emphasis upon apophasis. Ibn ‘Arabi> is also pointing to the Divine

nothingness in the very same context of Divine transcendence or as he calls it, (تنزيه).

The second resonance here is that Ibn ‘Arabi> is grounding his view in his reading of the

Qur’a>n just as Eriugena thinks that his identification of nihil with God is implied by the

Scripture itself. (DDN III: 684C-685A)

A third similarity between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on the point under discussion

becomes manifest by the latter’s remark that “nothing other-than-God makes God

known with greater knowledge than does absolute non-existence.” (Fut. II: 672) Here

the description of nonexistence as being the best signifier or God in a manner

Page 81: 988S

68

reminiscent of Eriugena’s declaration that God is better known through negation than

through affirmation.

Finally, a comparative remark about Eriugena’s identification of Deus with nihil

in the context of creation out of nothingness is in order. Ibn ‘Arabi> shares Eriugena’s

view that creation out of nothingness does not mean creation out of absolute

nothingness and furthermore interprets creation as Divine self-disclosure just as

Eriugena does. Moreover, in the elliptical opening sentence of his Al-Futu>h}a>t (Fut. I:1)

Ibn ‘Arabi> writes: “Praise belongs to Alla>h who created things from non-existence and

its non-existence. (عن عدم و عدمه)” The words ‘an ‘adam wa ‘adamihi” can be interpreted

to mean that God did not create the world out of pure nonexistence but from

nonexistence plus the non-existence of none existence (‘adam wa ‘adam al-‘adam) i.e.

being. And the identification of being with God is one of the axioms of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

thought. All this implies that the world was created out of nothingness plus the

existence that belongs to God.

Anyway, the doctrine of Divine nothingness has some important doctrinal

implications. One of these is that since God is nothing, that is “no-thing,” He does not

know Himself. To a consideration of this we turn now.

3.73.73.73.7 DivineDivineDivineDivine Darkness: Darkness: Darkness: Darkness:

3.7.13.7.13.7.13.7.1 Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on Eriugena on DivineDivineDivineDivine SelfSelfSelfSelf----KnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledge

In our opinion, one of the strangest dimensions of Eriugena’s thought is his denial of

Divine self-knowledge: “So God does not know of Himself what He is because He is not

a ‘what’.” (DDN II: 589B-C)

Page 82: 988S

69

An attempt to make Eriugena’s statement plausible by emphasizing, as Carabine

does, God’s knowledge, in His very ignorance of Himself, that he is not at all any of the

things or that he is more than all things. Such approach would be perfectly in line with

Eriugena’s own argument. What seems problematic, however, in this account is that in

discussing Divine self-knowledge a reference to “things” seems to be a projection of

human point of view upon God. It is human knowledge (or pseudo-knowledge or

whatever) of God that has to depend upon God and God while thinking about His

essence does not have to contrast him with things other than Himself.

At one place in book II Eriugena argues again that God does not know of

Himself what He is. Here the argument presupposes that when we ask regarding the

quiddity of anything we in fact make a demand for its definition, hence to know

something is to define it “in terms of circumstances which circumscribe it, so to speak,

within limits.” (Ibid. II: 586D) From this general observation about human knowledge

Eriugena leaps to Divine Knowledge: “If, then, God knows of himself what He is, doe

He not define Himself? --- for everything which is understood by itself or by another as

to what it is can be defined and therefore is not infinite.” (Ibid. II: 587B)

What we find questionable in this argument is the leap from finite sphere of

human knowledge to the infinite sphere of Divine knowledge and the presupposition

that since our knowledge of what something is amounts to having a definition of it; this

must also be the case with God.114 Where is the argument for this transition? Is not this

a violation of via negativa of which Eriugena is so fond?

114

Augustine says in another context “that which specially leads these men astray to refer their own

circles to the straight path of truth, is, that they measure by their own human, changeable, and narrow

intellect the Divine mind, which is absolutely unchangeable, infinitely capacious, and without succession

of thought, counting all things without number,” The City of God and the Christian Doctrine, ed. Phillip

Page 83: 988S

70

Moreover, if one is really to construe Divine infinity spatially and push it to its

farthest logical limits then the only option is to say nothing at all about God, not even

that He is infinite, unknowable, absolute etc., and there remains no room for talking

about God either in affirmative or negative or superlative manner. We submit that

human beings, since they are finite beings cannot know the Infinite however the Infinite

can know Himself since He does not fall short of His own Infinity, if such way of

expressing the point be permissible.115 The correct entailments of Divine infinity and

simplicity seem to be, not that God does not know what He is, but that the question

whether or not He knows what he is, is misplaced. Divine Simplicity is already

compromised the moment this question is put before giving an affirmative answer to it.

3.7.23.7.23.7.23.7.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> and Ibn ‘Arabi> and Ibn ‘Arabi> and Ibn ‘Arabi> and DivineDivineDivineDivine SelfSelfSelfSelf----KnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledge

As far as Ibn ‘Arabi> is concerned, one of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s most favorite aphorisms,

attributed to al-Ghaza>li> (d. 1111) and Abu> Sa‘i>d al-Kharrāz (d. 890) is: “None knows

God but God.” (e.g. Fut. I: 271; II: 69) Although Ibn ‘Arabi> quotes this mostly in order

to emphasize its negative part regarding unknowability of Divine essence, but the

saying explicitly affirms God’s knowledge of Himself.

He differentiates between knowing quiddity of something and defining

something in his commentary upon an argument that took place between Pharaoh and

Schaff (New York: The Christian Literature Publishing Co., 1890), 238. The City of God also contains a

detailed refutation of the claim that God does not know infinite. See Book XII chapter 18. 115 The concept of Divine infinity has been used by Beierwaltes in a defense of Eriugena’s attempt to see

the self-unfolding of Tri-unity in the light of causality against the objection that it subordinates second

and third persons to the first person who is the cause. Beierwaltes holds: “it (i.e. the principle) sets a

second cause which is begotten but in the infinite realm not less than the first, but indeed necessarily

equal.” Beierwaltes, Unity and Trinity, 11 (emphasis added).

Page 84: 988S

71

the Prophet Moses regarding the nature of God. (See Fus}. 208-209) Toshihiko Izutsu

comments:

Strictly speaking, asking about the ma>hiyyah of something is not exactly the

same as asking for its logical definition. To ask about the ma>hiyyah of a thing,

as understood by Ibn ‘Arabi>, is to ask about the reality of that object which is

unique and not shared by anything else. Definition in the logical sense is

different from this.116

On this account if question about the whatness of definable creatures is not a question

about their definition then the question as to what He is a fortiori is not about His

definition, since He cannot be defined. As Ibn ‘Arabi> has put it succinctly “the

knowledge of the infinite that it is infinite is without encompassing.” 117 Hence on the

question of Divine Self-Knowledge Ibn ‘Arabi>’s standpoint differs from that of

Eriugena.

An alternate interpretation of Eriugena’s position on Divine Darkness can be

made in the light of his saying 1) “Divine Nature… willing to emerge from the most

hidden recesses of its nature in which it is unknown even to itself, it knows itself in

nothing because it is infinite… [ in nullo se cognoscit quia infinita est]. (DDN III.689B)

If we emphasize in nullo instead off quia infinita est we can see the meaning of the

claim that God does not know himself in a new light. The meaning of saying that God

does not know Himself will simply be that there is nothing other than Him in which He

could know Himself. This interpretation fits in nicely with his claim that from His

ineffable nothingness God emerges and knows Himself in theophanies.

116

Toshihiko Izutsu, Sufism and Taoism, 29. 117 Ibn ‘Arabi>, Kita>b al-‘Aba>dilah (Cairo: Maktabat al-Qa>hirah, 1994), 122.

Page 85: 988S

72

The interpretation of Eriugena suggested here bridges the gap between him and

Ibn ‘Arabi>.

Let us conclude by pointing out something upon which Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>

seem to be in complete agreement. This concerns Eriugena’s assertion that God is not a

“what.” We find that Ibn ‘Arabi> negates, unlike other classical Muslim philosophers and

exegetes118, that God could be a called a “thing” since the traditional Islamic sources, in

his opinion do not warrant the application of this name to God. (Fut. II: 99; trans. SPK,

88)

118

Fakhruddi>n al-Ra>zi>, Ibn ‘Arabi>’s famous contemporary theologian, philosopher and exegete, with

whom he also corresponded, takes the position that God can be called a thing since the Qur'a>n says: “Say,

‘what thing is most weighty in evidence?’ Say: “Alla>h, witness between me and you.’” (6:19). He has

mentioned that Jaham ibn Safwan is the only one who denied that God is “thing” and adds that this is just

a verbal disagreement. See al-Tafsi>r al-Kabi>r relevant verses.

Page 86: 988S

FourFourFourFour

MetaMetaMetaMetacosmcosmcosmcosm----II: Causes and Entities II: Causes and Entities II: Causes and Entities II: Causes and Entities According to Saint Augustine119 God did not create the material world directly but

creation took place in two phases. In the first phase the seminal reasons (rationes

seminales) of everything were created simultaneously. These are, to quote Copleston,

“germs of things or invisible powers or potentialities, created by God in the beginning in

the humid element and developing into the objects of various species by their temporal

unfolding.”120 The second phase consisted of successive creation of the effects of those

seminal reasons. Eriugena’s second division of nature termed by him as “primordial

causes” can be seen as continuation of Augustine’s seminal reasons. In Ibn ‘Arabi> we

also find a concept that channels the creation of material world and this is his famous

concept of عيا ن الثابتةEا, variously translated as “fixed entities,”121 “permanent

archetypes”122 or “immutable identities”123 etc. In the present chapter we undertake a

comparative analysis of Eriugena’s primordial causes and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s fixed entities.

The first section deals with the nature, functions and characteristics of primordial causes

in Eriugenian Cosmology while the second section investigates whether or not those

characteristics are shared by Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of fixed entities.

119

Augustine, The Literal Meaning of Genesis, volume I (Mahwah: Paulist Press, 1982) Book V chapters

7, 20 and 23. 120

Frederick Copleston, A History of Western Philosophy, Vol. II Medieval Philosophy, 76. 121

William Chittick in Self Disclosure of God. 122

Toshihiko Izutsu in Sufism and Taoism: A Comparison of Key Philosophical Terms (Berkeley:

University of California Press, 1984). 123

Caner Dagli’s translation in The Ring-stones.

Page 87: 988S

74

4.14.14.14.1 The Nature The Nature The Nature The Nature of Primordial Causes of Primordial Causes of Primordial Causes of Primordial Causes and and and and their their their their Functions in Functions in Functions in Functions in

EriugenianEriugenianEriugenianEriugenian CosmologyCosmologyCosmologyCosmology

4.1.14.1.14.1.14.1.1 Meaning and Scriptural Basis of the Primordial Causes Meaning and Scriptural Basis of the Primordial Causes Meaning and Scriptural Basis of the Primordial Causes Meaning and Scriptural Basis of the Primordial Causes

We have already met with the concept in Book One where Eriugena discusses the modes

of being. We have seen that in accordance with the third mode, “whatever of the

primordial causes through generation is known as to matter and form, as to times and

places is said to be” while “whatsoever is still held in those folds of nature and is not

manifest as to as to form or matter, place or time, and the other accidents,” is said not to

be.124 Hence the primordial causes are the secret folds of nature for things which have

not yet emerged in the spatio-temporal boundaries. Also, they are “the principles of all

things because all things whatsoever that are perceived or understood, whether in the

visible or the invisible creation, subsist by participation in them.” (DDN II: 616B).

Eriugena identifies the primordial causes with a myriad of concepts from traditional

philosophy and his own original ones. These identifications, given below, encapsulate

the nature and function of the primordial causes:

1. He reminds us that they are what the wise men of the Greeks call

prototypa, that is, “the principal exemplars which the Father made in the

Son and divides through the Holy Spirit.”

2. They are also called poorismata or “predestinations” or “predefinitions,”

“for in them whatever is being and has been and shall be made by the

Divine Providence is at one and the same time and immutably

predestined. For nothing naturally arises in the visible and invisible

except what is pre-defined and pre-ordained in them before all times and

places.” As we shall see below, the primordial causes are the connection

between the superessential God and the world. Since “there is not found

124

See supra chapter II, section 2.2.

Page 88: 988S

75

in the nature of things any power, whether general or specific which does

not proceed by an ineffable participation from the primordial causes,”

whatever things are good, alive, wise, true, just, powerful, healthy,

eternal or subsist or understand or practice reason are so and do so by

participation in primordial causes. (See DDN II: 616 C-D)

3. Eriugena identifies them with what the philosophers customarily call

“Divine volitions” (theia thelemata) because everything that God wished

to make He made in them primordially and causally; and things that are

to be have been made in them before all ages.

4. They are what the Greeks call ideas ideae that is the eternal species or

forms and the immutable reasons after which the visible and the invisible

world is formed and governed.125

5. At one place the primordial causes are simply spoken of as the “origins of

things (occasiones rerum)” (See DDN II: 562B) and at another as

primordial essences which were created before all things. (See ibid, II.

528D)

6. In his translations of the works of Pseudo Dionysius Eriugena calls the

primordial causes paradigms (paradigmata). In a long quotation from

Pseudo Dionysius’ De Divina Nominibus given at the very end of DDN II

an explanation of paradigmata can be found: “the reasons in God which

substantiate existing things and were preformed after a unitary mode

which the Divine word calls “predestinations” and “Divine and good

volitions” which determine and make the existents and after the pattern

of which the Superessential has both predestined and brought forth all

things.” (Ibid. II: 619A-620A)126

125 The first four labels are provided in DDN II:529B while their explanation is taken from II. 615D-616B. 126

Pseudo Dionysius also writes that “the Cause of the earth, of it (i.e. the Sun) and of all things

preformed on high in itself the exemplars (paradigmata) of all existents in one superessential unity, and it

then brings forth the essences by an emanation from Essence.” De Divina Nominibus 824C This passage

is quoted by Eriugena at DDN II. 618D-619A.

Page 89: 988S

76

These labels gathered from various places of the second book of DDN give us a fair idea

of what primordial causes are and what function they are meant to play. Their

discussion properly starts at 545B and after another long digression continues from

615D to 618 and then in Book 3 from 619A-630A. Let us turn now to the question of

their scriptural basis.

According to Thomas Duddy Eriugena reveals his Neo-Platonic sympathies

while trying to characterize the second division of nature and he does so by slipping a

Neo-Platonic element into the relationship between creator and creation. The question

of Neo-platonic influence aside, Eriugena attempts to establish himself before anything

else upon the authority of Holy Scripture itself. In the beginning and by way of

preamble the Nutritor says that “the text of present book makes no further demand than

that to the best of our ability we discuss whatever the light of minds shall have granted

concerning the primordial causes” and that “ we take the beginning of our discussion

from the Divine Oracles”, i.e. the Holy Scriptures. (Ibid. II: 545B) The passages that

follow take the opening verses of Genesis as springboard for the introduction of the

primordial causes. Eriugena offers his symbolic commentary on “In the beginning God

made heaven and earth (in principio creavit Deus caelum et terram).” Without naming

or contradicting anyone, he mentions some interpretations of the words “heaven and

earth” mentioned in Genesis I: 1. The first opinion, identified by Sheldon-Williams as

that of Philo and the Alexandrines, is that these two words constitute “a compendious

expression comprehending the whole [perfecte d] creature.” According to this

opinion, by the creation of “heaven” the creation and formation of the whole of spiritual

and intelligible creatures is intended while making of “earth” means “the constitution of

the whole corporeal and sensible creatures.” According to the second opinion, attributed

Page 90: 988S

77

to St. Gregory of Nyssa, what is signified is “the formlessness of each creature, the

inception of the spiritual by the name “heaven” and that of this corporeal world by the

appellation of earth.” This opinion is soon going to confuse the Alumnus with the

laudable effect of furthering the clarification of the relation between primordial causes

and prime matter. Two more opinions, of St. Basil and St. Maximus the Confessor, are

mentioned but the Nutritor considers it “tedious and irrelevant to the subject of the

present work to prolong the discussion.” This reluctance to contradict the opinions of

the fathers bespeaks, of course, of Eriugena’s reverence for them. It also points to the

arbitrariness of his interpretation of the words without any hermeneutic necessity. This

fact would become clearer when we contrast the scriptural basis of primordial causes to

that of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s immutable identities in the second section of the present chapter.

4.1.24.1.24.1.24.1.2 Causes as the origin of intelliCauses as the origin of intelliCauses as the origin of intelliCauses as the origin of intelligible and sensible creaturesgible and sensible creaturesgible and sensible creaturesgible and sensible creatures

Without intending to refute these opinions Eriugena solemnly offers his own

interpretation: “I think that in the aforementioned words of the Scripture, we should

understand the primordial causes of the whole creature, which the father created in his

only begotten son, who is given the name of ‘beginning.’” According to Eriugena

“heaven signifies the primordial causes of the intelligible and celestial essences while

earth points to those of the sensible things by which the universe of this corporeal world

is made up.” Sheldon-Williams has noted that here “primordial causes” are not identical

with the intelligibles, but the common cause of intelligibles and sensibles. This apt

observation serves to distinguish Eriugena’s causes from Plato’s ideas which are

normally understood to be the intelligible archetype of the sensible objects. We can add

that Eriugena’s interpretation can be considered a combination of the opinions of

Philo/Alexandrines and St. Gregory of Nyssa and not a complete contradiction thereof.

Page 91: 988S

78

4.1.34.1.34.1.34.1.3 Primordial Causes and Primordial Causes and Primordial Causes and Primordial Causes and materia primamateria primamateria primamateria prima

Now, although Eriugena had refused to enter into controversy with competing

interpretations of Genesis, the Alumnus expresses his “slight trouble” over seeing how

Eriugena’s interpretation differs from the one which identified heaven and earth with

the formlessness of things because “we say that the formless matter and its formlessness

are a kind of cause of things.” In reply the Nutritor shows that prime matter cannot be

called “cause” in a proper sense and that there is a world of difference between his

interpretation and that of St. Gregory of Nyssa. First, the difference cannot be slight

between “formlessness of things” and “cause” of things since nothing is closer to true

non-being than the former while nothing is closer to true being than the created causes

of created things. He then refers to the principle that “the cause, if it truly be the cause,

most perfectly pre-encompasses in itself all things of which it is the cause and perfects

in itself its effects before they become manifest in anything.” Therefore, we cannot call

formless matter a “cause” of essence and form and perfection of things but rather it is

privation of the essence, form and perfection of things. After listening to these

arguments the Alumnus suddenly gets wiser and not only concedes to them but tries to

elaborate the distinction further than his teacher. As he puts it, the formlessness of

things is nothing else but a certain motion which is departing from absolute non-being

and seeking its rest in that which truly is. The primordial causes, on the other hand, are

so created in the Beginning, that is in the word of God which is truly said to be and is,

that they do not by any motion seek their perfection in anything.” Since the causes of

place and time are in them they have nowhere to depart but they themselves by no

means look toward the things that are below them, but eternally contemplate their Form

which is above them. (Ibid. II: 547B-D) He also adds that the primordial causes have a

Page 92: 988S

79

cause of everything and this includes prime matter itself so the latter cannot be identical

to the former. (See ibid. II: 548A)

4.1.44.1.44.1.44.1.4 Immutable perfection of the causesImmutable perfection of the causesImmutable perfection of the causesImmutable perfection of the causes

The Nutritor then comments on Genesis I.2-3: “But the earth was waste and void and

darkness was over the face of the abyss (terra autem erat inanis et vacua et tenebrae

super faciem abyssi).” He mentions that the earlier commentators have identified “waste

and void” with the formlessness of visible creatures and “dark abyss” with the

formlessness of invisible essence and “earth.” He also talks about those who pointed to

“this hulk of earthly body” to be intended by the aforementioned words. Like before, he

announces his reluctance to adjudicate between the opinions of the Holy fathers and his

interest in selecting out of these the one which seems after rational consideration to

accord the better with the Divine Oracles. (See ibid. II: 549A) As one would expect,

these words “refer to nothing other than the primordial causes.” (Ibid.) The words

“waste and void” “signify rather the most complete and immutable perfection of the

primordial nature that was created before all things in the Word than the mutable and

imperfect and as yet formless procession of this sensible world extended in places and

times and coming into being through generation and seeking to be formed in the diverse

individuals of the sensible creatures.” (Ibid. II: 549B) After giving some examples from

classical literature of the usage of these words, Eriugena concludes that there is no

wonder that if the primordial causes of visible things are figuratively signified by “waste

and void earth” on account of their excessive subtlety and the ineffable simplicity of

their intelligible nature before they flowed forth through generation into species and

sensible individuals.

Page 93: 988S

80

4.1.54.1.54.1.54.1.5 Questions of Knowability: Questions of Knowability: Questions of Knowability: Questions of Knowability:

Darkness of the primordial causesDarkness of the primordial causesDarkness of the primordial causesDarkness of the primordial causes

As for the word “abyss” it is applied by the scripture to the primordial causes of

intelligible essence on account of its unfathomable depth. Likewise they earn the name

of darkness because of their purity. (See ibid. II: 550C) In his explanation of “darkness”

Eriugena points out that the sun often brings darkness upon those who look into it since

they are unable to face its excessive brilliance, “thus there was darkness over the abyss

of the primordial causes. For before they entered into the plurality of the spiritual

essences no created intellect could know of them what they were, and darkness is still

over this abyss because it is perceived by no intellect except that which formed it in the

beginning. (See ibid. II: 550D-551A) Here Eriugena has maintained that the primordial

causes are unknowable, hence an inquiry into this issue ensues. Eriugena asks whether

this unknowability is permanent or pertains only to this visible world. He thinks that the

causes are always invisible and dark. (Ibid. II: 551C)

The Nutritor likes this answer and adds that the causes both proceed into the

things of which they are the causes and at the same time do not depart from their

Principle that is, the wisdom of the father in which they are created, remaining

themselves eternally concealed in the darkness of their excellence, they do not cease to

appear by being brought forth into light as it were of knowledge in their effects. (See

ibid. II: 552A) As far as their unknowability is concerned, the primordial causes are just

like the uncreated creator we dealt with in the previous chapter.

SelfSelfSelfSelf----KnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledge

The Nutritor next attends to the question about the self-knowledge of the primordial

causes. Since it is not to be believed that anything was created in the Divine Wisdom

Page 94: 988S

81

which is not wise and does not know itself “all things that were made in Wisdom, as

wisdom knows herself and the things that are made in her, so not only know themselves

but also do not lack knowledge of the things of which they are the principles.” (See ibid.

II: 552B)

Creation of the primordial causes took place through the Holy Spirit. In order to

establish this dimension of the causes, Eriugena refers to a slightly different version of

Genesis I: 2 viz., Et spiritus dei fouebat acquas, “and the Spirit of God fermented the

waters.” This means in Eriugena’s understanding that the Holy Spirit nourished the

primordial causes in the fermentation of the Divine Love so that they might proceed

into their effects, like the eggs are fermented by the birds. (See DDN II: 554B). In

addition to bringing out the function of Holy Spirit, this passage also reminds us that

the causes were made in the Son of God. Hence the creation of primordial causes

involves God the father, God the Holy Spirit and God the Son, all three persons of

Trinity. In view of this a long digression starts into the nature of this trinity.127 Eriugena

resumes the discussion of primordial causes at DDN II: 615D by identifying them with

some Greek philosophical concepts.128

Primordial Causes Known to GodPrimordial Causes Known to GodPrimordial Causes Known to GodPrimordial Causes Known to God

In order to show that the primordial causes, unknowable to every intellect, are after all

known to God, Eriugena offers his symbolic interpretation of Genesis I.2, “And the

spirit of God was borne above the waters (et [spiritus Dei] superferebatur super aquas).”

God comprehends them in His super-eminent (and) infinite Gnostic power since He

127 Since we have treated the subject of trinity in Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabī in the previous chapter, we will

not touch upon it in the present chapter. 128

We have mentioned these in the beginning of this section.

Page 95: 988S

82

made them in the beginning as a kind of foundations and principles of all the natures

which are from Him. (See ibid. II: 553A)

One of the reasons for the aforementioned words of the Genesis Eriugena thinks

is that in their absence one could have thought that “the primordial causes of all (things)

are of such excellence that no higher cause precedes them so as to surpass them. For

there is one and the same cause of all things out of which, through which and in which

and for which the causes and preceding origins of all things were first created.” (Ibid)

Again, a further meaning of the superferebatur super acquas is given, viz.: “it is borne

above all things because it precedes the order of the universal creature which takes the

beginning of its being from it and in it finds its end.” (Ibid. II: 553B. Emphasis added)

Obviously the former explanation was epistemological one while this latter is

ontological since it involves the existence of primordial causes rather than the question

of their knowability. While summing up his interpretation Eriugena combines both in

this way: “Only the Creator Spirit is super-eminent over created causes in the excellence

of His knowledge and is the one and only cause which precedes and excels over all the

causes.” (Ibid. II: 553C)

4.1.64.1.64.1.64.1.6 Primordial Causes and the EvilPrimordial Causes and the EvilPrimordial Causes and the EvilPrimordial Causes and the Evil

The notion of primordial causes being made in Wisdom gives rise to an interesting

question: “If the primordial causes have wisdom of themselves because they are created

in wisdom and subsist eternally in that which admits nothing unwise in itself, how is it

that from the wise causes many unwise things proceed?”(DDN II: 554B) Eriugena

suggests an answer with the help of an analogy: “It is not strange that the causes of

unwise things subsist in wise exemplars when we see that the origins of darkness

Page 96: 988S

83

naturally inhere in the rays of the sun and that while these allow no darkness in

themselves, yet they produce it as opposite.” (See ibid. II: 552C)

Thus he admits that the responsibility for things thought to be evil exists in

primordial causes he is not ready to believe that this implies that these causes

themselves are evil. However, this very example shows that the relation he is willingly

admitting between primordial causes and evil in not a direct relation but an indirect one.

The sun is directly responsible for light while darkness is inevitable but indirect result of

a ray from the sun. Those who are fond of making connections with Neo-Platonism

might discern behind this explanation an identification of evil with non-existence, in our

opinion the most valuable implication of this proposed solution is that evil can be

considered as the logically necessary counterpart of the good.

4.1.74.1.74.1.74.1.7 Timeless creation of the primordial causes: Timeless creation of the primordial causes: Timeless creation of the primordial causes: Timeless creation of the primordial causes:

In connection with there being a cause of primordial causes two caveats must be made.

First, since Eriugena has mentioned the precedence of the spiritus dei over the

primordial causes, he is quick to add that it is not implied that one thing is created

sooner or later than another in a temporal sense, for “all things are eternally in it and

were created by it at the same time.” (Ibid. II: 553B) The second caveat is that the

timeless creation of primordial causes should not be taken to mean “being made out of

nonexistence” but “they are participations of the one cause of all things, namely the

most high and holy trinity.” (Ibid. II: 616B)

4.1.84.1.84.1.84.1.8 No creature between God and the primordial causes.No creature between God and the primordial causes.No creature between God and the primordial causes.No creature between God and the primordial causes.

Although the primordial causes are intermediary between God and the spatio-temporal

world there is nothing between them and God. The Scripture mentions the spirit being

borne above the water because, Eriugena says, “the Divine providence brought forth

Page 97: 988S

84

from non-existence into existence the universe of created nature in an order (which is)

ineffable and incomprehensible to every intellect” and because they are in the immediate

and proximate presence of God without the interposition of any higher creature (See

DDN II: 553B-C) This notion of the direct relation of primordial causes to God has its

merits and demerits. On the one hand it makes Eriugena safe from susceptibility to

third-man like arguments. On the other hand it gives rise to confusion. One might

wonder how it is possible to say that there is nothing between God and primordial

causes once it is admitted with Eriugena that these causes were made by the Father in

the Son.

4.1.94.1.94.1.94.1.9 Hierarchy of Primordial Causes:Hierarchy of Primordial Causes:Hierarchy of Primordial Causes:Hierarchy of Primordial Causes:

Eriugena has already enumerated some of the primordial causes in Book II, but, as the

Alumnus complains, “in an confused and indiscriminate sequence:” Goodness-through-

itself, being -through-itself, Life-through-itself, Wisdom-through-itself, Truth-through-

itself, Intellect-through-itself, Reason-through-itself, Power-through-itself, Justice-

through-itself, Health-through-itself, Magnitude -through-itself, Omnipotence-through-

itself, Eternity -through-itself and Peace-through-itself. (See ibid. II: 616C) Urged by

the Alumnus to explain the natural order of the causes and by appealing to the authority

of Pseudo Dionysius, Eriugena presents ten primordial causes in an order of hierarchy.

The first is goodness-through-itself by participation in which whatsoever things are

good are good. (See ibid. III. 622 B-C) The highest primordial cause is followed by

Essence (being), Life, Reason, Intellect,129 Wisdom, Power, Blessedness, Truth, Eternity

and Infinity. Important questions arise regarding the specific ordering of the primordial

129

On the difference between reason and intellect see DDN, II.577B-C and section 1.4.3.

Page 98: 988S

85

causes but before addressing them let us first analyze the passage referred to above in

order to map the place of primordial causes within the cosmic hierarchy.

Eriugena tells us in that passage that the creatures forming the external world

participate in primordial causes which in turn participate in God. But God in whom each

specific primordial cause participates will be mentioned by a specific name. In the

passage at hand the primordial cause being discussed is goodness-through-itself and God

is mentioned as Supreme Goodness or Goodness-through-itself. Same will be the case

with all primordial causes. For instance, we will say that whatever has being in this

world is so by participation in being- in- itself which participates in nothing but is

participation of being which is Super-essential Goodness. Hence in order for a specific

primordial cause to be a participation of super-essential Good it must participate

specifically in Super-essential Good. What is the nature and what are the principles of

this specification? Eriugena seems to be silent so we have to place a question mark in

the following table of Eriugena’s cosmic hierarchy. We are pressing this point since we

hope to find a clearer position in this regard in our discussion of a similar notion in Ibn

‘Arabi>. The hierarchy of the causes themselves within a wider cosmic hierarchy is

presented diagrammatically on the next page.

Page 99: 988S

87

4.1.104.1.104.1.104.1.10 Infinity of Primordial CausesInfinity of Primordial CausesInfinity of Primordial CausesInfinity of Primordial Causes

The above table on the previous page gives us three divisions of nature, God, causes and

the world shown in the three rows and these can be reduced to just the first one, as we

have already seen in a previous chapter.130 Let us notice here that the ten causes that

Eriugena mentions here are only the first ten out of infinite number of them. Since the

causes can be reduced to their principle which is none other than God, Eriugena sees no

problem in calling them infinite: “For as the First Cause of all things, from which and in

which and through which they are created, is infinite so neither do they know any end to

limit them…” (Ibid. III: 623D) The presumption seems to be that the effect must

resemble its cause.

4.1.114.1.114.1.114.1.11Simplicity and Unity of Primordial CausesSimplicity and Unity of Primordial CausesSimplicity and Unity of Primordial CausesSimplicity and Unity of Primordial Causes

About the hierarchy Eriugena observes that it “is constituted not in themselves but in

the aspects, that is, in the concept of the mind which investigates them and which

conceives in itself such knowledge of them as is permitted…” (Ibid. III: 624A) A little

latter he says, “The order of the primordial causes is constituted in the judgment of the

mind which contemplates them… a devout and pure-minded philosopher may start from

any one of them at will.” (Ibid. III: 624 C) The real intention of Eriugena in emphasizing

role of mind is not to deny their objective status as much as to emphasize their unity,

first with their principle and then among themselves. Thus he writes, explaining the

above quoted passage III: 624A, “For in themselves these first causes are one and simple

and none knows the order in which they are placed or distinguished one from another.

For, this is something that happens to them in their effects. “(Ibid. III: 624A-B) Second,

130

See chapter 2 section 2.1.

Page 100: 988S

88

near the end of discussion of hierarchy Eriugena makes the Alumnus exclaim, “who

would reasonably look for order or number in those things which are created by the

Creator of all things because of the loftiness of their nature beyond every order and

every number, seeing that the beginnings of all number and all order are in themselves

united with one another and cannot be seen apart in the eyes of any lower nature.” (Ibid.

III: 626C) Eriugena also says, “For they are one and a simple one and not a one that is

composite of many.”(Ibid. III: 624B) There is no way to distinguish the primordial

causes from one another accept through looking at their effects. Hence, in themselves

they are one but they are multiplied by proceeding into their effects. Eriugena provides

his readers with two models to illustrate the simplicity of primordial causes, firstly

subsistence of all numbers in the monad (Ibid. III: 624 A-B) and secondly, the unity of

all lines at the centre point. (Ibid. III: 625A)

These two facts, namely their simplicity/ unity and their containing the cause of

order, provide the basic rationale for the claim that there is no order among the

primordial causes in themselves but only in the mind that contemplates them. Eriugena

is not consciously putting forward an idealistic view of nature, as Moran and others

think.131 He is not absolutely denying the objective existence of order but denying it

only from a certain perspective. Moreover, the existence of order only in the judgment

of contemplating mind does not prevent primordial causes from creating order within

their effects. Thus, Eriugena asserts that every ordered thing is ordered through

participation in its primordial cause which is order-through-itself and which in turn

participates in Order which is the Cause of all things. (See DDN, III: 624B) If the

provision of hierarchy leads someone to suppose that there is real multiplicity within the

131

Cf. Dermot Moran, The Philosophy, 261.

Page 101: 988S

89

causes, it would be said that hierarchy exists only in mind. Hence even though the order

of causes is in mind, it is not an illusion.

4.1.124.1.124.1.124.1.12 Priority of “Goodness” and ObjectivityPriority of “Goodness” and ObjectivityPriority of “Goodness” and ObjectivityPriority of “Goodness” and Objectivity of Hierarchy of Hierarchy of Hierarchy of Hierarchy

The idealistic implications of above discussed passages are further jeopardized when

Eriugena explains why he started with a particular primordial cause by giving an

objective criterion. The Alumnus expresses the desire to know why his dialogue partner

started with a particular cause, goodness-through-itself rather than any other since “it is

not the way of those who dispute in an orderly manner to waste time in saying anything

without reason.” (Ibid. III: 627A) The question presupposes that although every mind is

free to order the causes as it likes, there is no room for arbitrariness, solid reasons must

be there for the order particularly envisaged. After making an esoteric confession of his

humility, the Nutritor gives two reasons. First, he had learnt from the authority of holy

fathers, especially Pseudo Dionysius that goodness-through-itself is the most general of

the Divine gifts and in some manner precedes others. (See ibid. III: 627C) He asserts

emphatically that goodness must be prior to and considered more basic than being, for

“all things that are, are insofar as they are good, but in so far as they are not good, or

rather they are less good, to that extent they are not, and so if goodness is removed, no

essence remains.” (Ibid. III: 628A) This assertion is bound to seem a little curious in the

first sight. Eriugena grants that one could object that in order for there being goodness,

there first must be something which is good, so it would seem more appropriate to say

that if being is removed no goodness remains. He takes the bold step of including

nothingness within goodness and indeed the bolder one of saying that non-existent

things are better than those which are, “for the further they transcend essence by reason

of their excellence, the nearer they approach the Superessential Good, namely God,

Page 102: 988S

90

whereas the more they participate in essence the further they are separated from the

Superessential good.” (Ibid. III: 628 B)132

Eriugena proceeds to establish goodness as the highest genus (summum genus)

that has as species two groups, things that are and things that are not. Hence the second

primordial cause is one species of genus goodness. Likewise, being is the genus which

includes things that live and things that do not; life includes reason, reason wisdom, so

on and so forth. The Alumnus quickly formulates the rule underlying the ordering, or as

Eriugena calls it, the division of primordial causes: “Everyone who employs the method

of division correctly ought to begin from the most general and proceed through more

general, and so… arrive at the most specific.” No arguments need to be mustered in

order to show that the original apparent idealism of the hierarchy of primordial causes

loses its strength by the time we arrive at this point in argument.

4.24.24.24.2 Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Fixed Entities in Comparison with Primordial Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Fixed Entities in Comparison with Primordial Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Fixed Entities in Comparison with Primordial Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Fixed Entities in Comparison with Primordial

CausesCausesCausesCauses

The concept of primordial causes implies that Eriugena does not believe in a single and

direct act of creation but in a sort of double creation because God creates first the

primordial causes and then their effects are brought about. Will there be a place for this

or a parallel concept in Muslim religious cosmology? It would seem that the Qur’a>n

precludes any such view by saying that “His command, when He desires a thing, is to

say to it ‘Be!’ and it is.” (36:82). Hence all that the Creative act involves is Divine will,

a Divine command (Be!) and things come to be. Nothing lies between Divine command

and the coming into existence of a thing. Ibn ‘Arabi>, however, does not read the Qur’a>n

132

Cf. Schuon viz., “To speak of the world is to speak of separation from the Principle and to speak of

separation is to speak of the possibility –and necessity – of evil.” See his “The Problem of Theodicies,” in

Islam and the Perennial Philosophy (Lahore: Suhail Academy, 1984), 165.

Page 103: 988S

91

36:82 in that way and puts forward the concept of fixed entities (عيان الثابتةEا) that

interpolates, in a way, between Divine command and the thing that comes into

existence.

4.2.14.2.14.2.14.2.1 The Scriptural Foundation of the ConceptThe Scriptural Foundation of the ConceptThe Scriptural Foundation of the ConceptThe Scriptural Foundation of the Concept

Just as Eriugena introduced his concept of primordial causes through his understanding

of Scripture, Ibn ‘Arabi> comes up with the concept of fixed entities by his reading of the

Qur’a>n, interestingly, of the very passage referred to above as implying direct creation

through Divine will and command. He requires from us to pay closer attention to the

letter of those Qur’a>nic words. As if he is asking that if creation takes place out of

absolute nothingness, so that the desired thing does not exist in any sense of the word,

then to whom is God’s command is addressed? In his discussion of Divine nothingness

in Eriugena this very question is raised by Michael Sells in connection with what he

aptly calls the problem of “ontological shadow,” a problem that according to him haunts

Eriugenian doctrine of participation.133 As we have seen, participatio is the relation

between primordial causes and their creator on the one hand134 and between them and

their spatio-temporal effects on the other and both these sides raise this problem. As for

the participation of primordial causes in being, “‘how can being flow into primordial

causes and ‘make them to be?’ They would have to ‘be’ in order to act as vessels

receiving the flow of being.”135 Regarding the participation of the effects in their

primordial causes, we can ask, “What were they before they received their being?”

133

See his Mystical Languages of Unsaying, 38. 134

At DDN III: 632B-C Eriugena also expresses this particular relation with the help of “an emanation

metaphor” according to which, in Sell’s summary, “After welling up within the source… everything

“which is in the source of all things” then “flow out first into the primordial causes” and then “make them

be”. Mystical Languages, 40. 135

Ibid.

Page 104: 988S

92

When Ibn ‘Arabi> asks “Whom is God addressing with His command “Be!” at the

moment of creation, supposedly, out of absolute nothingness?” he is obviously raising

this very ontological shadow problem. However when he comes up with his concept of

fixed entities, it is a result of accepting the logical requirement of this very problem.136

To provide further scriptural foundation to his concept of fixed entities, Ibn

‘Arabi> refers to another Qur’a>nic verse, “There is nothing whose treasuries are not with

us (15: 21)”:

But treasuries are nothing but the fixed objects of knowledge, which, then, are

fixed with Him, he sees them and sees what is in them so He brings out from

them whatever he likes and he keeps whose being in them he desires. (Fut.

IV: 295)

The identification of Divine treasuries as the container of fixed entities reminds us of an

expression Eriugena used to talk about things when before coming into spatio-temporal

existence, they are still in their primordial causes. According to the third mode of

demarcation, things which are still held in those secret folds of nature and are not as yet

manifest are said not to be. The “secret folds of nature” at this point without doubt is

the Eriugenian counterpart of the “treasuries of everything” of which Ibn ‘Arabi> talks.

Hence before existence attaches to them, things are in the treasuries of God, as

fixed objects of His knowledge. These fixed objects of Divine knowledge are called

“fixed entities” and these are addressed by the Divine Command “Be!” Creation

therefore consists in bringing them out, in the sense of bestowing spatio-temporal

existence upon them. Thus Ibn ‘Arabi> talks about two phases of creation separated by

the Divine command, first, the creation of determination (خلق تقدير) and second which is

136

Cf. the Kantian view that something must exist first in order to become predicated with perfection or

any other such attribute.

Page 105: 988S

93

coextensive with the Divine command, the creation of existence giving (خلق إيجاد) (Ibid.

IV: 210; trans. SDG, 50) The first creation consists, not in making (facere), but in

determining the nature of what is to be created. Once the nature is determined, Divine

command is directed to the object determined in the Divine knowledge, so the “thing”

mentioned in Qur’a>n 36:82 is the fixed entity.

Does this mean that the entities are mutable? Ibn ‘Arabi> likens fixed entities

with the pole around which a round millstone revolves, while the pole itself neither

revolves nor moves from one point to another. (Fut. IV: 416) Izutsu observes about

these entities that “they have been fixed once and for all in the eternal past, and are

therefore absolutely unalterable and immovable. “There is no altering in the words of

God.”(10:64)137 However, Ibn ‘Arabi> himself has also allowed mutability in the fixed

entities by saying, “Each entity receives changes of state, qualities, accidents, and the

like, for it becomes clothed in the affair that is off to its side and toward which it

changes.” (Fut. IV: 210; trans. SDG, 51) To understand this conflict between

immutability and mutability a distinction must be made. It will be observed that the

change which Ibn ‘Arabi> allows does not include change of essence but only of accidents

and states etc. Hence one entity never changes into another; it might change its state.

The above discussion shows that, just like Eriugena’s primordial causes, Ibn

‘Arabi>’s concept of fixed entities is based on his understanding of Scripture. However,

unlike Eriugena, here Ibn ‘Arabi>’s interpretation does not seem arbitrary and allegorical

rather it is literal and necessitated by logic. Ibn ‘Arabi> does not simply identify a word

in the Scripture with a philosophical concept but raises a hermeneutical question on the

text and then suggests his solution relying upon other Qur’a>nic verses. His

137

Toshihiko Izutsu, Sufism and Taoism, 168.

Page 106: 988S

94

interpretation is in line with the basic principles of Qur’a>n interpretation stressing the

necessity of honesty to language and taking into account different passages of the

Scripture itself.

Although Ibn ‘Arabi> tries to show that his concept has scriptural foundations and

he develops it to its farthest limits, he frankly admits its historical roots in Muslim

theology. (See Fut. IV: 210) These roots lie in the controversy over whether or not the

nonexistent (المعدوم) is a thing, a controversy which in Wolfson’s opinion, hid the

question of ex nihilo creation, behind it.138 Ibn ‘Arabi> takes sides with the Mu‘tazilites

and thinks that their position can be supported by evidence from the Islamic sources:

It has been narrated from the prophet who narrated it from God the Exalted that

He said: I was a treasure but was not known so I loved to be known and I

created the creatures and made myself known to them. In the words, “I was a

treasure,” one finds an affirmation of the immutable entities which were upheld

by the Mu‘tazilites. (Ibid. II: 232; trans. SPK, 294)

Hence, the fixed entities are the objects of Divine knowledge which under

Divine command come into engendered existence.

4.2.24.2.24.2.24.2.2 Ontological StatusOntological StatusOntological StatusOntological Status

An important issue in the comparison of primordial causes and fixed entities is that of

their ontological status. As far as the primordial causes are concerned we have to

synthesize two Eriugenian positions. On the one hand we see Eriugena, in book III,

assigning them a place “closest to the true being” in contrast to the prime matter which

is said to be next to nothing. He considers them so perfect in all respects that they do

not seek perfection in anything, including existence. According to this standpoint,

primordial causes really are. On the contrary when we recall the third mode of being, in

138

See The Philosophy of Kalam, 359 passim.

Page 107: 988S

95

Book I, we remember Eriugena saying that “whatever of these (i.e. primordial) causes

through generation is known as to matter and form, as to times and places,” is said to be

while “whatsoever is still held in those folds of nature and is not manifest as to form or

matter, place or time, and the other accidents” is said not to be. According to this mode

primordial causes belong to the category of non-existent things whike their spatio-

temporal effects are among things which exist. Eriugena comes back to this mode in a

latter place. When the alumnus questions him about things “being made and being

eternal at the same time,” Eriugena tells him that “they were always; they were not

always.” “They “were always” as causes in the word of God, in potentiality, beyond

every quality and quantity.” They “were not always because before they flowed out

throught generation into the forms… they were not in generation.” (DDN III: 665B)139

This shows that it would be closer to the intentions of Eriugena to say that primordial

causes both are and are not.

Ibn ‘Arabi> frequently emphasizes that the fixed entities are called “fixed” since

they are fixed “in nonexistence:” “The identities (=entities) which have an immutable

non-existence within Him, have not sensed the odor of any existent.” (Fus}. 76; trans.

Ringstones, 53) This view of non-existence of fixed entities can be seen as a response to

a difficulty raised by the Qur’a>nic declaration that a thing is nonexistent before

creation: “Will not man remember that we created him aforetime, when he was

nothing.” (19:67) While Ibn ‘Arabi>’s interpretation of Qur’a>n 36:82 was that things in

some way do exist before creation. Therefore Ibn ‘Arabi> divides what he calls

“thingness” (شئيئة) into two sorts which give us two phases in the history of anything

namely, thingness of fixity and thingness of existence. ( شئيئة الثبوت ) and “thingness of

139

Some important problems in this passage are discussed by Sells, Mystical Languages, 54-55.

Page 108: 988S

96

existence” (شئيئة الوجود). Before coming into spatio-temporal world of existence the thing

is in the former state. Ibn ‘Arabi> does not contrast immutability with mutability but

with existence and consequently a fixed entity “remains fixed in its non-existence.”

(Fut. III: 566; trans. SPK, 29-30) They come to be once God, The Exalted Light,

discloses Himself to them “while they are in the state of their non-existence.” (See Fut.

I: 732)

It is certainly very odd to consider non-existent something which has been

posited as the listener of “Be!” before emergence in spatiotemporal existence. The

whole point of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s interpretation of Divine command was to show that the

addressee must exist before existing (ref. ontological shadow), hence labeling of fixed

entities as nonexistence must not be the whole story and we have to look for the other

half of it.

On the other hand we find in Ibn ‘Arabi> several indications that one must not

press the non-existence of fixed entities too far. Firstly, he clarifies that by the non-

existence of the fixed entities he does not mean absolute nonexistence. He connects the

ontological sense of non-existence (i.e. not-being) to the epistemological one (i.e. not

being known or found) by identifying it as an existence which we do not perceive. “So

things are never in sheer nonexistence, on the contrary, the apparent situation is that

their nonexistence is a relative nonexistence, the things are witnessed by God.” (Ibid.

III: 193; trans. SPK-87)140 Secondly, Ibn ‘Arabi> also allows a specific sort of existence to

the fixed entities which he calls “imaginalized existence” (Ibid. IV: 210; trans. SDG, 51)

and it is well known that the “imaginal” with Ibn ‘Arabi> is not the “imaginary” or

“unreal.”

140

“What is with you comes to an end but what is with God remains.” (16:96)

Page 109: 988S

97

One of the reasons behind Eriugena’s claim that primordial causes are closest to

the real Being is revealed by his assertion that no creature interpolates between the

Creator and the primordial causes. Now, even if Ibn ‘Arabi> does assign non-existence to

his fixed entities he is at one with Eriugena at this point. He writes, speaking about the

fixed entity he has in the Divine knowledge, “I am nearer to the Real in the state of my

being qualified with nonexistence than in the state of my being qualified with existence

due to the claim (الدعوى) that is found in it.” (Ibid. II: 528) He means that since real

existence is God’s but in some sense creature also exists and seeing that there is certain

continuity between two sorts of existence the creature might become proud and claim

existence vis. a vis. God. Since nonexistents lack this continuity they are immune from

making such proud claim so they are in a better position than the existents. In section

4.1.12 we found Eriugena elevating the non-existents over the existents on account of

their similarity to Divine nothingness. Ibn ‘Arabi> thinks that it is on account of their

dissimilarity with Divine being that nonexistents are better than the existent. At this

point the final conclusion of our both writers is identical although they are assigning

different reasons for reaching that conclusion.

In the second chapter we discussed Ibn ‘Arabi>’s division of totality and came

across the “third thing.” We mentioned there that Ibn ‘Arabi> identifies this with the

locus of fixed entities. This makes it possible to synthesize the apparently conflicting

standpoints that fixed entities are both existent and nonexistent. Ibn ‘Arabi> writes about

the locus of fixed entities:

This is the Supreme Barzakh, or the Barzakh of Barzakhs. It possesses a face

toward being and a face toward nothingness. It stands opposite each of these

two known things in its very essence. It is the third known thing in its very

essence. (Ibid. III: 46; trans. SPK, 204)

Page 110: 988S

98

Hence Ibn ‘Arabi>’s position on the ontological status of fixed entities contains

two contrary claims which are synthesized in a third claim. If our reading of Eriugena on

the same question was accurate then his view of the status of the primordial causes was

the same. This synthetic view is the only inevitable one on account of the ontological

shadow, present in Eriugena as a problem but in Ibn ‘Arabi> as a way to a new concept

which demands that certain things exist before they are (priusquam essent).

In a context like the present one, where existence is not considered to be limited

to spatio-temporal existence only, it can be more helpful to set apart the word

“existence” for things that exist in space and/or time and use the word “reality” for

things that although non-existent in the specific sense are not unreal. If this

terminological suggestion is accepted then we can say that although both primordial

causes of Eriugena and the fixed entities of Ibn ‘Arabi> do not exist, they are real.

4.2.34.2.34.2.34.2.3 Fixed Entities and Fixed Entities and Fixed Entities and Fixed Entities and Materia PrimaMateria PrimaMateria PrimaMateria Prima

Another point can be briefly mentioned at this juncture is with reference to the relation

of primordial causes and fixed entities with materia prima. Eriugena is not ready to

identify primordial causes with prime matter since the former are perfect beings while

the latter is “next “to nothing.” Ibn ‘Arabi> is more positive to the concept of prime

matter and uses it to elaborate the relation between fixed entity and existent entity. In

his shorter work Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir, having identified the presence of fixed entities with

the “third thing” he likens the relation of the realm of fixed entities to the world to the

relation between a chair or any wooden piece of furniture with wood and explicitly

permits labeling the third thing as hylé (ھيولى) or prime matter. (Insha>’, 19) 141 However,

it must be observed that the basic purpose of mentioning prime matter here is not to

141

The translation has been taken with modification from Izutsu’s Sufism and Taoism, 162.

Page 111: 988S

99

identify it literally with one of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concepts but only that of analogically

elaborating one of his doctrines.

4.2.44.2.44.2.44.2.4 The Questions of Knowability The Questions of Knowability The Questions of Knowability The Questions of Knowability

An important and multidimensional issue in Eriugena’s discussion of primordial causes

was that of knowability. First, does God know them? Second, do the causes know God?

Third, are they accessible to human knowledge? Here we raise these very questions,

again, but with respect to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of the fixed entities, in order to shed

some more light on their nature in comparison with Eriugena’s primordial causes.

DivineDivineDivineDivine knowledge and the Fixed Entities:knowledge and the Fixed Entities:knowledge and the Fixed Entities:knowledge and the Fixed Entities: Ibn ‘Arabi> subjects his fixed entities to Divine

power and knowledge in a fashion similar to Eriugena since the latter tried to infer from

the Scripture (i.e. et spiritus dei superferebatur super acquas) that primordial causes are

under the power of their creator. Ibn ‘Arabi> writes, interpreting a Qur’a>nic verse “And

He is powerful over everything” (5: 120) that here the Qur’a>n is speaking about the

thingness of fixed entities, and telling that they are under the authority of God.... (Fut. II:

95) The fixed entities also do not escape Divine knowledge rather their very essence

consists in being objects of Divine knowledge. As always, at this point too, Ibn ‘Arabi>

appeals to the Qur’a>n. He writes, taking advantage of the word “thing” in a Qur’a>nic

verse “And He knows everything” (2:29) and interpreting the word “everything” as

“thingness of entities and thingness of existence in so far as its genera, species and

individuals” (Ibid. II: 95) Since there is nothing “hidden” for God “He sees us in the

state of our non-existence in the thingness of our fixity as He does in the state of our

existence.” (Ibid. I: 732)

Do Entities know God?Do Entities know God?Do Entities know God?Do Entities know God? Thus, God knows the entities that are fixed in nonexistence, but

do the entities know Him? “Absolutely not”, answers Ibn ‘Arabi> interpreting

Page 112: 988S

100

symbolically a h}adi>th saying, “Majesty is His cloak and tremendousness His shawl.”142

He tells us that when God addressed the fixed entities with His word “The Cosmos was

witnessed by Him but He was not witnessed by it. Upon the eyes of the possible things

was the veil of non-existence, no other.” (Ibid. II: 303; trans. SPK, 93-94)

Are they knowable to us?Are they knowable to us?Are they knowable to us?Are they knowable to us? The third question in this discussion is: Can we know things

in the state of their fixity of nonexistence or is our knowledge limited to the objects that

exist in spatio-temporal terms? The answer is that the entities are not absolutely

inaccessible to human knowledge. When God wills, some of His servants can know them

through spiritual unveiling: “…there are servants of God whom God gives to see,

through unveiling, the fixed entities. Then they see them in the form of the adjacency

that we have mentioned. But rational consideration does not see that the entities have

either state or locus.” (Ibid. IV: 81; trans. SDG, 34) Ibn ‘Arabi> also thinks that the

workings of human imagination are grounded in knowledge of the fixed entities. Thus

he writes, “When any human being who possesses an imagination and the power to

imagine imagines something, his gaze extends into this Barzakh, though he does not

know that he is looking upon that thing in this presence.” (Ibid. III: 47; trans. SPK, 205)

Here Ibn ‘Arabi> adds a limitation to the imaginal knowledge of the entities, one knows

them without being conscious of them. He tells us in his Fus}u>s} that knowledge of fixed

entities is bestowed upon some individuals and this bestowal is not permanent but is

made at certain times. (Fus.} 99; trans. Ringstones, 94)143 Mus}t}afa> Ba>li> Za>deh, a

commentator on Fus}u>s}, tells us that these individuals are the Prophets and Friends of

142

Muslim, S}ah}i>h}, Kita>b al-Birr wa al-S}ilah, ba>b tah}ri>m al-Kibr 143

We do not agree with Dagli’s translation of the italicized three words. See the note below.

Page 113: 988S

101

God.144 The limitation is that even these individuals do not always know the fixed

entities but, as Da>wu>d al-Qays}ari>, another great Fus}u>s} commentator, puts it “This

unveiling is not permanent but is at certain moments and not at others as He said to his

Prophet “Say ‘… I do not know what shall be done with me or you (46:9)’.” All this

applies to the knowability of entities in general and Ibn ‘Arabi> marks an area as

unknowable mystery by maintaining that the form of existentiation or acceptance of

existence of the entities always remains beyond the knowledge of creatures. Only God

knows these modalities. (See Fut. II: 103)

Thus, the fixed entities are partially knowable to some human beings and that

too through special acts of Divine grace and not through rational understanding but by a

spiritual unveiling.

In summing up the issue, it can carefully be maintained that like the primordial

causes the fixed entities do not escape Divine knowledge but unlike the former they are

partially knowable to human beings under certain conditions. Just like for Eriugena God

is unknowable to all creatures, whether these belong to the second division of nature or

to the third one, in Ibn ‘Arabi> God remains unknown to the entities fixed in their non-

existence.

144

This second limitation is unfortunately misunderstood by some English translations but is fortunately

discerned by major Arabic and Persian commentaries on the work. Both R.W Austen and Caner Dagli

have understood the words يكون مستصحبا � to mean that an individual is granted the unveiling when he is

not in the company of others but in his solitude, which does not make much sense. Arabic commentaries

of Qays}ari> (Tehran: Sharikat Intisha>ra>t e ‘Ilmi, 1375), 681, Mus}t}afa> Ba>li> Za>deh, Sharh} Fus}u>s} al-H}ikam

(Beirut: Da>r al-Kutub al-‘ilmiyyah, 2002), 121 and the Persian commentaries by H}asan Za>deh Amooli,

Mumidd al Himam (Tehran: Waza>rat e Farhang e Isla>mi, 1378 A.H), 227; Ta>j al-Di>n Khawa>rzami>

(Tehran: Intisha>ra>t e Mawla>, 1368) I: 331 all understand that the unveiling is not permanent but is

bestowed some time or the other.

Page 114: 988S

102

4.2.54.2.54.2.54.2.5 Entities Created or Eternal?Entities Created or Eternal?Entities Created or Eternal?Entities Created or Eternal?

It is abundantly clear that Eriugena’s primordial causes are creatures which God has

created in His Word. Are the fixed entities which we are comparing with these are also

created? On the face of it, the fixed entities are not the creatures. Since the fixed

entities are primarily the objects of Divine knowledge it is not possible to maintain that

they are created as Divine knowledge is eternal (ref. in deo nihil accidit). The doctrine

of fixed entities does not mean that God makes the world twice, but that he makes what

he knows already and the object of knowledge is already there, God did not make it in

Him but eternally knew it. Ibn ‘Arabi> expresses the fact that fixed entities were not

created by saying that “He invented us actually not that He created in himself our

exemplar” and “there is no existentiation in exemplar.” (إختراع في المثال �) (Fut. I: 91)

This means that that the exemplar which is the fixed entity does not itself originate

through an act of existentiation, only spatio-temporal objects, or “effects” in Eriugenian

language. This interpretation fits in with Ibn ‘Arabi>’s statement about the entities that

“these did not attain existence from Him.” (Ibid. II: 246) Ibn ‘Arabi> also characterizes

fixed entity as the eternal relationship of eternity “which has no beginning” (أول لھا �).

(Ibid. II: 55) In order to preclude the inference that creation took place in the state of

fixity or nonexistence Ibn ‘Arabī interprets the Qur’a>nic verse, “Will not man remember

that we created him aforetime, when he was nothing (19:67) by saying, “That is, ‘we

determined it in its state of thingness’, toward which was directed His command, ‘to

another thingness’ for the Divine dictum, ‘Our only speech to a thing, when we desire it,

is to say to it “Be!” and it is.’” (Ibid. II. 62) So creation in nothingness does not mean

the creation of fixed entities but determination of the object about to be created in the

spatio-temporal world. We have already seen him extending the meaning of creation to

Page 115: 988S

103

include pre-creation Divine determination. All this shows that fixed entities are not

created according to Ibn ‘Arabi>.

Now this characterization of fixed entities creates a gap between them and the

primordial causes, a gap which can make the comparison less plausible. We submit that

this gap is bridged by bringing out the meaning Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> assign to the

word “creation” or the phrase “being created.” Ibn ‘Arabi> is not denying the createdness

of fixed entities in the sense in which Eriugena affirms the createdness of his primordial

causes. If the meaning of Eriugenian “creation” is made explicit then an express

affirmation of the creation of fixed entities in that sense can be found in Ibn ‘Arabi>.

It is well known among Eriugena scholars that when he uses the term “creation”

in the context of God’s creation of the creatures, he does not understand by it “temporal

making out of nonexistence” but “self-manifestation and moving from incorporeal to

corporeal.”145 At DDN III 689A Eriugena himself tells us that the Divine nature creates

itself that is, allows itself to appear in its theophany. Hence creation for Eriugena is

theophany and by “theophany” Eriugena understands, primarily, “the appearance of

God,” (DDN I: 446C-D) or “ineffable descent of the Supreme Goodness … into the

things that are, so as to make them to be.” (Ibid. 678: D)146 Therefore, when he says that

something is created by God what he actually means is that it is a theophany.

145

Dermot Moran, The Philosophy, 177. Moran has admitted that Eriugena considers primordial causes as

theophanies and this position Eriugena adopts, in Moran’s view to get round a difficulty regarding their

status. In Moran’s words, “What kinds of beings have the primary causes? If they are real beings they

would seem to impose an intermediate ontological level between God and the created effects, if they are

not fully real and are merely Divine appearances then it is difficult to speak of creation.” Ibid. 262. 146

A detailed comparison of “theophany” with some terms used by Ibn ‘Arabi> will be undertaken in

chapter 7.

Page 116: 988S

104

It can be argued that in all instances where Ibn ‘Arabi> negates the creation of

fixed entities he only negates that in the sense of “making out of nonexistence” and that

his fixed entities, like primordial causes are theophanies. Ibn ‘Arabi> writes at one place

that “the fixed entities, being مظاھر, relate to the Divinity in same relationship.” (Fut. II:

95) Speaking about a fifth universal reality identified with “the manifestation of Divine

realities and lordly (ربانية) forms in the fixed entities” Ibn ‘Arabi> says that these latter

are مظاھرالحق . (Ibid. II: 103) With reference to the fixed entity of a human being he says

that it is what “God took as a مظھر and manifested Himself in it.” (Ibid. II: 513) The

word مظھر with which Ibn ‘Arabi> is identifying the fixed entities is grammatically a

noun of place derived fromظھور, which means “manifestation, outwardness,

appearance.”147 Notice how close this term is to “theophany” which, as Michael Sells

explains, is derived from two Greek words, theos (god) and phanio (bringing to light,

make appear) and it is “an appearance or manifestation of deity.”148

Thus it is clear that the fixed entities although not created in the sense of “being

made” they are created in the sense of being “theophanies” that is to say the loci of self-

disclosure of God ( مجالى. مظاھر ). In this way the apparent gap between Eriugena’s

primordial causes and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s fixed entities, vanishes.

4.2.64.2.64.2.64.2.6 Order and Hierarchy within the Fixed Entities Order and Hierarchy within the Fixed Entities Order and Hierarchy within the Fixed Entities Order and Hierarchy within the Fixed Entities

We saw that the primordial causes are arranged in a hierarchical order, a hierarchy

which some writers argue is not objective but only in mind. Is there any order within the

fixed entities and if there is, what is the principle of this order, hierarchy or something

147

See William C. Chittick, The Sufi Path of Knowledge, 89. 148 See Mystical Languages of Unsaying, 43.

Page 117: 988S

105

else? We shall try to answer these questions presently. Let us begin by trying to

understand the following obscure passage from Al-Futu>h}a>t al-Makkiyah:

… order in the entities of possible things in the state of their fixity became

manifest with the wisdom of the Wise, as there is no possible thing attributed to

a possible thing but that it can be attributed to another possible thing for itself.

However Wisdom required arranging it with its decree as it is according to its

time and state in the state of its fixity. This is the knowledge which has become

specific to the Real, the Most Exalted and which from Him was not known (by

anyone). With it the decree appeared in the order of entities of possible things in

the state of their fixity before their existence. Hence the Divine knowledge

became connected to them according to that at which the Wise One had ordered

it, so wisdom bestowed the possible thing what it was in the fixity, the contrary

of which is permissible and the order gave the knower the knowledge that the

affair is like this so he does not give existence except in accordance with what it

is at in fixity which is the order of the Wise one according to decree of Wisdom.

(Fut. IV: 258)

This passage implies that there is order within the fixed entities. The primary

intent is not to claim the existence of order but it is to show that order is based on

Divine wisdom and the difference and relation between Divine wisdom (الحكمة) and

Divine knowledge (العلم) and the order of fixed entities is being discussed as an instance

or playground of these two qualities. According to Ibn ‘Arabī, every possible thing that

is related to one thing can be or could have been related to another possible thing. This

means that the actual order between the entities is not necessary, it could have been

otherwise. But still it is one specific order, that is to say, for instance, that entity x

actually is related to y and not to z although it could have been related to z. That is why

Ibn ‘Arabī says about this order near the end that its “contrary is permissible ( يجوز

The next point that needs to be clearly understood before making sense of the ”.(خ\فه

Page 118: 988S

106

full passage is the subordination of Divine knowledge to Divine wisdom149 and to reality

as it is created by the latter. It is well known principle of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s metaphysics that

knowledge, Divine or human, does not determine but is determined by the thing known

as it is in itself (العلم يتبع المعلوم). In the present case Ibn ‘Arabī is telling us that the reality

of the order of fixed entities is created by wisdom upon which Divine knowledge is

based as much as He is the Knower. Now we can understand his words: “Hence the

Divine knowledge became connected … according to decree of Wisdom.” One final

thing remains to be clarified. If knowledge is subordinate to wisdom then why does Ibn

‘Arabi> identify both by saying in the beginning, “this is the knowledge which…”? The

answer is that the word knowledge (العلم) does not mean the relation between knower and

the known but is to be understood as “the known”, that is to say, knowledge here means

“an item of knowledge.” So Ibn ‘Arabi> is trying to tell us that the wisdom behind a

particular order is known only to God.

There is one particular type of order which Ibn ‘Arabi> is careful enough to negate

within the fixed entities. This negation is so emphatic that it might give the impression

that he is negating any order and hence contradicting himself. Ibn ‘Arabi> has written:

Entrance into the thingness of wuju>d happens only in order. The affair of the

things in the thingness of fixity is otherwise, because none of them is ordered.

After all their fixity is described by eternity without beginning, and there is no

order in eternity without beginning, no priority, no posteriority. (Ibid. III: 280;

trans. SDG. 194)

Despite appearance Ibn ‘Arabi> here is not negating order per se in fixity but only

temporal order and the reason he gives is quite obvious. Since fixed entities are objects

149 This is the case only from this particular point of view, otherwise Ibn ‘Arabi> also provides for the

priority and generality of knowledge as compared to wisdom. For more see Fut. II: 237, 243 etc.

Page 119: 988S

107

of Divine knowledge they are eternal and eternal things cannot be arranged in temporal

order. So Chittick’s remark on this passage that “Although the entities follow an order

in wuju>d, they have no order inasmuch as they are fixed entities in God’s knowledge”150

is not adequate. It would have been more appropriate for Chittick to include the passage

from Fut. IV: 258 and present a synthetic view of order within the fixed entities.

Unfortunately, he does not take this passage into account, so his view remains one-

sided.

The order about which Ibn ‘Arabi> speaks is the network of particular relations in

which fixed entities and their existent counterparts are found. This general concept of

order as relation implicitly contains the concept of hierarchy.151 We find Ibn ‘Arabi>

providing for the hierarchical order within the fixed entities in the Fus}u>s} by providing

that

What is first encompassed by God’s Mercy is the thingness of that entity which

existentiates Mercy through Mercy. So the first thing encompassed by Mercy is

itself; then the thingness indicated; then the thingness of all existents that exist,

which have no end… (Fus}. 177; trans. Ringstones, 219)

As the final sentence of this passage implies, the Divine names demand the

existence of entities existentiating them and that the highest entity is the one that

existentiates the name “Merciful” or the attribute Mercy. Then come all other fixed

entities which are existentiated through Divine command “Be!” Our reading of the

above passage differs from Izutsu’s since he thinks that “the thingness of that entity…”

150

William Chittick, The Self Disclosure of God, 194. 151

It is significant that the Arabic word ترتيب which is used by Ibn ‘Arabi> is translated by Chittick in his

Self Disclosure as order and in Sufi Path of Knowledge as hierarchy. He explains that this is because the

Arabic word for level (رتبة) is derived from the same root as the term (ترتيب). See his Self Disclosure of

God, 194.

Page 120: 988S

108

refers to Divine Essence. He thinks that this sentence implies that “by the very first

manifestation of its own Mercy, the absolutely Unknown-Unknowable turns into a

‘thing’ (شئ).” 152 We think that this reading involves certain difficulties. For one thing, it

makes Divine Essence subject to and manifestation of an attribute or a Divine name and

it is well known that according to Ibn ‘Arabi> names and attributes belong to a level

below that of Essence. In his technical terminology the level of absolute Divine essence

is called “unity (أحدية)” while that of names and attributes is called “oneness (واحدية)”

Furthermore to make the Essence locus of manifestation is itself problematic. The

difficulty can be seen clearly if we take into account what has been said even by Izutsu

himself in the same work. At one place he has admitted that the Absolute in its Essence

is completely independent of the world which also implies that it has no need of the

names.153 Secondly, he has related to us that there is no manifestation at the level of

unity (أحدية)154, so how can something belonging to the next level convert the Essence

into a thing?

In our opinion the reading of Caner Dagli is more plausible and his reasons for

understanding thingness as the fixed identity of the name “Merciful” are sound.

According to him Ibn ‘Arabi>’s saying that the first thing encompassed by Mercy is itself

means that “The All-Merciful is given an immutable identity over which it is Lord.” 155

His interpretation should be understood in the light of the fact that fixed entities

themselves are manifestations of the Divine names just like Eriugena’s world does not

152Sufism and Taoism, 119-120.

153 See Ibid. 101.

154 See Ibid. 24: “The tajalli of the Absolute begins to occur only at the next stage, that of the oneness

(wa>hidiyyah) which means unity of the Many.”

155 Dagli, Ringstones, 220n.3.

Page 121: 988S

109

directly participate in the superessential good but in its participation, i.e. primordial

cause.156 Hence there is hierarchy within the immutable identities and the climax is

constituted by the entity that is governed by the Name al-Rah}ma>n. Entities of other

Divine names come next to it, which then have their existent entities in the

spatiotemporal world.

Having seen that there is order and hierarchy within the fixed entities we are in a

position to construct a table of hierarchy of fixed entities and compare it to that of the

primordial causes and see what we can learn from this comparison. We submit that the

former hierarchy can help us understand a dark area within the latter. It will be

remembered that we had to place a question mark on the relation between the supreme

Good and its first participation, by participation in which good-through-itself has its

being. This confusion in Eriugenian hierarchy can be removed by learning a lesson from

the parallel hierarchy within the fixed identities, since, here the logic of first (Divine

names), second (fixed entities) and third (existent things) participations is clear. This

logic consists in the fact that Divine names and attributes require the existence of their

subjects, just as being “father” requires the existence of “son.”

156 “Each existent has an identity which is itself the form of a Divine Name that determines what it is. It

is this name which is the lord of that specific existent.” This comes as a comment on Ibn ‘Arabi>’s saying

“Every existent has a specific lord in God.” Caner Dagli, Ringstones, 79n.1.

Page 122: 988S

110

Table: Fixed Entities in HierarchyTable: Fixed Entities in HierarchyTable: Fixed Entities in HierarchyTable: Fixed Entities in Hierarchy

4444....2.72.72.72.7 The Intermediary Status of Entities The Intermediary Status of Entities The Intermediary Status of Entities The Intermediary Status of Entities

As it is obvious from the diagrammatic presentation of the hierarchy, and as Professor

Izutsu and others have elaborated,157 the fixed entities occupy an intermediary status

between God and the world. This fact is very important from the comparative

perspective which concerns us here. We can compare the intermediary ontological status

of fixed entities with Eriugena’s primordial causes on this particular juncture from two

points of view. As it will appear, from one standpoint two concepts stand apart but from

the second the gap between them is reduced. On the one hand Eriugena claimed that

nothing interpolates between the Creator and the Creatures which implies that the

primordial causes are not to be considered intermediary between these two poles.

Comparing the fixed entities to primordial causes from this point of view it might be

concluded that the former’s explicit intermediary character marks them off from the

latter, but if we look at the fact that the fixed entities according to Ibn ‘Arabi> are firstly,

not existent and secondly, not outside Divine principle but exist within Divine

consciousness as objects of knowledge the difference between the two is reduced.

Fortunately however, we also possess another Eriugenian perspective on the primordial

157

See Sufism and Taoism, 158-163.

DIV

INITY

DIV

INITY

DIV

INITY

DIV

INITY

Level ILevel ILevel ILevel I Ah}adiyyah| Absolute Divine Essence

God

Barzakh

Level IILevel IILevel IILevel II Wa>h}idiyyah | Names and Attributes Determining Determining Determining Determining the

Essence

FIXITY

FIXITY

FIXITY

FIXITY

Level ILevel ILevel ILevel I Supreme Fixed Entity ManifestingManifestingManifestingManifesting the “Merciful”

Level IILevel IILevel IILevel II Fixed Entities ManifestingManifestingManifestingManifesting all other Divine Names

EXISTENCEEXISTENCEEXISTENCEEXISTENCE

الوجود

Existent Entities in this World ManifestingManifestingManifestingManifesting the fixed

entities

World

Page 123: 988S

111

causes according to which they are intermediaries between the Creator and creature.

This perspective becomes clear when we understand the latter as referring to “effects of

the primordial causes” and excluding the causes themselves. From this perspective

Eriugena says that “the other goods do not through themselves participate in the

supreme and substantial Good but that which is through-itself the first participation of

the Supreme Good. And this rule is uniformly observed in the case of all primordial

causes.” (DDN III: 622 B-C) From this perspective there is no difference between the

primordial causes and the fixed entities, the intermediary status of which has been

described by Izutsu thus: “[b]riefly stated the plane of archetypes (=entities)158 occupies

a middle position between the Absolute in its absoluteness and the world of sensible

things. As a result of this peculiar ontological position, the archetypes have the double

nature of being active and passive, that is, passive in relation to what is higher and

active in relation to things that stand lower than themselves.”159 Note that the

simultaneous activity and passivity of the entities is parallel to the primordial causes

which on the one hand participate in (to be more exact, “are participations of”) what is

higher than them and on the other hand are participated in by what is lower than them,

that is to say their effects.

158

Izutsu translates عيان الثابتةEاas “permanent archetypes” which is based in his view, I think unjustified

view, that the entities are universals and as such “remind us of the Ideas of Plato”. See Sufism and

Taoism, 164. We think that none of the texts which Izutsu presents as evidence in favor of his position

deals with fixed entities, rather all of them talk about “Divine attributes”, which, as we have seen and as

Izutsu himself asserts, are one level above the entities. Besides, inter-relation among the Platonic ideas is

that of “one over many” but for Ibn ‘Arabi> each particular existent has one particular fixed entity which is

not shared by or participated in by other individuals. So there is a “one-to-one” relationship between

fixed entities and existent ones. There is no difference between a fixed entity and existent entity except

that the latter has existence while the former does not have it, as Ibn ‘Arabi> has written, “the thing in the

state of its immutability is identical to the thing in the state of its existence, except that God has clothed

it in the robe of existence through Himself.” Fut. IV: 320. 159 Sufism and Taoism, 159.

Page 124: 988S

112

4.2.84.2.84.2.84.2.8 Essence, Names and EntitiesEssence, Names and EntitiesEssence, Names and EntitiesEssence, Names and Entities

It will be recalled that in the diagrammatic presentation of Eriugenian hierarchy we

highlighted an unanswered question. Since the table representing cosmic hierarchy

conceived by Ibn ‘Arabi> also consists of parallel levels, two levels of divinity and two of

fixed entities, same question arises as to the relation between the first two levels of

divinity namely, that of essence and names. We saw that the fixed entities are forms of

Divine names160 while things existing in this world of space and time are manifestations

of the fixed entities. At one place Ibn ‘Arabi> uses the shadow metaphor to describe the

relation of fixed entities to the existent entities and tells us that the existent entities are

shadows of fixed entities, and as a shadow cannot exist in the absence of light, the light

that illuminates the fixed entity giving rise to its shadow in the form of existent entity

is Divine name Al-Nu>r (the Light). (Fut. III: 47) Thus Ibn ‘Arabi> enlightens us here

about all the members of hierarchy, and what is more, explains the relationship between

first two levels with a clarity that was missing in Eriugena. Hence we get here, firstly,

non-delimited being, the name Al-Nu>r, the fixed entities and existent entities. Ibn

‘Arabi> tells us that the fixed entities are shadows of Non-Delimited Being in respect of

the Name Al-Nu>r. This expression “من” which we translate as “in respect of” is the key

to solution. It indicates that there are many respects from which the non-delimited being

can be related to creatures at the level of delimitation or determination ( مرتبة

تقييدال\التعيين ). So the relation of Divine names to the Absolute is that of perspectives or

relations. They are, as Izutsu has aptly described them, the channels through which the

Absolute articulates itself at the first state of manifestation.161 The notion of “aspects”

or “perspectives”, which Ibn ‘Arabi> himself uses, makes an implied reference to the

160

See footnote 157 above. 161

Izutsu, Sufism and Taoism, 160.

Page 125: 988S

113

existent entities, from whose point of view the Absolute can be seen through these

aspects.

4.2.94.2.94.2.94.2.9 The Highest fixed entityThe Highest fixed entityThe Highest fixed entityThe Highest fixed entity

Eriugenian cosmic hierarchy gives priority to Supreme Goodness while the highest fixed

entity according to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s hierarchy is the one that is essential form of the Name

“All-Merciful.” In other words, the fixed entity of Mercy is the foremost and all other

entities are found through and due to it.

Although for Eriugena the specific order of primordial causes is not the only one

and we have just seen that from one point of view Ibn ‘Arabi> assigns fundamental

cosmogonic role to Divine name Al-Nu>r, it is pertinent to compare goodness with Mercy

spoken by Ibn ‘Arabi>.

Eriugena said that “it is a property of the Divine goodness to call things that

were not into existence.” (DDN III: 627C-D) We can compare this to Ibn ‘Arabi> when

he says that “Every identity has an existence that it seeks from God, His Mercy applies

universally to each identity. Through his Mercy, by which He shows mercy upon each

He accepts their desire for existence so existentiates them.” (Fus}. 177; trans.

Ringstones, 219)162 This comparison reveals that the function of Goodness for Eriugena

and that of Mercy for Ibn ‘Arabi> is one and the same since it consists in bestowing

existence upon the non-existents. We can conclude that although for Eriugena it is

goodness-through itself that is the highest primordial cause and for Ibn ‘Arabi> this place

162 Note that the Arabic word for existence is derived from the root و ج د while that for “munificence” is

from ج و د though these are different roots but they contain same letters in different order. As Titus

Burkhardt has explained, between such roots there is sometimes certain continuity. See his essay “The

Impact of the Arab Language” published in Mirrors of the Intellect: Essays on Traditional Science and

Sacred Art (Lahore: Suhail Academy, 2001), 240 n.6.

Page 126: 988S

114

is given to Divine mercy, the function of these respective concepts are in both cases

ontological and not passional or ethical.

4.2.104.2.104.2.104.2.10 Unity and Multiplicity Unity and Multiplicity Unity and Multiplicity Unity and Multiplicity

Eriugena showed that the multiplicity of primordial causes is only from the perspective

of their effects and as far as their principle i.e. God is concerned they are one and simple

and not multiple. Since oneness of God (التوحيد) is one of axioms for Ibn ‘Arabi> and since

fixed entities are forms of Divine names and Divine names are multiple in contrast to

the absolutely one Divine Essence, the problem of the multiplicity is also important one

for Ibn ‘Arabi>. Interestingly, his solution is not very different from Eriugenian in which

a reference is made to the “effects.” Ibn ‘Arabi> maintains that “the entity of Being is

One, while the properties (أحكام) are diverse in accordance with the diversity of the

immutable (=fixed) entities, which are the “others” without doubt, though in the

immutability, not in existence, so understand.” (Fut., II: 519; trans. SPK, 91) The

concept of properties plays here the same function that is played by “effects” in

Eriugena’s response to the issue of multiplicity of primordial causes. The difference

however is that, for Ibn ‘Arabi>, this multiplicity is not absolutely isolated from Being,

but relates to it at a certain level. Thus he says speaking from a specific perspective that

Being becomes manifest only in accordance with the properties of the fixed entities.

(Ibid) Fundamentally, the entity of Being is one, and we know that Being is God, hence

God is one. However, unlike Eriugena, Ibn ‘Arabi> does not try to make unity latently

include multiplicity, with references to monad or the circle’s centre, but makes the latter

dependent upon the effects of the perspectives through which to look at Being. He

seems to be less afraid of multiplicity than is Eriugena. So he admits the multiplicity of

the entities in the state of fixity and for the person who contemplates God through the

Page 127: 988S

115

entities God becomes manifest through the different colors, so to speak, of those

entities.163

There is yet another facet of the fixed entities, mentioned already, which gives

us an additional clue. Pointing out that fixed entities are non-existent, William Chittick

has explained the above-quoted passage by saying, “Being is one and Manifest. Hence

multiplicity and distinction arise from the properties of the nonexistent things, which

are many and non-manifest.”(Ibid.) Ibn ‘Arabi> simultaneously makes use of both clues,

that the Divine essence, “He-ness” is beyond relations and thus multiplicity, and that it

is the fixity, i.e. non-existence, of the entities which makes the Essence into multiple

relations. (See Fut. II: 94; trans. SPK, 313)

4.2.114.2.114.2.114.2.11 Entities and the WordEntities and the WordEntities and the WordEntities and the Word

According to Eriugena’s allegorical interpretation of Genesis, creation of primordial

causes “in the beginning” and “in Divine wisdom” means that these were created in the

Word of God, personified in the person of Christ. A comparison of primordial causes

with fixed entities must take into account this particular characteristic of the former.

Can we get over this issue by simply saying that personified word of God is peculiar to

Christianity so no parallels can be found in non-Christian, especially Muslim thought? It

seems that this is not the case since the Christian conception of word of God (logos) can

plausibly be compared with the concept of Perfect Man (ا8نسان الكامل) or Muh}ammadan

Reality (الحقيقة المحمدية), but in the present context this comparison is not very helpful,

since the plane of fixed entities is not contained by this since Ibn ‘Arabi> speaks of an

entity of the perfect man as well. (Ibid. II: 642) Hence there is no possibility of claiming

163 This is an epistemological interpretation of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s saying that “such a person observes in the very

being of the Real the properties of the fixed entities.” Fut. II: 519.

Page 128: 988S

116

that Muh}ammadan Reality contains the fixed entities of everything. So at this point the

fixed entities are unlike the primordial causes and this is an important non-reducible

difference between the two conceptions.

4.2.124.2.124.2.124.2.12 Infinity of EntitiesInfinity of EntitiesInfinity of EntitiesInfinity of Entities

Although Eriugena’s primordial causes are creatures (in the sense of being theophanies)

they are infinite. The fixed entities are also infinite. One obvious reason for the infinity

of fixed entities is that they are “objects of Divine knowledge” and Divine knowledge is

infinite. Another more philosophical reason is presented by Ibn ‘Arabi>. According to it,

immutable entities are the form of Infinite Being which It sees in the mirror of Non-

Delimited nothingness and consequently the form is as infinite as the Infinite Being

whose form it is. (Ibid. III: 47; trans. SPK, 205)164 Accordingly, fixed entities are infinite

since they exist because of coming of two infinites face to face, absolute existence and

absolute non-existence. In addition to being quantitatively infinite and “eternal without

beginning” (أزلية), Ibn ‘Arabi> points out at various places, the fixed entities are also

“eternal without end” (أبدية): “Subsistence is the permanent state of a servant which does

not end because non-existence of his fixed entity is one of the impossible things.”(Ibid.

II: 516)

4.2.134.2.134.2.134.2.13 Fixed Entities and EvilFixed Entities and EvilFixed Entities and EvilFixed Entities and Evil

As the creation of primordial causes in wisdom raises the question of evil for Eriugena

so does the notion of fixed entities for Ibn ‘Arabi>. In the context of creation of the world

out of the fixed entities he makes an important remark in the twenty-first chapter of the

Fus}u>s} (Ringstones). Although he shares Eriugenian adherence to the principle that evil 164 Also see ibid. III: 46 where Ibn ‘Arabi> talks about infinity of the Supreme Barzakh which is the

presence of fixed entities and IV: 295 where he writes about them that “limitation and finitude is

imagined regarding them while they are infinite.”

Page 129: 988S

117

is non-existence and thus privation,165 he does not appeal to it when talking about evil in

the context of fixed entities and he could not have, as we shall see at present. Let us see

how the problem arises for him in this specific context. Fixed entities are eternal objects

of Divine knowledge. However creation takes place when spatio-temporal existence is

bestowed upon a particular fixed entity. Now since there are existent entities which can

be considered evil, the question is why God bestows existence on fixed entities of evil

things since this makes Him directly responsible for these evil existents. To respond that

evil is nonexistent will not do since the nonexistence that is evil is absolute non-

existence166 and not the relative non-existence that is the world and we are talking about

the existence of evil in this world. So why does God clothe the fixed entities of things

having evil accidents with the robe of existence? Let us first note how Ibn ‘Arabi>

defines “evil.” Evil according to him is “failure to reach one’s desire (غرض) and what is

agreeable (م\ئم) to one’s nature.”(Ibid. III: 389) This definition clearly brings out that

something is evil with reference to someone who looks at it with a specific desire or

having a specific nature. Now Ibn ‘Arabi> simply states that all fixed entities request

existence and since Divine mercy applies universally to each identity: “Through His

Mercy, by which he shows mercy upon each, He accepts their desire for the existence of

their identities, and so existentiates them….The attainment of some purpose or the

agreeability with one’s nature are not taken into account as far as it is concerned; indeed

what is agreeable and what is not are all encompassed by the Divine Mercy in

165

For instance see Fut. III: 373: “evil is only the nonexistence of good.” 166

Ibn ‘Arabi> has written, “The Real possesses non-delimited being (إط\ق الوجود) without any

delimitation. He is sheer good without any evil. He stands opposite non-delimited nothingness (إط\ق العدم),

which is sheer evil without any good.” Ibid. trans. SPK-290. Ibn ‘Arabi> also recognizes that although the

world is good in its essence evil occurs to it as an accident since it does not stand in the level of Necessary

Being which is sheer good. See Fut. III: 389.

Page 130: 988S

118

existence.” (Fus}. 177; trans. Ringstones, 219-220) This is tantamount to accepting that

God is indirectly responsible for the existence of accidentally evil things. Thus at

another place in the same work Ibn ‘Arabi> writes: “To Him the whole affair shall be

returned (XI: 123), thus applying to the blameworthy as well as the praiseworthy.

Naught is there but the praiseworthy and the blameworthy.” (Fus}. 60)167 Now, does this

solve the problem of evil? It endorses one horn of the dilemma that constitutes the

problem of evil but at the same time relativizes and subjectivises the concept of evil

itself.

In the light of the above conducted comparative analysis, it can be safely

concluded that Eriugena’s concept of primordial causes and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of

fixed ideas share most of their characteristic features and perform almost identical role

in their respective cosmologies, that of mediating Divine Self and spatio-temporal world

in the context of creation. Hence, one is presented as “the secret folds of nature” from

which things that are said to be proceed and the other is described, alluding to the

Scriptural expression, as “the treasuries of everything with God” wherefrom God

“reveals” things in accordance with His knowledge and wisdom. In some way, both pre-

determine the nature and scope of spatio-temporally existing things. This is clear from

Eriugena’s calling his causes “predestinations” and “foundations and principles of all

nature and it parallels in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s arguing for the absolute power of the fixed entities

and with comparing them with materia prima. Moreover, both concepts are

167 Ibn ‘Arabi> cannot be taken to contradict what he himself says in many places commenting on the

saying of the Prophet “The good, all of it is in Thy hands, while evil does not go back to Thee!” that evil

becomes manifest from the side of a possible thing not from the direction of God (Fut. III: 289) since

there is difference between good/evil and praiseworthy/blameworthy similar to the one between the good

and the right.

Page 131: 988S

119

ontologically rooted in Divine wisdom, since Eriugena talks about the causes as being

comprehended by God in “his super-eminent” wisdom and Ibn ‘Arabi> defines his fixed

entities as the objects of Divine knowledge. This, however, is not to deny that there are

differences, apparent and real, between two doctrines.

Page 132: 988S

FiveFiveFiveFive

MacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosm----IIII:::: Participation Participation Participation Participation and and and and DivineDivineDivineDivine RootsRootsRootsRoots

In the present chapter we wish to raise the following question: How does Eriugena

conceive the spatiotemporal world (his third division) and relates it to God (the first

division of nature) and are there any interesting parallels between him and Ibn ‘Arabī?

We intend to show that our both thinkers conceive the world and its relationship

to the Divine in remarkably similar, if not identical, manner. Eriugena is not primarily

interested in physics, that is to say, nature of the world. He is more interested in relating

it to its principle and Ibn ‘Arabī’s cosmology shares this spirit. Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>

agree that the world is symbolic of the Divine. Eriugena says “For it is in my opinion

that there is no visible or corporeal thing which is not the symbol of (significet)

something incorporeal and intelligible. (DDN V: 865D-866A) Similar remarks are

scattered here and there in the works of Ibn ‘Arabi>, according to whom the Arabic word

for the world العالَم derives from the same root as “ع\مة” which means that the world is a

signpost for God. (See Fut. II: 473; trans. SDG, 3). The scriptural basis of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

teaching that the entities of the cosmos are signs of God is the Qur’a>n 41: 53 which

reads “We shall show them Our signs upon the horizons and in themselves until it is

clear the them that He is the Real,” (Fut. II: 151; trans. SPK, 93). Moreover, he

comments on the Qur’a>n 22: 32, viz., “Whoever magnifies God’s waymarks, (شعائر هللا)

that is of God weariness of the hearts” by saying that “there is no entity in the cosmos

Page 133: 988S

121

that is not one of God’s waymarks (شعائر)168 inasmuch as the Real has put there to

signify Him.” (Fut. III: 527; SDG, 10). It goes without saying that these words of Ibn

‘Arabi> resonate completely what we saw Eriugena saying above.

We can understand Eriugena’s position on God-World relationship through an

analysis of his two terms, participatio and theophania. The present chapter deals with

the former while we address the latter in the following chapter. If we look at God-World

relationship from the world’s side, it participates in Him but if we view from God’s side,

He manifests Himself in the world. These two ways can be symbolized respectively as

the upward way “from world to God” and the downward one “from God to the world. It

can be shown that the Eriugenian concepts “participation”and “theophany” correspond

respectively in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought to “Divine Roots doctrine” and “al-tajalli>.”

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabī alike diverge from usual views regarding creation and are not

ready to accept that the world was created out of absolute nothingness. An investigation

of this question is bound to lead into questions of the nature of nothingness and the

discussion of Six Divine Days of creation (Hexaemeron) according to Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi>. We however would not discuss these issues here. We have already made some

comments on the former question in the first and the third chapters. As for the

Hexaemeron, Eriugena presents his more or less allegorical exegesis of Genesis and

168 The word sha‘a>’ir (sing. Sha‘i>rah) is one of the Qur’a>nic terms the basic meaning of which is “a place

[of the performance] of religious rites and ceremonies of the pilgrimage,” and “all those services which

God has appointed to us as signs; as the halting (wuqu>f) [at Mount ‘Arafa>t]…” Edward William Lane, An

Arabic English Lexicon, (Beirut: Librarie Du Liban, 1863), part IV: 1561. Although Chittick has rendered

this word plausibly as “waymark” in many translations of the Qur’a>n it has been translated as “symbol.” It

is also very important to notice that the word comes from the same root as that of shu‘u>r meaning “to

know, understand, be cognizant of something.” Since derivatives from a single root share some element of

the meaning, sha‘i>rah or sha‘a>r is an object which lets one “know of” another thing. Hence, the word

sha‘a>’ir is equivalent of “symbols.”

Page 134: 988S

122

concentrates on what was created on each day. Ibn ‘Arabī seems to be more interested in

the container rather than the content, that is to say, he has to say more on the nature of a

“Divine day” than what God did during that day. One of the reasons for this difference

is that although both Genesis and the Qur’a>n mention creation in six days, the latter

does not give details of the Divine work of each day. However, it provides that “Each

day He is in some affair” and this interests Ibn ‘Arabī more than the contents of the

Hexaemeron. Moreover, the views of the latter have been competently analyzed and

discussed in a recent work by Mohamed Haj Yousef.169

One of the important themes that Eriugena discusses in the first book of his

DDN and which should have been discussed in our third chapter is the relationship

between God and ten categories (Categoriae Decem). We however are going to analyze

this subject in the present chapter since it cannot be understood without elaborating Ibn

‘Arabi>’s doctrine of Divine roots first.

5.15.15.15.1 Eriugena Eriugena Eriugena Eriugena on on on on ParticipationParticipationParticipationParticipation

5.1.15.1.15.1.15.1.1 Participation: History and Context Participation: History and Context Participation: History and Context Participation: History and Context

Eriugena properly inaugurates discussion of the third division of nature in Book III

630A-634 with an account of “participation.” This concept of participation links the

first division of nature (God) to the second (Primordial Causes) and the second to the

third (the world). In view of this function we do not see any reason to agree with

169

See his book Ibn ‘Arabi>: Time and Cosmology (London: Routledge, 2008), chapter 3, 73-100.

Page 135: 988S

123

Dermot Moran’s view that Eriugena’s “more complex relations of being and non-being

make the concept of participation less relevant.”170

Eriugena is neither the first nor the last thinker to use the term “participation.” It

already was used by Plato to explain the relationship between intelligible forms and

their sensible instances.171 In spite of being critical of Platonic forms, Aristotle himself

used the concept while referring to human participation in the essential life.172 The

concept was popular with Neo-Platonism inherited by the Alexandrines, latter Christian

Platonists like Saint Augustine and his Franciscan followers. It also lurks behind the

medieval proofs for the existence of God from the degrees of being, truth, goodness and

perfection. This fact is epitomized by Augustine who advises: “Look at what you see

and seek Him, Whom you do not see.”173 After Eriugena it was also used by Saint

Anselm in his lesser known a posteriori proofs for the existence of God and by Saint

Thomas Aquinas “who held that things participate in Divine perfections by an imitation

according to an ordered proportion corresponding to their respective modes of being.”174

The contemporary ears are also not completely unfamiliar with this term since Paul

170 Dermot Moran, The Philosophy, 234 n. 23. The way Michael Sells has used the notion in his recent

study for understanding negative theology also shows importance of this concept for Eriugena. See

Mystical Languages, 34-63. 171

Sr. M. Annice, “Historical Sketch of the Theory of Participation,” New Scholasticism, 26 (1952): 49-

79. She concludes the sketch by remarking that “Participation by the diminished and imperfect in the

whole and perfect is held by all outstanding philosophers from Plato to St. Thomas.” Platonic Caveat

(Phaedo 100d) is emphasized by David C Schindler, “What’s the difference? On the Metaphysics of

participation in a Christian Context,” Saint Anselm Journal, 3(2005), 46. 172

“Historical Sketch,” p. 56. The reference is to Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book XII, chapter 7, 1072a. 173

Quoted in Ibid. 60 from the Saint’s Sermo CXXVI. Available online at mb-

soft.com/believe/txuf/august7d.htm (last visited on 12-03-2009.) 174

“What’s the difference?” 46.

Page 136: 988S

124

Tillich used it to differentiate between “sign” and “symbol.”175

The concept of participation, however, has been criticized by some Christian

theologians as well. David Schindler thinks, that while being suitable to Christian

thinking, participation also leads away from the Christian Weltanschauung, firstly since

its implied reference to the “beyond” twists participation to pantheism and secondly it

seems to deprive the finite, temporal, and physical world of any reality of its own.176

These two problems have not forced any major dissent within Christian tradition, since

the only dissenting voice we hear is that of Søren Kierkegaard in 19th century. In our

opinion, out of the two issues raised by Schindler only the former posits a serious

question, but can be answered satisfactorily from the standpoints of both Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabī. As for the second problem, it seems to be begging the question. One has to

show first why it is necessary for “the finite, temporal, and physical world” to have “any

reality of its own” especially in the context of Christian worldview. If participation

means metaphysically, as Schindler himself says, “that one thing has what it is with and

indeed after and in pursuit of, another: it has its reality by virtue of something other

than itself” then precisely this is the intent of “impassibility,” recognized by Christian

philosophical tradition as one of the metaphysical Divine attributes. Impassibility also

implies “the ontological dependence of the world on spiritual/intellectual realities and

ultimately on God” something which is expressed by participation, as Schindler himself

admits.177

175 Paul Tillich, “The Nature of Religious Language,” in Theology of Culture (New York: Oxford

University Press, 1964), 54-55. 176

Schindler, “What’s the difference?” 2. 177

Ibid. 1.

Page 137: 988S

125

5.1.25.1.25.1.25.1.2 Participation and “All that is (Participation and “All that is (Participation and “All that is (Participation and “All that is (omne quod estomne quod estomne quod estomne quod est))))”

Eriugena uses “participation” in order to divide “everything that is” (omne quod est)

into the following three categories: God, the primordial causes and the world. He

divides everything that is into four categories, participant, participated in (i.e. object of

participation), participation and that which is both participated and participant

simultaneously. The Supreme principle of all things is only participated since it

participates in nothing above itself while the first member of this division, created

nature, is participant only since there is nothing below it which should participate in it.

Naturally the realm of primordial causes is what simultaneously participates in the first

division of nature while it is participated by the third division. (See DDN III: 630A-

630D)

Thus Eriugena gives three levels of being, the highest, the lowest and the

intermediary. It goes without saying that there is nothing above the highest to be

participated in and below the lowest to participate in it. Hence it is only the

intermediate region that can both be participated and participant. It is difficult,

however, to see the point of including “Participation” as a member of this division.

Sheldon-Williams remarks that it is rather general name for things “which are” since

things which are neither participants nor participated nor both would not fall under

“things which are” 178 However, this remark is not of much help since it interprets

Eriugena as having included the whole as one of its parts.

178

See Sheldon-William’s note 5 to the text of DDN.

Page 138: 988S

126

5.1.35.1.35.1.35.1.3 Participation: Literal and metaphorical explication Participation: Literal and metaphorical explication Participation: Literal and metaphorical explication Participation: Literal and metaphorical explication

Eriugena understands that the Latin term particpatio has a reference to “taking parts”

(partem capere) which would imply the existence of “parts” in the thing participated.179

Therefore he not only makes it explicit that “participation is not the taking of some

part, but the distribution of the Divine gifts and graces from the highest to the lowest

through high orders to the lower” (DDN III.631A) but also prefers its Greek

counterparts metoxe and metoxia for its explication. These Greek terms have the

advantage of being free from any reference at all to “parts.” He reads metoxe as if it

were “meta ex ousia” as meaning “having after” or “having second” while metoxia as

simply “meta-ousia”, that is, “after-essence” and concludes that participation means

nothing but “the derivation from a superior essence of the essence that follows [after it]

(ex superiori essentia secundae… deriuationem) and the distribution from that which

first possesses being to that which follows it in order that it may be.” Moreover, his

understanding of participation as something’s coming after another is close to the literal

sense the prefix met gives in compositional words, “after” or “behind.”180 Eriugena’s

exposition, therefore, falls somewhere between literalism and metaphor. Although he

rules out the “partem capere” element he does accept the “having after” sense which is

implied by the Greek met.

Eriugena also resorts to metaphors in order to elaborate the meaning of

participation. He first presents an arithmetical metaphor and says that “between all the

natural orders from the highest to the lowest the participations by which they are related

are similar, just like as the proportions between the terms of numbers, that is, among the

179

See Schindler, “What is the Difference?” 180 See ibid. 1.

Page 139: 988S

127

numbers when they are constituted under one principle, are similar. (DDN III: 631A) He

characterizes “participation” with the distribution of “gifts by which every nature

subsists and graces by which every subsisting nature is adorned.” So the distribution of

these gifts and graces “flows down by degrees from the Supreme Source of all good gifts

and graces through the higher orders to the lower as far as the lowest of all.” (DDN III:

631A-B) This flowing to all orders is important since Eriugena emphasizes that “none of

the nature not even the lowest must be thought to be denied participation in a Divine

grace proportionate to itself.”(Ibid) However, Divine gifts and graces other than being

and well being, like sense, reason, wisdom, “do not descend to the lowest” since, for

instance “life does not extend to the lowest order.” (DDN III: 631C)

Eriugena then draws our attention to the way all radii are already present and

united within the central point of a circle and it is only when they approach toward the

circumference that they become separated. Thirdly, we are given the example of a river

which first flows forth from its source, and through its channel the water which first

wells up in the source continues to flow always without any break to whatever distance

it extends. In the light of these metaphors, the concept of participation can be

considered tantamount to being included in something and then having come out of it.

Out of these three metaphors the last mentioned is most physical of all and reveals this

meaning most clearly. The number and centre metaphors also point in this same

direction since the lines that connect the central point to circumference are contained by

the point itself and all the numbers greater than the unit are nothing but aggregates of

the self-same unit. Therefore, to say that the relationship between the world, primordial

causes and God is that of participation would mean that the world is “derived from” a

higher essence, i.e. the primordial causes, which in turn derive from God. We can also

Page 140: 988S

128

say that whatever the world is, it is with or after the primordial causes and God and

whatever the primordial causes are they are with and after God. As for God Himself

whatever He is or has, is with Himself and in Himself. As Eriugena says, God is God per

essentiam, whereas man is God per participationem. (DDN III: 145C) Similarly, he

states later that the human nature is not the Light but only participates in light. God

alone is the Light per se; we are light per participationem. (Hom. 0292C-D) Moreover

participation implies existence of participant in God and in grace and Eriugena explains

that the participation of effects in the causes means that the causes are nothing but the

essence of all things. (DDN III: 145C)

5.25.25.25.2 Ibn ‘ArabIbn ‘ArabIbn ‘ArabIbn ‘Arabī on “on “on “on “DivineDivineDivineDivine Roots”Roots”Roots”Roots”

5.2.15.2.15.2.15.2.1 DivineDivineDivineDivine Roots and Roots and Roots and Roots and Omne quod estOmne quod estOmne quod estOmne quod est

Ibn ‘Arabī states: “There is nothing (ما ثم) but the Divine presence (الحضرة ا8لھية)

comprising of the Essence (الذات), Attributes (الصفات) and actions (فعالEا).” (Fut. II:

173)181 The essence is God as He is in Himself without reference to anything else. The

attributes/ Divine names, being identical to the Divine Essence, do not have substantial

existence but simply are relations between Divine Self and creatures. Ibn ‘Arabi> equates

“Divine actions” with the created world. The first two constituents of the Divine

presence, essence and attributes, to the exclusion of the world, may be called in Ibn

‘Arabī’s language “the Divine side” (الجانب ا8لھي).

181 See Frithjof Schuon, “The Five Divine Presences”, in Form and Substance in the Religions (New

Delhi: Third Eye, 2005), 51. At page 55 Schuon identifies “God as creator” i.e. Being with “the degree of

Divine qualities” which obviously is a reference to “Attributes” mentioned by Ibn ‘Arabi>. For more on

five presences also see William Chittick, “The Five Divine Presences: From al-Qu>nawi> to al-Qays}ari>” The

Muslim World, 72(1982), 107-128.

Page 141: 988S

129

We can now formulate our question concerning God-world relationship more

precisely: What relationship the world (Divine actions) has to the Divine Side (Divine

Essence + Names/Attributes), according to Ibn ‘Arabi>? Ibn ‘Arabi> states that “no

property (حكم) becomes manifest in existence except that it has a root (أصل) in the

“Divine side” by which it (i.e. the property) is supported.” (Fut. II: 508) At another

place he writes that “There is no existent possible thing in everything-other-than-God182

that is not connected to the Divine relationships and lordly realities (الحقائق الربانية) which

are known as “the most beautiful names.” Therefore every possible thing (ممكن) is in

grasp of a Divine reality.” (Fut. II: 115; trans. SPK, 37)

Before exploring the doctrine of Divine roots we need to make a few

observations by way of clarification and comparison regarding what has just been

mentioned.

Firstly, it can be observed that Eriugena’s participation and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Divine

roots theory are both set in the context of a classification of totality. Eriugena talks

about omne quod est while Ibn ‘Arabi> uses the negative expression for the same thing

namely, “there is nothing but…” However, there is certain divergence between the two

which must not be lost sight of. Whereas the three members of Eriugenian division

stand in same relation to each other, namely participation, in Ibn ‘Arabi> a participation-

like relationship holds only between the Attributes/Names and the World. As far as the

Essence and Attributes/Names are concerned the question of relation does not arise for a

relation would necessitate substantial distinction which in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s theology does

not appear. Since Ibn ‘Arabi> believes in Essence-Attributes identity and moreover, to

182

ماسوى هللا This is the name Ibn ‘Arabi> gives to cosmos.

Page 142: 988S

130

ask “what relation there is between something and a relationship” would be susceptible

to the third-man argument and will thus lead into infinite regress.

Secondly, the tripartite division of Divine presence (totality) can be considered

to contain origins of the broader doctrine of five Divine presences which came to be

generally accepted in the Sufi circles. Five Divine presences are, in ascending order:

human realm (الناسوت), realm of royalty (ملكوت), realm of power (جبروت), Realm of the

Divine (ھوت�) and Ipseity (ھاھوت).183 The reduction of five to three presences can be

made more conveniently if we have before us Schuon’s description of these, in an

ascending order, as 1) material states, 2) animistic states, 3) angelic states, 4) qualified

being and 5) Beyond-being. Here the first three presences can be reduced to one, namely

the cosmos, or as Schuon himself would have preferred, “existence.” We would thus

acquire three presences namely Existence, Being and Beyond-Being which correspond to

Ibn ‘Arabī’s Actions, Attributes and Essence.

Thirdly, the identification of one component of the Divine presence (viz. actions)

with the world seems to imply that the latter is included in God, an apparently

pantheistic position. However, this inclusion need not necessarily be interpreted as

pantheism. For one thing, Ibn ‘Arabi> does not go for out and out God-world identity but

assigns to the world the mid-way-house of being He/not-He ( � ھو| ھو ( . (Fut. II: 379) He

relates deiform world184 to God via his doctrine of Divine roots. Moreover, the orthodox

teachings of Islamic tradition leave ample room for maintaining the inclusion thesis

without verging on pantheism. Schuon has excellently related the idea with Qur’ānic

183

The translation of the terms is taken from Schuon “Five Divine Presences,” 53 184

Ibn ‘Arabi> believes that God created the world upon His image. See Fut. II: 557. Further details are

discussed in the seventh chapter.

Page 143: 988S

131

teachings. He writes, encapsulating Ibn ‘Arabi>’s spirit185 “But in reality it is the

Principle which envelops everything; the material world is only an infinitesimal and

eminently contingent content of the invisible Universe. In the first case, God is—in the

language of the Qoran—the ‘Inward’ or the ‘Hidden’ (الباطن), and in the second, He is

the ‘Vast’ or ‘He who contains’ (الواسع), or ‘He who surrounds’ (المحيط).” 186 In the third

chapter we have noticed that Eriugena himself extends the definition of God to include

Divine manifestations and the world187 and we have seen that he always attempts to

retain a distinction between God and the world.

Fourthly, when Ibn ‘Arabi> says that “Nothing becomes manifest in existence ( في

,he wants us to take the expression “in existence” quite seriously. Therefore ”…(الوجود

only positive realities are rooted and not privations like darkness and ignorance. This is

why he refuses to connect ignorance to some Divine root as it “is a quality pertaining to

non existence while the names only bestow existence they do not bestow nonexistence.”

(Fut. II: 592; tr. SPK 55) Talking about the Divine roots of levels he writes that levels

themselves do not have Divine roots since they are only “relations” only their

“designation” is so rooted in divinity. (Fut. II: 468-469)188

Now, if there is a Divine root for every manifestation, contemplation can

proceed in two ways. One can start from a specific Divine name or attribute and

185

Ibn ‘Arabi> writes: “‘Surely He encompasses everything’ (41:54) in the cosmos. ‘Encompassing’ (إحاطة)

a thing conceals that thing. Hence the Manifest is the Encomapsser (المحيط)… Hence within the

Encompasser that thing—that is, the cosmos—is like the spirit within the body…” Fut: II: 151; trans.

SPK, 93). 186

Schuon, “Five Divine Presences,” 51. 187

See chapter 3 section 1 with reference to DDN I: 448B. 188

It is somewhat perplexing, though, to find out the ontological criterion under which “designation”

pertains to existence but “relation” does not.

Page 144: 988S

132

contemplate what stems from that root in the world. Or one could proceed the other way

round. Ibn ‘Arabi> seems to have elaborated his doctrine of Divine roots in both ways.

From the World to the Names From the World to the Names From the World to the Names From the World to the Names

Throughout his al-Futu>h}a>t Ibn ‘Arabi> tries to discover the Divine roots of various

phenomena. He starts by some of the microcosmic or macrocosmic features and tells us

what their Divine roots are. Two basic features of the world, plurality (الكثرة) and

polarity (الزوجية) have roots in the Divine side. Multiplicity is a manifestation of the

diversity of Divine names and attributes while polarity is rooted in the fact the all

attributes submerge under two basic ones namely, mercy (الرحمة) and wrath (الغضب).

Divine names are either names of beauty (الجمال) or those of majesty (الج\ل). The former

imply the similarity or proximity of the Divine to the cosmos while the latter show

Divine transcendence. This division is ultimately reducible to “God’s two Hands”

spoken of in the Qur’a>n.189 It is not difficult to see that the cosmic polarities especially

the male-female polarity, are rooted in this fact about the Divine nature.

Multiplicity and polarity respectively imply two further features, hierarchy

and these are also rooted in the Divine nature. Ibn ‘Arabī (منازعة) and contention (مفاضلة)

writes: “The Divine Names that are attributed to the Real have various levels in

attribution. Some of them depend upon others, some of them supervise others and some

have a more inclusive connection to the cosmos and more effects within it than the

189

Sachiko Murata summarizes this as follows: “In brief, they (i.e. Ibn ‘Arabi> and his followers)

understand the “two hands” to indicate a polar relationship in God Himself. That He should create Adam

with these two hands indicates that He employed this polarity to bring the microcosm into existence. The

microcosm itself, made in the image of God, must have “two hands” in the same qualitative sense that

God has them, not only physically. And so also must the macrocosm, which is the microcosm’s mirror

image.” Sachiko Murata, The Tao of Islam: A Sourcebook on Gender relations in Islamic Thought (New

York: SUNY, 1992), 82

Page 145: 988S

133

others.” (Fut. II: 34) For example the Divine name “Alive (الحي)” has the “most

tremendous degree” among the names since it is the precondition of the other names. 190

(Fut. IV: 228; trans. SPK, 49) This hierarchy is the Divine root of cosmic hierarchy. The

Divine root of the cosmic conflict is the fact that Divine names having diverse

properties demand diverse effects within the cosmos. The name “Avenger” )المنتقم (

demands the occurrence of vengeance in its object, while the name the Compassionate

demands its removal. (Fut. II: 93; trans. SPK, 55) Hence, the cosmic plurality, polarity

hierarchy and contention between various levels are all rooted in the divinity.

Other cosmic realities whose Divine roots Ibn ‘Arabī mentions include

prophethood (النبوة) which is rooted in the Divine name “The All-Hearing (السميع)” (Fut.

II: 252), all human character traits rooted, especially love, in Divine character traits

(Fut. II: 241),191 possibility of human transmutation in different forms rooted in Divine

transmutation(Fut. III: 44), changes of states (حوالEتغير ا) (Fut. II: 385), days (يامEا)192

and the present moment (الوقت) (Fut. II: 539) rooted in God’s being “upon a task

everyday (Qur’a>n: 55:29), productivity of and receptivity towards effects in Divine

responsiveness (إجابة) (Fut. II: 453), feeling of inner sweetness (Fut. II: 507) and spiritual

movement rooted in God’s rejoicing and joyfully receiving his repenting servant (Fut. II:

366) and cosmic contraction (القبض) which is rooted in God’s describing himself with

attributes of the creatures especially in being embraced by a believer’s heart. (Fut. II:

509)

190

This means that God has other essential attributes (like Hearing, Speaking, Will, Power etc.) because

He has Life. 191Vide Fut. II: 241 viz.: “For God is the Necessary Being through Himself while man exists through his

Lord, so he acquire s existence and character traits from Him.” Trans. SPK, 287. 192 For discussion of relationship between solar days and Divine days in Ibn ‘Arabi> see Mohammed Haj

Yousef, Ibn ‘Arabi> time and Cosmology , 73-77.

Page 146: 988S

134

From the Names to the WorldFrom the Names to the WorldFrom the Names to the WorldFrom the Names to the World

In the long 198th chapter of al-Futu>h}a>t Ibn ‘Arabī starts with specific Divine names and

tells us what originated within the cosmos through their particular attentiveness )التوجه( .

In the main he mentions 28 Divine names but some further names occur within the

discussion of the first name البديع. Heterogeneous phenomena manifest from these Divine

names: principles, levels of reality, letters of Arabic alphabet, heavenly spheres and

bodies, days of the week, prophets and genera etc. Through the attentiveness of the

name “The Life-Giver (الحي)” originated “what appeared in water, the letter (س) and the

stars included in the Sagitta.” The angels were created through attentiveness of the

Overpowering (القوي) (Fut. II. 466) while man was created through that of the Uniter

It is easy to see the connection between these Divine names and (Fut. II: 468) .(الجامع)

feature of things which originate through their attentiveness. Water is the principle of

life, as the Qur’a>n says that “From water we made everything alive.”(21:23) hence its

connection with “The Alive”; the Jinn are subtle creatures hence their connection with

“The Subtle”; the angels are the most powerful of God’s creatures hence they originate

through the attentiveness of “The Overpowering” and it is only man who unites within

him the Divine image and the cosmic image hence his origin is from the name “The

Uniter.” However, it is less clear how certain names, particular days, Arabic alphabets,

heavens, and heavenly bodies, spiritual states can be connected with specific Divine

names. Ibn ‘Arabī remarks that all Divine names related to cosmos have effect in

everything and he specifies one of these only because it has more powerful and effective

rule over it. (Fut. II: 468) This implies that understanding the “sense” of Divine names is

not sufficient for understanding its cosmological connection since the affair is not

entirely amenable to rational investigation but is based on spiritual unveiling.

Page 147: 988S

135

Ibn ‘Arabi> maintains that more than one Divine name concurs in an individual

substance. For example, he provides two Divine names “الغنى” and “الدھر” which jointly

attend to the manifestation of days etc. He has explained earlier that in it there are

numerous aspects requiring a corresponding number of Divine Names. For the reality of

its creation (إيجاده) requires the Name, the Powerful ; while the aspect of its perfection

[ظھوره] requires the Name, the Purposer; and the aspect of its manifestation [إحكامه]

requires the Name, the Seer[البصير], the Observer [الرائي] and other [such Names]. (Fut.

I: 100)193 The first two aspects i.e. existence and perfection remind one of Eriugena’s

distinction between Divine gifts and graces in terms of some-things’ being and well-

being. Thus the relationship between a Divine root and its manifestation is not one-to-

one relation like the one between Platonic forms and objects. This qualifies William

Chittick’s view that what corresponds to the Platonic Ideas in Ibn al-‘Arabi> is the

Divine names. 194 (SPK 84)

5.2.25.2.25.2.25.2.2 DivineDivineDivineDivine Roots and “participation” literally understoodRoots and “participation” literally understoodRoots and “participation” literally understoodRoots and “participation” literally understood

Like Eriugena Ibn ‘Arabi> would certainly have ruled out the world’s literal taking part

in God since the Divine names which relate the world to God as Divine roots are not

parts of divinity but aspects and relationships. However, as stemming from their Divine

roots, existents might be considered to participate in Divine side in the sense of “being

derived from higher essences.” Things can be considered to “participate” in the sense of

“having with” and “coming after,” not only in the sense of temporal succession but also

of ontological dependence. The world’s “coming after” Divine roots is explicit from the

way Ibn ‘Arabī understands the Qur’a>n 15:21: “There is nothing whose treasuries are

193

The relevant text has been translated by Gerald Elmore, “Four Texts of Ibn al-‘Arabi> on the Creative

Self-Manifestation of the Divine Names.” JMIAS, XXIX(2001), 23. 194

See SPK, 84. In as much as their archetypal function the Divine names do correspond to Platonic ideas.

Page 148: 988S

136

not with us but We only send down thereof in due and ascertainable measures.” This

demands, according to him, that “He bring them out from treasuries which are with him,

that is, from an existence which we do not perceive to an existence which we do

perceive.” (Fut. II>: 587) 195 In one of his prayers Ibn ‘Arabi> says, “From Him (عنه) and

with Him (به) is the existence of everything.”196 This expression of world’s being

brought and, especially, sustained into existence by God is given a characteristic

metaphysical touch by Ibn ‘Arabī in his commentary upon the cosmology of alphabet.

He uses the first letter ا to symbolize Divine Essence and ب to symbolize attributes.197

This is very apt since ا, whose numerical value is 1, is the only letter which never

attaches itself to another, something designating the absolute transcendence of the

Essence. Commenting on Abu Madyan’s saying “I have never observed anything except

that I observed ب written over it” Ibn ‘Arabī says that this letter accompanies all

existents which points to the fact that everything appeared “with Him” (به). (Fut. I: 102)

One of the meanings of saying that the cosmos is rooted in divinity is to say that it

appear within it, an apparent parallelism with participation.

5.2.35.2.35.2.35.2.3 DivineDivineDivineDivine Roots and Metaphors of “Participation”Roots and Metaphors of “Participation”Roots and Metaphors of “Participation”Roots and Metaphors of “Participation”

The metaphors Eriugena presented for explication of “participation” are also relevant

for the comparison. His first metaphor highlights the principle that all orders of reality

are identical in being participants but differ from each other in other respects. His view

that “none of the orders of nature how-low-so-ever can be denied participation in Divine

195 Although treasuries do not directly refer to Divine names but to the fixed entities, they do so indirectly

as the entities are nothing but manifestations of Divine names as we saw in the previous chapter. 196

Ibn ‘Arabi>, Awra>d al-Ayya>m wa al-Laya>li> (Oman: Da>r al-Fath}: 2003), 46. Trans. Pablo Beneito and

Stephen Hirtenstein, The Seven Days of the Heart (Oxford: Anqa Publishers, 2008), 28 (with slight

modification). 197

Souad Hakim, Al-Mu‘jam al-S}u>fi (Beirut: Dandarah, 1981), 181.

Page 149: 988S

137

gift or grace appropriate to itself” reiterates the same principle. This principle finds its

application in Ibn ‘Arabī’s cosmology at two levels. First, the Divine names are one in

referring to Essence and in determining it but they are different in view of their specific

meanings. Second, in the created world everything is different and separate from others

in respect of its quiddity but identical to them in being a manifestation of God. Likewise

Ibn ‘Arabī considers all existence “Divine symbols” (شعائر) and says that nothing of the

world can be discarded or held in contempt. (Fut. III: 527) He, however, would have

corrected Eriugena’s claim that graces like sense and life do not descend to the lowest

levels of existence since in his view there is nothing in the world which is not alive and

glorifying its Lord with an eloquent tongue. (Fut. II: 504)

Having discussed Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine of Divine roots in general and having

looked at some of its specific examples we now turn to an important issue that is very

dear to Eriugena and which Ibn ‘Arabi> solves in the light of his Divine roots theory,

namely the question of applicability or non applicability of ten categories to God.

5.35.35.35.3 God and God and God and God and Categoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae Decem

5.3.15.3.15.3.15.3.1 Eriugena on God and CategoriesEriugena on God and CategoriesEriugena on God and CategoriesEriugena on God and Categories

After many digressions Eriugena comes at last to treat the question of applicability of

ten categories to God in I: 562 which was asked many passages ago. His position is

clearly stated at the beginning of the long dialogue that ensues. The Alumnus declares

that the categories cannot apply to God since God is neither genus nor species nor an

accident while the application of categories would have implied God’s being a genus.

(See DDN I: 463C) The Nutritor happily accepts this as being in line with the

requirements of via negativa he has propounded in preceding passages, but the Alumnus

himself starts wavering in the assertion he has made. Hence he asks that the category of

Page 150: 988S

138

relation should be allowed to be properly predicated to God. This request is not granted

since it is contrary to an assertion already made and agreed upon, namely, that “nothing

can properly be predicted of God.” So this category is also predicated of God

metaphorically. But after discussing the nature of various categories the alumnus again

shows hesitation in accepting that action and affection are not properly predicated of

God, who according to Scripture and patristic writings is said to have made the world,

to love and be loved etc. One of the examples that the Alumnus cites is the saying of

Christ: “Whoso loves me shall be loved by my father and I shall love him and shall

reveal myself to him.” In response Eriugena implies that although “he loves” seems to

be an active verb in fact it is in fact not so since “he who loves or desires suffers himself

while he who is loved or desired acts” therefore we cannot take “God loves” literally

since that would imply that He is moved by His love and God’s loving someone is a

metaphorical expression for His being loved. (DDN I: 505A)198

As is shown by this specific example the categories do not really apply to God

and whenever they are found to be applied in the Scripture they should be taken as

metaphors. However, there is one limitation in the analysis Eriugena presents for God’s

loving; although it shows that “action” cannot apply to God properly it anyway applies

the category of “affection” to God understood in the sense of “being object of an action”

since it replaces “loving” with “being loved.”

198

Interestingly, Ibn ‘Arabi> looks at this issue from a quite different angle and makes a point contrary to

Eriugena’s. He claims that God can love creatures but creatures cannot love Him. Since “love is related to

the non-existent, so no love is conceivable from the creature to God.” (Fut. II: 113) The point being made

is that since love for something or someone implies lover’s lack of that thing or distance from that person

and since it is God who truly is and the creature never was, only God can love the creature by bringing it

from nonexistence to existence.

Page 151: 988S

139

5.3.25.3.25.3.25.3.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on God and CategoriesIbn ‘Arabi> on God and CategoriesIbn ‘Arabi> on God and CategoriesIbn ‘Arabi> on God and Categories

Ibn ‘Arabi> gives the initial impression that he dislikes the whole discussion as a part of

which the question arises. In his discussion of the combination between the standpoints

of incomparability and similarity Ibn ‘Arabi> observes regarding the debate among

Muslim theologians on the applicability of Categoriae Decem to God that it feels like

the proverb says “I hear the grinding, but I do not see any flour.” (Fut. II: 116; trans.

SPK, 75) At another place he combines this distaste for the discussion of categories and

God with the practical demands of Sufi piety. Indulging into such discussion is not

recommended since it distracts one from focusing on “one thing needful” that is,

“knowing oneself” and makes one do something God has prohibited to do, namely

contemplation upon Divine Essence. The Qur’a>n says, “God warns you regarding His

self.” (Ibid. III: 81-82)

However, many interesting and insightful comments are scattered on the

question of God’s relation to the categories throughout his major as well as some shorter

works. To begin with Ibn ‘Arabi> does not hold a substantial view of the nature of

categories but considers them to “appear with the appearance of substance for itself

when the Real brings it out from its hiddenness.”(See ibid. III: 11)

Quite contrary to Eriugena who holds that the categories apply really to

creatures and metaphorically to God Ibn ‘Arabi> is of the opinion that all are attributes of

God’s perfection and only secondarily apply to other things. (See ibid. II: 473; trans.

SPK, 75–76) Hence Ibn ‘Arabi>’s position regarding the applicability of specific

categories to God is different from Eriugena’s but, interestingly, his understanding of

the nature of these categories and their correlation is same as Eriugena’s. Thus the

Page 152: 988S

140

relational status that he awards to all the categories is indirectly comparable to

Eriugena’s considering the categories to be incorporeal. (DDN I: 478D-479A)

Secondly, as John Marenbon has observed, Eriugena’s was not a pure

Aristotelian version of categories since according to it the first category substance

(ousia) was not an individual of such and such a kind but the most inclusive of all

classes and is conceived as substrate to which accidents are attached.199 That Ibn ‘Arabi>

also understands ousia as a substrate is obvious from the diagrammatical presentation of

the ten categories in his Insha>.200 It appears that for Ibn ‘Arabi> too this category is the

most basic of all and relates to them like a substrate does. This presentation consists of

a circle representing Primordial Matter which comprises all knowable realities, existent,

nonexistent and those which are beyond existence/non-existence. In that diagram ousia

is given the central position while the rest of ten categories form a circumferential circle

around it:

199

John Marenbon, “John Scottus and the Categoriae Decem” in W. Beierwaltes, ed., Eriugena: Studien

zu seinen Quellen, (Berlin: Carl Winter Universitäts Verlag, 1980), 122. At DDN I: 492C Eriugena says

concerning ousia that “it subsists in its subdivisions eternally and immutably as a whole that is always

together and all its subdivisions are always together as an inseparable unity in it.” 200

See Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir, 24-25. The diagram given here is scanned from Fenton-Gloton translation of

Insha>’ cited earlier from Ibn ‘Arabi>: A Commemorative Volume.

Page 153: 988S

141

Ibn Ibn Ibn Ibn ‘‘‘‘AraAraAraArabi>bi>bi>bi>’s Circle of s Circle of s Circle of s Circle of Categoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae Decem

Coming to the question of the applicability of categories to the Divine nature, as

a point of departure we could consider Ibn ‘Arabi>’s negative response that in view of the

fact that nothing makes God known in positive terms, “there is nothing of the ten

categories, except for a verified passivity and a definite activity.” (Fut. II: 211; trans.

SPK, 349) Hence none of the ten categories can be really applicable to Divine reality

except for the fact that from the passivity observable in the nature one is able to infer

the existence of an agent. But this agent himself remains beyond knowledge. At another

place Ibn ‘Arabi> indicates that he does not construe Divine agency in the sense of first

cause. While discussing the ritual of stoning the Satans, which Ibn ‘Arabi> symbolically

interprets as a dialogue between the pilgrim and Satan, he negates applicability of the

Page 154: 988S

142

word “cause” to divinity since whenever there is cause, effect must be there, while God

was there and there was nothing beside Him, at least in the sense of spatio-temporal

existence. (See ibid. I: 720). Ibn ‘Arabi>, however does not stop at this negative

standpoint but recognizes a correspondence between God and the world characterized by

the categories. We submit that this is an application of one of his Divine roots

doctrine.201 The correspondence between categories and the nature of God is established

in at least two places in al-Futu>h}a>t, at I: 180 and III:11.

At III: 11 after providing that the world consists of the entities of substances and

the relation that follows them, i.e. the remaining nine categories, Ibn ‘Arabi> provides the

principle that since the world is a copy of its archetype in Divine knowledge and Divine

knowledge of the world is identical with Divine self-knowledge the world must be upon

the image of the creator. Then he immediately mentions Divine qualities that

correspond to the ten categories by which the spatio-temporal world is characterized and

crowns this enumeration by commenting that the categories constitute the form of the

world.

If we combine this list of correspondence with the one mentioned at Fut. I: 180

we might see the former as explaining latter and bringing out certain important

differences. This can be seen from the table given below.

201

This can also be seen as an implication of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s commitment to principle-manifestation

continuity along with a discontinuity, which finds its expression in his synthesis of incomparability and

similarity.

Page 155: 988S

143

Table: Table: Table: Table: DivineDivineDivineDivine Roots of Roots of Roots of Roots of Categoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae DecemCategoriae Decem

CategoriesCategoriesCategoriesCategories

المقو�ت

The Roots in the The Roots in the The Roots in the The Roots in the DivineDivineDivineDivine SideSideSideSide 8صول في الجانب اEلھيا

I.I.I.I.180180180180 III. III. III. III. 11111111

SubstanceSubstanceSubstanceSubstance Essence Essence

QuantityQuantityQuantityQuantity Names Number of His Names

QualityQualityQualityQuality Self-

Disclosures

“Each day He is upon some task”(55:29)

“We will finish with you, O mankind and

jinn.”(55:31) “The All-merciful sat upon the throne.”

(20:5).

PlacePlacePlacePlace Sitting upon “He came to be in a Cloud” (h}adi}th) “And

He is God in the Heavens.”

TimeTimeTimeTime Eternity He is God in the Eternity

PosturePosturePosturePosture Al-

fahwa>niyah

Allah spoke directly to Moses

(4:164)

RelationRelationRelationRelation Relation “Master of the Kingdom”

(3:26); Creator of Creatures

ActionActionActionAction Munificence A Balance in His Hand, lifts it and lowers it

AffectionAffectionAffectionAffection Manifestation

in forms of

beliefs

He is called upon and Responds; Asked and gives; Is

asked forgiveness and forgives

Page 156: 988S

144

Some Observations on the Correspondence between Some Observations on the Correspondence between Some Observations on the Correspondence between Some Observations on the Correspondence between DivineDivineDivineDivine Nature and Ten Nature and Ten Nature and Ten Nature and Ten

CategoriesCategoriesCategoriesCategories

Posture:Posture:Posture:Posture: The root mentioned for posture at I: 180 is الفھوانية which is a term used by Ibn

‘Arabi> to denote “Face to face address of the Real in the imaginal world.” ( م المثالعال )

(Ibid. II: 128) God’s direct address to Moses is mentioned at III.11 as an instance.

Quality and PlaceQuality and PlaceQuality and PlaceQuality and Place:::: The table reveals that one root is assigned to different categories.

Hence “sitting upon” (ا8ستواء) is assigned to quality202 in the first list and to “place” in

the second one. It seems that istawa>’ itself does not answer the question regarding qua

as is obvious from the question placed before Ma>lik b. Anas regarding the quality (كيف)

of istawa>’.203 It is possible to take istawa>’ in the text quoted from Ibn ‘Arabi> not as a

single word but as an abbreviation for the whole statement in which it occurs.204 In that

case the Divine root of istawa>’ not necessary the quality denoted by istawa>’ but some

other fact meant by the words “The All-Merciful sat upon the throne.” From some of his

comments upon these words we do get an idea of the quality to which the word istiwa>’

points. In this case, by mentioning istawa>’ as the Divine root of quality, Ibn ‘Arabi> can

be taken to be pointing to mercy, which clearly corresponds to quality.

StateStateStateState: : : : The category of state is missing from both lists. It is worth our while to try to

complete this list by finding out what Divine root “state” could have. In the circle of

202

At another place Ibn ‘Arabi> has explicitly claimed that istawa>’ is an attribute of God. See Fut. III: 162.

A quality according to Aristotle’s Categories (8a:25), is “that in virtue of which people are said to be such

and such.” The Works of Aristotle (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica Inc.) II. 13. 203

See Abd al-Kari>m al-Shahrista>ni>, Al-Milal wa al-Niùal (Beirut: Da>r al-Ma‘rifah, 1975), chapter 3, Al-

úifa>tiyyah. Certainly “sitting,” even though it is not a very accurate translation of istawa>’, is mentioned

by Aristotle himself as instantiating the category of position. See Categories, 2a. 204

This strategy can be justified by invoking analogy with Ibn ‘Arabi>’s treatment of the category of

quantity in the two lists given in the table. Although at I: I80 the root for quantity is just “names” we

know from III: 11 that this word is just an abbreviation for “number of names.”

Page 157: 988S

145

categories that we came across in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir, he uses the word حال

for the category in question. This word is introduced from philosophy and Kala>m into

Sufism to denote a spiritual state, corresponding to theophany or Divine self-

manifestation. Normally, Ibn ‘Arabi> uses this word in its original linguistic meaning and

at other times as a technical Sufi term. Since a term retains some of its original meaning

even when it is taken over by some specific discipline, we hope to learn something about

the relationship between Divine nature and “state” as one of the ten Aristotelian

categories. We hypothesize that we could find the Divine root of “state” in the Qur’a>nic

words quoted by Ibn ‘Arabi> at III.11 as providing Divine root for the category of

quality. Before we attempt to find textual evidence for our hypothesis from Ibn ‘Arabi>

let us recall that Ibn ‘Arabi> has derived roots of two categories from a single Qur’a>nic

text in the parallel lists of Divine roots shown in the table above. Secondly, Ibn ‘Arabi>

has mentioned the Qur’a>nic verse against the category “quality” and according to him,

“the qualities are states.” (Fut. I: 195)205 At another place while discussing love he

considers the states as subordinate to quality and speaks of one quality’s having

multiple states. (Fut. II: 337) 206 Although at a number of places Ibn ‘Arabi> mentions

that the fact that there are Divine roots of “state,” and for that matter all other

categories, in “Divine states (أحوال إلھية)”, this does not mean that the predicate can be

applied directly to God, but that there is something about God which causes the

characterization of spatio-temporal world with “state.” In the Eriugenian language of

negative theology we can say that God is beyond states or creator of states. This can be

205 At Fut. II: 305 Ibn ‘Arabi> identifies this term just after quoting Qur’a>nic verse on Divine tasks. At II:

368 he relates the Divine states with certain characteristics mentioned in some traditions like God’s

joyfully receiving His servants and happiness upon repenting servant. 206 Ibn ‘Arabi> writes about the Sixth Pole (القطب السادس) that “he does not take any of his states except

from his Lord, so his states are the states of his Lord.” Ibid. IV: 82.

Page 158: 988S

146

seen from what Ibn ‘Arabi> expresses by connecting difference in human states and

Divine relations.

If it is asked why Divine relations have become different we would reply, “due

to difference in states!” … so the one whose state is hunger prays, “O All-

Provider” and the one whose state is drowning prays “O Helper.” (Fut. I: 265)

In this passage it is apparent that states characterize engendered existence but are

connected to Divine nature. Here we also find Ibn ‘Arabi> referring to the Qur’a>nic verse

about Divine tasks in the context of states, which encourages us to use it as a source of

their Divine root.

In view of these textual sources, we can finally submit that that the root in the

Divine side of the appearance and existence of “state” is the fact the God is upon some

task every day. This “being upon” is the archetype for the symbol of “state.”

TimeTimeTimeTime: : : : The primary consideration within God-time problematic is the fact that time is

taken to essentially imply movement, mutability, corruption, finitude and death207 while

God has to be free of all these imperfections. On the one hand this consideration entails

that God is beyond time, on the other hand, it necessitates spiritual attempts to

overcome temporality. As far as Eriugena himself is concerned, since he recognizes that

time implies mutability 208 and since he has maintained that the categories do not

properly apply to God, he had to conclude that “time and place are to be counted among

the things that have been created” and since God is not to be counted among the created

things He cannot properly be called time and place. (See DDN I: 468C) In view of its

supra-temporality Eriugena frequently uses the words “now and always” (nunc et

207

See Dermot Moran, “Time and Eternity in the Periphyseon,” in History and Eschatology in John

Scottus Eriugena and his Time, ed. James McEvoy and Michael Dunne, (Leuven, University Press, 2002),

489. 208

Eriugena writes, “Time is the exact and natural measure of movement and pauses.” DDN V: 890.

Page 159: 988S

147

semper) to denote Divine eternity. (See ibid. IV: 860) However, Eriugena identifies

creation of the world with Divine self-creation and his superlative theology demands

that we transcend this positive attribution. As Moran expresses it, “For Eriugena, time

belongs to the self-expression, self-externalization, self-manifestation or self-creation of

the creator God and also to the self-articulation of nous in sensibility.”209 In a famous

passage Eriugena mentions the supratemporal’s making himself temporal

(supertemporalis temporalem). (See DDN III: 678C) Therefore while creating the spatio

temporal world God makes Himself temporal. Moreover, since one must proceed from

affirmative to negative to superlative theology, one must say that God is, is not and is

more than eternal.210

A number of scholars have focused on Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of time.211 In the

light of these studies Ibn ‘Arabi>’s relevant views can be discussed conveniently by

dividing time into Principial time and theophanic time. The latter can further be divided

into microcosmic time and macrocosmic time. The Arabic word الدھر is taken to mean

Principial time or time with which God has identified himself, while the word الوقت is

considered to be the counterpart of time as it relates to theophany, whether microcosmic

or macrocosmic.

Thus when Ibn ‘Arabi> relates the Prophetic saying “Do not curse Al-Dahr

because Al-Dahr is God” he considers it to be about the Principial time, which “stands

209

Dermot Moran, “Time and Eternity,” 488. 210

Ibid. 497-8. 211

Particularly mention-worthy are Gerhard BÞwering’s “Ibn al-‘Arabi>’s concept of Time,” in Gott ist

Schon und Er liebt die Schonheit: Fetschrift Annemarie Schimmel, eds. A Giese and J.C. Burgel (Zurich:

Lang Verlag, 1994)71-91 and Ibrahim Kalin “From the Temporal Time to the Eternal Now: Ibn al-‘Arabi>

and Mulla Sadra> on Time” in JMIAS, LXI (2007), 31-63 inter alia.

Page 160: 988S

148

above temporal time and thus presents permanence against transience.”212 Therefore,

since this Divine time is eternal time, identifying God with it does not necessarily entail

the implausible consequence of attributing mutability or corruption to God, since time

spoken of here is different from time as we experience it.213

The first subdivision of theophanic time is microcosmic time i.e. time as we

experience it and is called “the moment”(الوقت)by Ibn ‘Arabi> and other Sufis. An

important principle of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s theory of theophany, as we shall see in the next

chapter, is that the Principle manifests Himself in accordance with the disposition or

preparedness (ا8ستعداد) of the locus of manifestation (مجلى). “Moment,” according to Ibn

‘Arabi> is “what you are with and upon” and “what is decreed by and passed onto

you.”214 This definition which connects time to the category of “state” also refers to

Divine manifestation by mentioning Divine decree. As Kalin has summed it up, “The

moment designates a state of being in which individual acquires God’s decree in tandem

with his disposition.”215 By the macrocosmic moment “every natural event is an

emergence or appearance. Just like the disposition of the individual the universe also has

a disposition according to which God’s decrees emerge in different degrees of

212

Ibrahim Kalin, Ibid. 50. 213

A further step can be taken in the light of Iqbal’s discussion of God and time, according to which even

change can be ascribed to God without thereby implying any imperfection to Him, since one can

understand change in connection with God just like one understands Divine time different from human or

cosmic time. Iqbal writes, for instance, that “The Ultimate Ego exists in pure duration wherein change

ceases to be a succession of varying attitudes, and reveals its true character as continuous creation,

‘untouched by weariness’ and unseizable by “slumber or sleep.” To conceive the Ultimate Ego as

changeless in this sense is to conceive Him as utter inaction, a motiveless, stagnant neutrality, an absolute

nothing. To the creative Self change cannot mean imperfection.” Muhammad Iqbal, Reconstruction of

Religious Thought in Islam, Ed. M. Saeed Sheikh (Lahore: Institute of Islamic Culture, 1986), 48. 214

Ibrahim Kalin, “From the Temporal Time,” 47. The first definition of moment is given at Fut. II: 539. 215 Ibid. 48.

Page 161: 988S

149

ontological intensity.”216 Theophanic time of both kinds is rooted in the divinity, as Ibn

‘Arabi> writes that “The support of the present moment in the Divine things is the fact

that He describes himself with the words, “Each day He is upon some task.” (Fut. II:

539; trans. SPK, 38) Hence the category of time (of course theophanic time) is rooted in

the same facet of divinity in which the category of state is rooted.

What we have been calling “Principial time” is called “Eternal time” by Kalin,

“Eternity” by Böwering, who has concluded his article by remarking that “Eternity

belongs to God alone, but God’s creature has the present moment.”217 It would be wrong

to get the impression from these terms that just like we/the world are in time, God is in

eternity. This is a conclusion that Ibn ‘Arabi> tries hard to contest in his Kita>b al-Azal.

With the help of a complex argument Ibn ‘Arabi> seeks to show that azal (eternity-

without-beginning) conceived after likeness of time or as extension leads to absurd

conclusions like attribution of God with nothingness, negation of Divine unity by

positing another eternal existent, naming God illegitimately and finally, of circular

reasoning (تسلسل) by posing eternity as one of his attributes, since He has his attributes

eternally and having eternity eternally is circular. After negating this concept Ibn ‘Arabi>

recommends that instead of saying “God spoke in eternity” we should say “Divine

Speech is a beginningless attribute of Allah, without qualification (kayf).218We can

conclude from this that on the one hand we have Principial time which is God, not

216

Ibid. 217

Bowering, “Ibn al-‘Arabi>’s Concept of Time,” 91. 218

Ibn ‘Arabi>, “Kita>b al-Azal” in Rasa>’il Ibn ‘Arabi>, 121-122. Compare Paul Helm: “it is better to think

of timelessness not as separate attribute but as a mode of possessing attributes. It is not that God is both

omniscient and timeless but that He is timelessly omniscient.” Eternal God: A Study of God without

Time (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 17.

Page 162: 988S

150

something that encompasses Him and on the other hand theophanic time which has its

root in God’s being upon some task each day.

To sum up the discussion of God’s relation to Categoriae Decem, Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> agree on the main features of the nature of categories and on the view that in

consideration of Divine transcendence none of these categories should apply literally to

God. However Ibn ‘Arabi> connects Divine nature and the existence of these categories

since they constitute the form of the world and in the opinion of latter form of the world

is ontologically connected to Divine Nature. This fact sets him apart from Eriugena’s

position only to a certain extent, because he is drawing implications of a metaphysical

principle of his which is found in Eriugena as well. So the difference is only that one of

these writers is applying his principle to the full while the other keeps it to a certain

limit.

It can safely be concluded from the preceding analysis that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine

of Divine roots squares fairly with Eriugena’s concept of participation. However, he is

more elaborate than the latter since he not only provides a general principle but also

endeavors to relate particular existential realities to Divine realities. Eriugena, in

contrast, was more elaborate in explaining the meaning of “participation” while Ibn

‘Arabi> gave us more specific information while leaving the task of defining and

discovering principles to his readers.

In the next chapter we turn to the concept of theophany and its counterpart in

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s cosmology.

Page 163: 988S

SixSixSixSix

MacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosmMacrocosm----2222: Theophany and : Theophany and : Theophany and : Theophany and AlAlAlAl----tajallitajallitajallitajalli >> >> In the present chapter we complete our comparative analysis of the views of Eriugena

and Ibn ‘Arabi> on metacosm-macrocosm relation by addressing the second of two key

Eriugenian terms, namely “theophany.” We compare the meaning, nature and functions

of this concept in Eriugena’s philosophy with “al-tajalli>” as it is understood and put to

work by Ibn ‘Arabi>.

6.16.16.16.1 Eriugena on TheophanyEriugena on TheophanyEriugena on TheophanyEriugena on Theophany

6.1.16.1.16.1.16.1.1 Etymology and Importance of the ConceptEtymology and Importance of the ConceptEtymology and Importance of the ConceptEtymology and Importance of the Concept

The word “theophany” is derived from the Greek theos (god) and phanio (to come/bring

to light, make appear, appear). A theophany is an appearance or manifestation of

deity.219 Professor Nasr has claimed that “[t]heophany, literally ‘to show God’ does not

mean the incarnation but the reflection of Divinity in the mirror of created forms.”220

However, it seems that historically there has been some connection between the concept

of theophany and the idea of incarnation since Eusebius, Bishop of Caesarea (c.263-

c339) penned a book called Peri-Theophania in which he treated of the incarnation of

219 See Michael Sells, Mystical Languages of Unsaying, 43.

220 Knowledge and the Sacred, (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1989), 215 n. 6.

Professor Nasr has also noted the correspondence between theophany and al-tajalli>. See his book Religion

and the Order of Nature (Lahore: Suhail Academy, 2004), 229 n. 63.

Page 164: 988S

152

Jesus Christ.221 This latter idea is sometimes described as “Christophany.”

To realize the importance of “theophany” for Eriugena one has merely to observe

that he wants us to understand the four divisions of nature as theophanies: They are

from God and in God.” (DDN III: 690A) He exclaims that “no deeper thing there can be

for human inquiry than theophany.” (DDN I: 449A)

6.1.26.1.26.1.26.1.2 Dionysian Influences: FormDionysian Influences: FormDionysian Influences: FormDionysian Influences: Form----Assuming, IlluminatiAssuming, IlluminatiAssuming, IlluminatiAssuming, Illumination and Elitismon and Elitismon and Elitismon and Elitism

Pseudo-Dionysius is one of Eriugena’s most important sources, and the concept of

theophany is one of those areas where this influence is most apparent. Dionysius applies

the name theophany to “that beholding of God which shows the Divine Likeness,

figured in Itself as a likeness in form of That which is formless, through the uplifting of

those who contemplate the Divine; inasmuch as a Divine Light is shed upon the seers

through it, and they are initiated into some participation of Divine things.”222 This

definition can be analyzed into following components:

Theophany (is)…

1. Beholding of God

2. Shows Divine likeness

3. Is figured… in the form of that which is formless

4. Through the uplifting

5. Of those who contemplate

221

Translated by Samuel Lee as Eusebeus on Theophania or Divine Manifestation of Our Lord and

Saviour Jesus Christ (Cambridge University Press, 1843) available at http://www.tertullian.org/fathers/

last visited on 25/3/2010. 222

Pseudo Dionysius, Celestial Hierarchy. Chapter IV., 161 at http://www.esoteric.msu.edu, last visited

on 28th March 2009.

Page 165: 988S

153

6. Inasmuch as a Divine light is shed

7. And they are initiated into some participation of Divine things

The first component is a succinct expression of the etymology of the word

theophania. Although this expression is compatible with basic Greek etymology of the

term as “appearance or manifestation of deity” it must be noticed that by using the word

“beholding” it assigns primary role to man who beholds God rather than God who

becomes manifest or appears. This is only to say that as far as this component is

concerned agency belongs to man and not to God. However this is significantly qualified

by the components 4, 6 and 7. A combined reading of these three shows that a double

agency is involved in the phenomenon of theophany. One part is played by human being

and another by Deity. Man contemplates while God uplifts and initiates. Hence agency

belongs partially to man and partially to God.

The fifth component signifies that Dionysian concept of theophany is elitist.

Beholding of God is a privilege of those who contemplate not others. Again, this

dimension is completely in line with the general elitism of Dionysius, for he has written:

“These things thou must not disclose to any of the uninitiated, by whom I mean those

who cling to the objects of human thought, and imagine there is no super-essential

reality beyond.”223

Furthermore, in the light of what was just said, among those who contemplate,

theophany belongs only to those upon whom Divine light is shed. That is to say

theophany belongs to those contemplatives who are illuminated. Hence, Dionysian

theophany, in addition to being elitist, is illuminationist.

223

The Mystical Theology, 192.

Page 166: 988S

154

If we emphasize the italicized word “likeness” then it gives us an important

feature of the concept. In the light of the doctrine of Uknowability of God, to which

Pseudo Dionysius adheres,224 it can be interpreted as ruling out the appearance of

Divinity in itself in theophany and emphasizing the appearance of its likeness only. This

characteristic shows that Dionysian theophany does not compromise Divine

transcendence.

A look at the way Eriugena uses and explicates the term “theophany” reveals

deep Dionysian influences. In fact most of the components into which we analyzed

Dionysian articulation of theophany find an expression in Eriugena. We “say most of”

since Eriugena seems to be more honest to the Greek etymology of the word since he

identifies theophanies with Divine manifestation (DDN I: 446). He seems to have taken

and developed the other strands from Dionysian definition of theophany. Thus we find

in Eriugena theophany’s characterization as “form-adopting of the Formless,” double

agency, elitist illuminationism and the essential unknowability of Deity. In the famous

negati affirmatio passage where Eriugena introduces theophany for the first time, he

typifies it as “the form of the formless (forma informis). (DDN III 633B) As for the

elitist-illuminationist dimension, Eriugena says that

… it is for very few, wholly detached from earthly thoughts and purged by

virtue and knowledge to know God in these visible creatures as the patriarch

Abraham knew Him from the revolutions of the stars, with natural law for his

guide… and as Moses in the Bush and on the summit of the mountain. (DDN

III. 689B-D)

The illuminationist dimension of Eriugena’s concept of theophany was recognized by

E.C McCue, S.J., who devoted a whole chapter to it in his doctoral dissertation as early

224

See the first chapters of two Dionysian treatises The Divine Names and The Mystical Theology.

Page 167: 988S

155

as 1939. Commenting on the word “vehitur” (i.e. “is carried.”) in Eriugena’s explanation

of intellect-reason relation (DDN IV: 745D) McCue wrote that it signifies that to be

moved or carried the soul must receive some impetus from the one to which it is

drawn.225 Interestingly, at one place Eriugena himself gives the impression that he is

speaking as someone who has been illuminated by a theophany.226 He adds this

dimension to the Eschatological theophanies, i.e. the Beatific Vision in the After-life.

Referring to the saying of Christ “There are many mansions in my Father’s House,”

Eriugena writes that “…each shall receive a form according to the degree of his own

sanctity and wisdom.” (DDN I: 448C) He also maintains that each man shall have his

proper place according to his conduct in this life. (Ibid. V: 983A) Those who have gone

beyond human nature (“transcended their selves” in Schuon’s terminology227) in their

holiness will not only be granted a theophany of God but will actually enter into the

cloud surrounding God, to experience what Eriugena describes as “theophany of

theophanies.”(See ibid. I: 450B; V: 905C, 963C-964A)

6.1.36.1.36.1.36.1.3 Epistemological Theophany and Unknowability Epistemological Theophany and Unknowability Epistemological Theophany and Unknowability Epistemological Theophany and Unknowability

In the above mentioned settings, both mundane and eschatological, “theophany”

signifies a mode of knowing God. This implies that theophany is an alternate for

knowing something as it is in itself. So Eriugena contrasts “theophany” with objective

reality. Indeed, he uses the term for the first time in DDN while negating the possibility

225

Theophany: A Study of God and His Manifestations in the work of the ninth Century Irish Philosopher

John Scottus Eriugena, Dissertation by E.C. McCue (St. Louis University), 146. 226

This is inferred by Dermot Moran from DDN III: 656D-657A: “you assign to me the things that are

harder to seek and find and demonstrate. However it is my part to seek, but to find is His alone who

illumines the hidden places of Darkness. His alone is the Demonstration because He [alone] can open the

senses of those who seek and the intellect. For of what use is a demonstration from without if there is no

illumination within.” See The Philosophy, 76. 227

See Frithjof Schuon, “Survey of Integral Anthropology,” in his To Have a Centre.

Page 168: 988S

156

of comprehending primordial causes in themselves, saying that “in the intellect of the

angels there are certain theophanies of those reasons and not reasons themselves.” (DDN

I: 446C) If primordial causes cannot be known as they are in themselves, then a fortiori

the essence of God cannot be seen or known either. (See DDN I: 448) Beatific vision is

mediated through theophanies even for the elect (See DDN I: 450C; V: 926C, 988C).228

It seems that here Eriugena is doing nothing more than developing the Dionysian

element of theophany according to which it shows likeness of God.

The contrast of theophany with knowing the essence of God serves a very

important role, namely, that of retaining the God-World duality. Dierdre Carabine

thinks that in view of this contrast “Eriugena always retains a basic distinction between

the self-manifestation of God and God’s self. Even in the final theophany when all

things will have returned to God and God shall be all in all Eriugena never “conflates”

God and creature.”229 Since God is found only in theophany to a certain extent, and not

found as to what He is in himself, the quest for God will be endless (DDN V: 919A-

D).230 The final word on this question is that God is both found and not found. He is

found through theophanies, but not found through contemplations of Divine nature

itself. (DDN V: 919C)

228

Eriugena also writes “But because they cannot behold the most high and holy Trinity in itself, for it is

incomprehensible and transcends the intelligible vision and all the faculties of mind and can only

contemplate It in comprehensible Theophanies which are of like nature with themselves, therefore they

are called the clouds of heaven. DDN V: 1000C. 229

John Scottus Eriugena, 33. 230

Carabine has pointed out the presence of this strand of thought in St Gregory of Nyssa, according to

whom the search for God will be infinite since the Divine nature is infinite. See John Scottus Eriugena,

125 n. 11.

Page 169: 988S

157

6.1.46.1.46.1.46.1.4 Ontological Theophany and TranscendenceOntological Theophany and TranscendenceOntological Theophany and TranscendenceOntological Theophany and Transcendence

In addition to considering theophany a “mode of knowing” Eriugena mentions that

“every visible and invisible creature can be called a theophany, that is, a Divine

apparition” since “the ineffable and incomprehensible brilliance of the Divine Goodness

begins to appear in its theophanies” and it can be said to be “known in all essence.”

(DDN III: 681A) As “manifestation of the hidden” and “becoming visible of the

invisible” theophany is the “ineffable descent of the Supreme Goodness, which is Unity

and Trinity, into the things that are so as to make them to be, indeed so as itself to be in

all things…” (DDN III: 678D, emphasis added). This requires that the understanding of

theophany as a mode of knowing be complemented by its understanding as a mode of

being. Should this descent into the things be taken to mean that Eriugena is

propounding pantheism? Many Eriugena scholars are now agreed that it does not. Otten

has pointed out that this does not mean an act of audacious pantheism since being

Divine apparitions theophanies cannot be put upon a par with the underlying essence of

God,”231 adding that “on the level of the text the comparison between God and his

theophanies leads us to declare them identical, although in the final analysis they cannot

be ranked on the same level, since one is ranked on the level of creative and the other on

the level of created nature.”232 Hence, everything’s being theophany lands us somewhere

between immanence and transcendence and is not a plain denial of Divine

transcendence. It should be recalled here that according to its epistemic understanding

theophany has given us a similar middle position on the question of finding God.

231

Otten, Anthropology, 88. 232

Ibid. 89 n. 12.

Page 170: 988S

158

6.1.56.1.56.1.56.1.5 Functions of “Theophany” in Eriugena’s ThoughtFunctions of “Theophany” in Eriugena’s ThoughtFunctions of “Theophany” in Eriugena’s ThoughtFunctions of “Theophany” in Eriugena’s Thought

Let us briefly outline the functions of “theophany” in general and its ontological

understanding in particular in the cosmology of Eriugena. A brief discussion of the

functions of theophany in Eriugena will shed more light on its centrality and

importance. Otten has come up with insightful remarks regarding the role played by

“theophany.” According to her theophany counterbalances Eriugena’s negative theology

by permitting the description of God in terms deriving from the realm of creation, while

guaranteeing the natural, hierarchical distance between God and creation.233 Although

this contention of Otten’s seems to be corroborated by Eriugena’s famous

characterization of theophany as negati affirmatio, that is to say, “affirmation of the

negated,” it loses its weight when seen in the light of Eriugena’s emphatic

negativization of his synthesis of affirmative and negative theologies as we pointed out

and explained in the third chapter. Secondly, it is through theophany that Eriugena

could associate scripture with the natural order of the cosmos.234 Eriugena believes

firmly in analogy between scriptura and creatura which he says are “two garments of

Chirst” indicating that under the difference of apparel the same contents can be found.

(See DDN III: 690A).235

To these two proposed functions of theophany we can add some other. In an

earlier chapter we witnessed Eriugena claiming that in creating the universe God creates

Himself. This problematic saying can be explained with the help of theophany,

understood ontologically. Hence if the universe is nothing but theophany then when God

creates it He creates only His theophany or appearance. Moreover, the fact that God is

233

See ibid. 83. 234

See Ibid 84 n. 3 235

See ibid. 102-3.

Page 171: 988S

159

the Middle as well as the Beginning and the End can be understood in this very light.

Eriugena describes two modes under which God appears as the Middle to its observers.

First “when the Divine Nature is seen to be created and to create—for it is created by

itself in the primordial causes, and therefore creates itself, that is allows itself to appear

in its theophanies” and second “when it is seen in the lowest effects of the primordial

causes” (DDN III: 689A-B). The italicized expressions indicate that what is at stake

here primarily is not “knowing God” but God’s appearing first in primordial causes and

then in the spatio-temporal effects of these causes. This is to say that this function as

well as the previous one is played by theophany in its ontological sense.

Before analyzing Ibn ‘Arabi>’s notion of “al-tajalli>,” let us summarize salient

features of Eriugena’s doctrine of theophany discussed above. This will help us find out

the extent to which both notions correspond to each other.

We brought out centrality of the notion in overall cosmology of Eriugena and its

Greek etymology gave us the meaning of “appearance of God.” We discussed the

Pseudo-Dionysian concept of theophany and noticed that Eriugenian elaboration of the

notion is predominantly Dionysian. In the light of an analysis of Dionysian definition of

“theophany” and its usage by Eriugena, the following features of Eriugenian doctrine

were brought out: first, theophany is appearing into form of a being who is formless;

second, Divine self-manifestation is not open to all, but to the spiritually self-disciplined

elite and in accordance with piety. Finally, it was maintained that Eriugena’s use of the

notion renders it analyzable into two kinds. Understood epistemologically, theophany

means “knowing God” while understood ontologically, it implies “being God.” Contrary

to their appearance these two ways do not compromise Divine transcendence but rather

help preserve it. The former point of view establishes an appearance-reality dichotomy

Page 172: 988S

160

as far as our knowledge of God is concerned. It also connects nature to the scripture and

serves to explain the meaning of theologically strange Eriugenian idea of Divine Self

Creation and God’s being the Middle.

6.26.26.26.2 Ibn ‘Arabi> on “Ibn ‘Arabi> on “Ibn ‘Arabi> on “Ibn ‘Arabi> on “alalalal----TajalliTajalliTajalliTajalli> > > > ””””

6.26.26.26.2....1111 Centrality of the ConceptCentrality of the ConceptCentrality of the ConceptCentrality of the Concept

If Eriugena knows nothing deeper for the human inquiry than theophany, ‘the term self-

disclosure (tajalli)236—often translated as ‘theophany’ – plays such a central role in Ibn

‘Arab�’s teachings that … he has been called one of the “companions of Self-

Disclosure” (as}h}a>b al-tajalli>).’237 Indeed Chittick, the maker of this remark, has found no

word to title his book on Principles of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Cosmology better than Self

Disclosure of God.

Since Ibn ‘Arabi> has to say many things on this subject and in the space of one

subsection we cannot analyze all his ideas, we stick to the main features of Eriugena’s

doctrine of theophany, outlined at the end of last subsection and see where does Ibn

‘Arabi> stand and why. However, we would discuss those of his other views which either

explain or add important dimensions to what was said by Eriugena.

Having seen that these two notions occupy central place in the cosmologies both

of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>, let us begin with comparing the etymologies of these terms.

236 Self-disclosure is not satisfactory translation of تجلي. The Arabic word does not have a reference to

Divine self. If we take the word “self” seriously it would denote Divine essence which does not have

disclosures. In the Qur’a>n itself tajalli> never occurs with the Divine Name Allah but al-Rabb which

pertains to the level of divinity not of Ipseity. It is better to translate the word simply as “disclosure”. 237

William C. Chittick, The Self Disclosure of God, 52.

Page 173: 988S

161

6.2.26.2.26.2.26.2.2 Etymology and Qur’a>nic usage of the term. Etymology and Qur’a>nic usage of the term. Etymology and Qur’a>nic usage of the term. Etymology and Qur’a>nic usage of the term.

Tajalli> is a noun derived from the root j-l-w. The verb jala> from this root means “to be or

become clear, un-obscured, exposed to view, displayed, laid open, disclosed or

uncovered.”238 Ra>ghib al-Isfaha>ni> (d. 1108), the famous lexicographer of the Qur’a>n,

maintained that disclosure is either essential or through an action or imperative.239 This

means that either something is essentially manifest or else, it has to do something in

addition to merely “being there” in order to become manifest.240 Day appears with the

simple appearance of the Sun and the Sun does not have to do anything in addition to

just being there in order to make the day manifest. Al-Is}faha>ni> thinks that the Divine

disclosure is not like appearance of the day. God is manifest only when He wills and to

whosoever He wills.

Ibn ‘Arabi> derives almost all of his technical vocabulary from the Qur’a>n itself

and an examination of the Qur’a>nic usage of the term reveals that the basic

etymological meaning of “appearance” is retained by it. Ibn ‘Arabi> has connected the

idea that God is witnessed in the creation to the already quoted Qur’a>nic verse, “We

shall show them…” (41:53). (See Fut. II: 305). He also mentions in this context the

prophetic tradition to the effect that “God transmutes (يتحول) in the forms.” However

these are only indirect references in addition to which the word itself occurs twice in the

Qur’a>n. At one place we read

والنھار إذا تجلى

By the day, as it appears in glory. (92:2)

238

See Edward William Lane, An Arabic English Lexicon, II: 82. 239

See Al-Mufrada>t fi> Ghari>b al-Qur’a>n, Karachi: As}ah}h} al-Mat}a>bi‘,1961), 94-95. 240 See Ibid.

Page 174: 988S

162

Then while narrating the famous Mount Sinai event when Moses requested that he must

see God, the verb is ascribed to the Lord:

...فلما تجلى ربه للجبل

When his Lord revealed Himself to the mountain … (7:143)

Most of the Qur’a>n interpreters render تجلى here simply as ظھر i.e. “appeared.”241

Some, however, find it necessary to qualify and explain that God’s appearing means a

manifestation of His power and Glory etc. One of these is the Mu‘tazilite al-

Zamakhshari> (d.1144)242 and the other is the anti-Sufi Burha>n al-Di>n al-Biqa>‘i> (d.

1480).243 Both occurrences of the latter word in the Qur’a>n connote “appearance or

disclosure” which parallels the Greek phanio and in one of these the word is applied to

God which makes a correspondence with the Greek theo-phania. All this manifests that

as Ibn ‘Arabi>’s understanding of tajalli> is rooted in the sources of Muslim orthodoxy as

is Eriugena’s notion of theophany immersed in the Christian tradition and that as far as

their etymology is concerned theophany and al-tajalli> are synonymous.

6.2.36.2.36.2.36.2.3 AlAlAlAl----Tajalli>Tajalli>Tajalli>Tajalli>: Ontol: Ontol: Ontol: Ontological and Epistemological ogical and Epistemological ogical and Epistemological ogical and Epistemological

We mentioned two modes of looking at Eriugena’s concept of theophany, ontological

and epistemological. According to the former theophany is a mode of God’s appearing

in the forms of the entities while in the light of the latter it is God’s making Himself

known. Now in case of Ibn ‘Arabi> this distinction is more clearly present within the

doctrine itself and we do not have to introduce it from outside, as many followers of Ibn

‘Arabi> have noticed its presence in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s understanding and use of the term

241

For example ‘Abdulla>h b. Ah}mad al-Nasafi>, Mada>rik al- Tanzi>l, (Beirut: Da>r al-Nafa>’is, 2005) , II: 108. 242

See his al-Kashsha>f ‘an H} aqa>’iq al-Tanzi>l (Beirut: Da>r Ih}ya>’ al-Tura>th al-‘Arabi>, n.d.), II: 146. 243

See his Naz}m al-Durar fi> Tana>sub al-A>ya>t wa- al-Suwar (Beirut: Da>r al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyah, 2002), III:

173.

Page 175: 988S

163

tajalli>. ‘Abd al-Kari>m al-Ji>li> (d. 832) set apart the term tajalli> for the epistemological

theophany while used the word تعيين to capture the ontological dimension of the

notion.244 In the writings of Ibn ‘Arabi> himself if one wanted to have a term for

exclusive reference to the ontological theophany one could refer to ظھور manifestation

which is the name given to the Absolute’s stepping, so to speak, out of Its sheer

Absoluteness. According to Chittick, “the term tajalli> may be employed in the context

of ontology, epistemology or—as more commonly happens, without any distinction

being employed between these two domains.”245 Those who prefer to use single term

tajalli> and maintain at the same time the distinction follow ‘Abd al-Rah}ma>n Ja>mi>

(d.1492) in dividing it into التجلي الوجودي and التجلي الشھودي.

Ibn ‘Arabi> has in his mind an ontological sense of the word tajalli> when he says:

“So He, the Exalted One, has a general tajalli> perpetually in the world and the degrees of

the world in it vary in accordance the intrinsic differences in the degrees of the world, so

He manifests according to their preparedness.” (Fut. II: 556) Or when he says: “The

world is naught but His self-Disclosure in the forms of their immutable identities, whose

existence would be impossible without it…” (Fus. 81; Ringstones, 61). As far as the

epistemological tajalli> is concerned it is obviously intended when Ibn ‘Arabi> says that

“Perfect knowledge only abides in Divine self-disclosure and in what the Real

unveils in removing the coverings from the eyes of discernment and vision. One

will then perceive things—the eternal among them and those which come to be,

their non-existence and existence, their impossible, necessary and contingent—

as they are in their realities and identities. (Fus. 133; trans. Ringstones, 150.)

244

Abu>’l-‘ala> al-‘Affi>fi>, “Ibn ‘Arabi> fi> Dira>sa>ti>,”> in Al-Kita>b al-tidhka>ri> li Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> (Cairo:

Da>r al-Ka>tib al-‘Arabi>, 1969), 28-31. 245

SPK, 91.

Page 176: 988S

164

Here Ibn ‘Arabi> is obviously referring to tajalli> as a mode of attaining the highest degree

of knowledge. So in its epistemological sense the term can be considered synonymous

with famous Sufi terms كشف and فتح that are normally translated as intuition, unveiling,

illumination or opening, although in one place (see Fut. IV: 32) Ibn ‘Arabi> does seem to

be differentiating between tajalli> and kashf.246 However the above quoted passage and

others are explicit in indentifying both these terms and the final sentence of the passage

quoted above takes us to the next level of the comparative analysis of the terms

theophany and tajalli>.

Does the claim that one can perceive things as they are in their realities and

identities means that tajalli> based knowledge is knowledge of things as they are in

themselves? An affirmative answer to this question would imply that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

concept of tajalli> differs from Eriugena’s theophany as sources of knowledge. We

have seen that Eriugena contrasts knowledge through theophany to objective

246 Ibn ‘Arabi> writes: “The first One-third of Divine knowledge is what can be known of/from/about Him

through arguments/signs; the second one-third is what is known of/from/about Him, may He be (منه)

Exalted, through witnessing on the occasion of tajalli> and the final one-third is what is known

of/from/about Him through His informing, may He be Exalted, and this is the truest of categories as far as

knowledge of God is concerned.” This passage is not explicitly establishing a semantic dichotomy

between al-tajalli> and al-kashf, though one of many possible readings might suggest so. We should read it

in combination with Fut. I: 39: “The first way is that of unveiling. ... This kind of knowledge may also be

actualized through a self-disclosure given to its possessors…” In this way we can get the more consistent

view according to which in Fut. IV: 32 Ibn ‘Arabi> is not dividing knowledge into that through tajalli> and

that through kashf but is giving us two sub classes, [witnessing (musha>hadah) and unveiling (muka>shafah

or kashf)] of the epistemic tajalli> itself. This interpretation is further supported by the fact that Ibn ‘Arabi>

not only differentiates between witnessing and unveiling but considers the latter as more excellent and

perfect than the former. For more on Ibn ‘Arabi>’s usage of these terms see al- Mu‘jam al-S}u>fi>, 664-665.

Page 177: 988S

165

knowledge.247 However, the above quoted passage from Ibn ‘Arabi> does not imply that

tajalli> based knowledge is that of things as they are in themselves. This is because by

“eternal things,” he understands nothing but the eternal objects of Divine knowledge, so

that in the sentence quoted above “eternal things” and “realities and identities” refer to

a single reality. Hence both Eriugena’s theophany and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s tajalli> constitute an

epistemological isthmus (برزخ) or veil (حجاب) between the knower and the known, and as

such simultaneously manifesting and concealing the veiled object. The agreement on

this point becomes clearer when it comes to the theophanic knowledge of God Himself.

Ibn ‘Arabi> is of the opinion that the Divine Self (الذات ا8لھية) can never become manifest,

so no tajalli> makes It known. As usual his opinion is based on an extraordinarily careful

reading of the Qur’a>n. He directs our attention to the Divine name al-Rabb (the Lord)

that accompanies tajjali> in the Qur’a>nic words fa lamma> tajalla> rabbuhu> and says that

tajalli> belongs only to the God [al-ila>h] and the Lord (al-rabb), never to Allah for He is

the Independent. (Fut. III: 178; trans. SDG, 54). We also find him expressing this idea in

clear terms by saying that, “The inmost centre of His majesty is not perceived by any

rational faculty, nor is the inmost center of His Essence perceived by eyesight when He

discloses Himself, wherever He should disclose Himself to His servants.” (Fut. III: 371;

trans. SDG, 55)

In spite of the resonance between our two thinkers it must be emphasized once

again that the way Ibn ‘Arabi> analyzes Divine Reality into Essence, Attributes/Names

and Actions makes his views on Divine nature more precise and detailed than those of

Eriugena.

247 We saw that according to Eriugena the Angels do not know the primordial causes themselves but only

certain of their theophanies.

Page 178: 988S

166

6.2.46.2.46.2.46.2.4 FormFormFormForm----Assuming, Illumination and ElitismAssuming, Illumination and ElitismAssuming, Illumination and ElitismAssuming, Illumination and Elitism

Finally, the same ontological understanding of the concept is involved in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

countless references to God’s appearing in forms (تجلي في الصور).248 He discusses this

notion in various contexts and in order to explain a number of different things. For

instance, he explains through it the “entification of everything” (شياءEظھور شيئية ا) (Fut. I:

188) and the existence of religious diversity (Fut. IV: 166). He also mentions the

opinion that different theological sects share single belief concerning the nature of God

because God appears in same form to all of them. Although he seems to disagree with

this opinion in view of his principle that a particular theophany does not repeat itself for

two or more individuals, this disagreement still includes a reference to theophany in

forms. (Fut. III: 384) He writes at one place, “So it is the Real who is Being and the

things are forms of Being, thus the affair is interconnected like form and matter are

interconnected.” (Fut. IV: 100) This notion of Divine disclosure “in forms” parallels

Eriugena’s characterization of theophany as form-assuming of the formless (forma

informis). At the end of this subsection, we come once again to theophany and Divine

form assuming in the discussion of “loci of manifestation.” Let us have a look for the

moment at the questions of elitism and illumination.

As for elitism in Ibn ‘Arabi>, obviously, it is only the knowledge or understanding

of the true nature of some fact that can be privilege of some intellectual or spiritual elite

and not the fact itself. Otherwise one would end up endorsing sheer Sophism. Therefore

the question of elitism arises in connection with epistemic tajalli>/kashf and not with

ontological one. The fact that God appears in the forms of the world remains a fact

whether it is known to all or some. At a number of places in his al-Futu>h}a>t Ibn ‘Arabi>

248

Also see Fut. III: 95 and IV: 101.

Page 179: 988S

167

explicitly states that knowledge acquisition through theophany or unveiling is specific

to some. At least at two place he mentions Prophets and Friends of God as those who

are exclusively bestowed with theophanic knowledge. (See Fut. I: 31 and I: 319) In this

context Ibn ‘Arabi> speaks of God’s singling out any of his servants whom He wills to be

granted access to this knowledge. (See Fut. I: 218)

These few examples are sufficient to show that epistemic theophany as

understood by Ibn ‘Arabi> is elitist in a general manner. Some more specific dimensions

emerge by taking into account a few distinctions he makes. First, there is a distinction

between theophany in a dream and while one is awake. Second, we have to differentiate

between the fact of theophany and knowledge of its real nature. Third, an important

distinction is made between exoteric and esoteric scholars of Islam. In the light of first

distinction, Ibn ‘Arabi>’s concept of theophany is elitist in the sense that although

ordinary folk may have a theophanic dream it is the privilege only of the Prophets and

Friends of God to have theophanic vision while they are awake. (Fut. IV: 200). In the

light of second distinction, “For many of the folk of the Path of God, even if they

witness the Real’s self-disclosure (tajalli>), have no knowledge of that, nor of what they

see, nor of the form of the actual situation.” (Ibid. III: 516; SDG, 56). Finally, it is in the

light of the third distinction that we find Ibn ‘Arabi> saying, “The Gnostics witness Him

in the forms of the created things while the veiled ones from amongst the exoteric

scholars (علماء الرسوم) do not recognize Him, so for the former He is named al-Z}a>hir

while for the latter He is named al-Ba>t}in.” (Fut. III: 541). The real and objective nature

of theophany is grasped by, to use Chittick’s expression, only a tiny minority even of

the esoteric scholars.

Page 180: 988S

168

However, to this elitist strand an important qualification must be added. The

unknowability or obscurity of theophany for the majority has as its cause a subjective

element also. As Ibn ‘Arabi> himself maintains, “Know that God discloses himself

perpetually (متجٍل على الدوام) and the veils are only lifted from our eyes. He, the Exalted

One said, ‘Now have We removed thy veil’ (50: 22) and He said ‘We are nearer to him

than ye, and ye see not (56: 85).’” (Fut. I: 706, emphasis added). This shows that unlike

Eriugena and Pseudo Dionysius, Ibn ‘Arabi>’s conception of theophany is not completely

elitist but he has brought out the subjective cause of its accessibility to the chosen few.

The word “subjective” can be confusing here so let us make it clear that we are not

using it in the sense of “relative” or “illusory.”

According to prevailing analysis, also followed by Chittick, there are two

components of theophany (tajalli): the Self-Discloser (المتجلي) and the locus of

manifestation ( مجلى or متجلى له ). While this is true in most of the cases, there are

certain cases where there is a human recipient of theophany in addition to the locus of

manifestation. In the case Burning Bush, God is the Manifest, the mount is locus of

manifestation and Moses is spectator. The mount itself was both the locus and

spectator. Now what we meant by saying that the veils are subjective rather than

objective was that it is not God who is veiled rather it is the recipient that is veiled. As

Schuon has put it, “Grace surrounds us infinitely and it is only our hardness that makes

us impervious to its radiation, in itself omnipresent. It is the soul which is absent, not

grace.”249 We must not forget however, that in one sense of the word “subject” God is

the subject of theophany and man is its “object.”

249 Echoes of Perennial Wisdom (Bloomington: World Wisdom Books, 1992), 37.

Page 181: 988S

169

The second component of theophany mentioned here, namely, the locus of

manifestation or recipient corresponds to the “forma” in Eriugena’s forma informis. A

locus of manifestation is the form in which God becomes manifest. According to Ibn

‘Arabi> the whole cosmos is nothing but “loci of Divine self-manifestation” and

consequently “anyone who loves the cosmos in this regard has loved it with God’s love

and has loved nothing but God’s beauty…” (Fut. II: 345; SDG, 28) A locus is not simply

passive receiver of theophany but exercises a certain influence over it by determining its

nature and channelizing it: “Hence in the image the ruling property (حكم) of the presence

of locus of manifestation is greater than that of the Discloser.” (Fut. III: 109) The

relationship between the Manifest and the locus of manifestation is not one sided but

dialectical one. This is one of the most significant aspects of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s doctrine of

theophany. In this regard he has formulated a general principle (“the principle of

preparedness”) that a theophany is always according to preparedness of the locus of

manifestation. (Fus}. 62; Ringstones, 25). Ibn ‘Arabi> explains the principle by referring

to many examples, of a single ray from the Sun having contrary effects on a person of

cold temperament and the one with a hot temperament and then on the washer-man and

the clothing. He therefore says that the theophanies of the One are diverse in accordance

with the diversity of the preparedness of loci of manifestation. (Fut. I: 287; SPK, 92)

This shows that the nature and limitations of the object condition the nature of

theophany itself. For Ibn ‘Arabi> this explains, inter alia, “the relationship between Being

and the existent things. Each entity is a receptacle of theophany.”

One other aspect of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s views on tajalli> closely related to the elitist

strand which is, moreover, comparable to Pseudo Dionysian and Eriugenian view is

illuminationism. Theophany as mystical source of knowledge is identified with light

Page 182: 988S

170

thrown by God in the believer’s heart: “Sound knowledge is only that which God throws

into the heart of the knower. It is a Divine light for which God singles out any of his

servants whom He wills, whether angel, messenger, prophet, friend, or person of faith.”

(Fut. I: 218)

6.2.56.2.56.2.56.2.5 AlAlAlAl----TajalliTajalliTajalliTajalli > and > and > and > and DivineDivineDivineDivine Transcendence Transcendence Transcendence Transcendence

In our discussion of Eriugenian view above scholarly consensus was mentioned on the

opinion that Eriugena’s concept of theophany does not compromise Divine

transcendence. We saw that in spite of using seemingly pantheistic terminology

Eriugena always retains a distinction between God and the world. Although Ibn ‘Arabi>

sees the world as Divine theophany and also considers theophany one of the modes of

knowing God, he is careful not to compromise Divine transcendence in maintaining all

this. His ultimate response to the question of God-world relationship remains

somewhere in between transcendence and identity. Just like Eriugena who maintained

that God both is and is not found in the theophanies, Ibn ‘Arabi> says, in more

ontological way, that the world both is and is not Him. In his terminology the world is

He/notHe. (Fut. II: 501). Moreover, Ibn ‘Arabi> agrees with Eriugena in subscribing to

the view that there is no end to the journey of knowing God. In his thought this belief

follows as a conclusion from a cluster of concepts like those of infinite theophanies,

perpetual creation and non-repetition of Divine self-disclosures. Ibn ‘Arabi> has

expressed this view by saying that on the Path to God’s knowledge there is no

“quenching of thirst,” so that a seeker of theophanic knowledge remains always thirsty.

Hence Divine transcendence is compromised neither by Eriugenian theophany nor by

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s al-tajalli>.

Page 183: 988S

171

With the comparative analysis of participation and Divine roots in the previous

chapter and that of theophany and tajalli> in the present we have shown that there is

remarkable correspondence in the way Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> understand the

relationship between God and the macrocosmic world. In the final chapter of this study

we are going to compare the thought of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> regarding the nature of

man vis. a vis. God and created nature in terms of the concepts of containment and

Divine image.

Page 184: 988S

SevenSevenSevenSeven

ManManManMan,,,, God and NatureGod and NatureGod and NatureGod and Nature After discussing the concepts of totality and ontology in the second chapter we have

presented in the three chapters that followed, a comparative analysis of the nature of

God, of the primordial causes and spatio-temporal world in relationship with God in

terms of participation and theophany. A discussion of the world without a substantial

account of the nature of man and his place vis a vis God and created nature would be

wanting. In the present chapter we discuss man according to Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>.

However, we are not going to, and cannot possibly within the scope of this short

chapter, present all anthropological views of these two thinkers. We shall remain

content, rather, with their views on man in relation on the one hand to God, and on the

other to cosmos.

7.17.17.17.1 Man and Nature in Eriugena Man and Nature in Eriugena Man and Nature in Eriugena Man and Nature in Eriugena

7.1.17.1.17.1.17.1.1 Theory of Universal Human ContainmentTheory of Universal Human ContainmentTheory of Universal Human ContainmentTheory of Universal Human Containment

Eriugena presents man not as one isolated being among others but in relation, on the one

hand, to God and on the other to the created nature. This is shown first and foremost by

the very definition that Eriugena offers us for man, namely, notio in mente divina, i.e. “a

notion in the mind of God.” (DDN IV: 768B) It is shown secondly, by Eriugena’s

adherence to and use of the traditional concept of human deiformity, i.e. creation upon

Divine image or form. On the other hand the keyword for the Man-Cosmos relation in

Eriugena is “containment,” the doctrine that man contains all the created nature.

Page 185: 988S

173

It would have been appropriate from the point of view of systematic treatment to

discuss first man-God relationship in terms of deiformity and proceed then to man-world

relationship. However this strategy is unfortunately difficult to follow since in Eriugena

human deiformity and containment are interconnected in a complex explanatory relation

to each other. In view of this difficulty let us take up the discussion from the side of

containment. The strategy of treating man-nature relationship before man-God relation

although a result of a difficulty is nonetheless justified since nature mediates God and

man in the sense that man reaches God through himself and through Nature, as we are

taught both by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>.

The leading question in the discussion of containment is related to its modality,

i.e. how everything is contained in man? Throughout his discourse on the doctrine of

containment Eriugena attempts to remain grounded in the Scripture in addition to

reason and tradition (i.e. the Church Fathers). Thus he refers to Scriptural text to the

interpretation of Six Divine Days of creation, God’s creating Adam last of all creature

and inviting him to name all the things. At one occasion he refers to the commandment

“Preach the Gospel to every creature.” (DDN IV: 760A) If preaching to man is

considered tantamount to preaching to every creature by the Scripture then it is implied

that every creature is in man. Now, although he would provide a detailed discourse into

the question of modality of containment later on, Eriugena does attempt to make sense

of the doctrine in its very first statement. This attempt is made with reference to the

obvious fact that man shares some of his characteristics with each of two fundamental

categories of creation. On the authority of Saint Maximus the Confessor Eriugena says

that in as much as his body man possesses the characteristics of sensible creatures but

inasmuch as his soul, those of the intelligible creatures “thus, he contains within him all

Page 186: 988S

174

creation.” (See DDN II: 530C) Commenting on the same masters’ words he has written

that human nature supplies a middle term between the sensible and intelligible creatures

which are opposed to one another as the extreme terms of created natures, for in it they

are joined to one another and from being many become one. (See ibid.) According to the

Homily also, man represents medietas between matter and spirit and is posited as the

third world (Tertius mundus) which brings in itself (unum facit lit. “unifies”) soul

(anima) and the body (corpus), the former from the spiritual world while latter from the

corporeal world. (Hom. XIX: 0294B)

Since in man every creature from the highest to the lowest is found, he is called

“agent of (continuity of) all things.” (See DDN II: 530C-531A) For the same reason he

is termed “the conjunction of the extremities of all creation” and “the workshop of

everything” (DDN IV: 893C) Eriugena, however, does not like to use the term

“microcosm” for man (DDN IV: 793C). This he does following Gregory of Nyssa who

did not want to use that term since that would downplay human deiformity. At 793C

Eriugena has quoted from Gregory of Nyssay’s De Hominis Opificio where the latter

has criticized the usage of microcosmos for man. It seems that Gregory is against this

usage not because he thinks that man is not a microcosm, rather he is against

considering man’s greatness to lie in his likeness to the created world rather than having

been “created according to the image of the Creator of Nature” (IV: 794A). Therefore,

using microcosm for human being will not be disapproved of by Gregory, and following

him by Eriugena, if it is placed beneath the concept of imago dei and is not made the

principal reason for human dignity. This also shows that an overemphasis on the

continuity of the theme of containment from middle ages to Renaissance, as is done by

Page 187: 988S

175

Dermot Moran,`250 is somewhat misplaced. It disregards the break between the medieval

conception of containment that was connected to homo imago dei motif and the

Renaissance appropriation of the idea that was humanistic and sought to make man

master of the universe in isolation from his Divine roots.

Now a more sophisticated explanation, or what Gracia calls “ontological

characterization”251 of the precise nature of containment is called for since man is also

part of the created nature himself. Thus we find the Alumnus confused as to how to

make sense of this doctrine of containment: “In what way are all things created in man,

and how do they subsist in him? Are they in him simply as essence, or simply as

accidents, or do they play in him all the roles which we observe in universal creation,

that is, essence, species, difference, property and everything which is understood to

relate to them? (DDN IV: 764C) Eriugena finds it difficult to give a rational answer to

this question since if one responds that everything was created in man simply as

essence, this leads to the dilemma of either leaving “things which are understood to

relate to essence or substance” out of the universe of things (Ibid.) or contradict the

basic claim that nothing whatsoever among created things is excluded from containment

in human being. (DDN 536B) The second option, that “not only the essences but all

things which are understood to naturally relate to them are from God and to be

numbered among parts of the whole” leads likewise to unacceptable consequence of

man’s containing “bestiality, quadrupidality, volatility … and all the other innumerable

attributes which seem to be so far removed from human nature” (DDN IV: 765B) So

how is it that everything is created in man after all?

250

See The Philosophy , 173-174. 251 G.J. E Gracia, “Ontological Characterization of the Relation between Man and Created Nature in

Eriugena,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, XVI (1978), 155-166.

Page 188: 988S

176

At this crucial point in the argument Eriugena turns away from the external

world of essences and properties to the internal world of knowledge and imagination.

The argument is founded on a statement made by alumnus himself to the effect that

“everything which is known by the intellect or the reason or imagined by the senses can

somehow be created in the knower and perceiver” (DDN IV: 765C). It is agreed in the

subsequent steps of the argument that “knowledge of things made in the soul” is not

only of a different ontological order than the “objects of knowledge themselves” (Ibid)

but of higher one as well, inasmuch as they are “in a better nature, namely the minds

that understands, … but the relation between this knowledge and the things themselves

which are its objects I do not fully grasp.” (DDN IV: 766A-766B) At this point the

Nutritor suddenly embarks upon the discussion of the relation between man and arts.

This digression is related firstly in an indirect way to the confession made by the

Alumnus in his initial statement at DDN 765C since the relationship between man and

art is equivalent to that between objects and their notions. Secondly, as the discussion

below shows, through the discussion of arts-minds relationship Eriugena will give us his

final answer to the basic question under debate, namely, the way everything was created

in man.

Now, as Eriugena proceeds to explain in the discussion that follows that art is

nothing other than the notions of things”252 the relation of art to man is presented as

that of a substantial part to a whole.” (DDN IV: 767D) Consequently a conception of

human nature emerges according to which it consists of human mind, its art and the skill

that it needs to acquire the latter (Ibid). 253 It has been stated that this is a “trinity of

Mind” of co-essential and co-substantial members “in the same way that God the

252

Gracia, “Ontological Characterization,” 161. 253 See ibid. 162

Page 189: 988S

177

Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are coequal members of the Trinity.”254 This

interpretation, which is justified by the reference to Catholic Faith made in the passage

immediately following those words (DDN IV: 768A), has the additional merit of

showing how Eriugena considers the nature of human mind a theophanic reflection of

Divine nature, in accordance with the God-world relationship discussed in the previous

chapter.255 The “trinity of mind” is identified with the notion of man possessed by God

and eventually man is defined as “certain intellectual notion formed eternally in the

Divine mind.” (768B)

7.1.27.1.27.1.27.1.2 Containment and Human SelfContainment and Human SelfContainment and Human SelfContainment and Human Self----KnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledgeKnowledge

Now Gracia has made a problematic out of this definition of man by considering it to

imply “a most curious but at the same time important” consequence namely that,

“because he is a notion, man cannot know himself, for to do so would necessitate that he

contain the notion of man, that is himself, and that would be contradictory.”256 Gracia

thinks that Eriugena himself has put this point clearly at the end of 767D, as quoted by

him with certain words omitted, “the human mind understands through… its … art and

it is understood … in its art not in terms of what it is , but that it is; otherwise it would

not be a coessential and coequal trinity.” Now we would like to disagree with Gracia’s

reading of Eriugena. It seems that he has unnecessarily interpreted Eriugena as denying

the possibility of human self-knowledge as such. For, a milder conclusion can be drawn

which both does justice to the text of what Eriugena says and saves from any

contradiction as well. Eriugena has said in clearer statement on the issue at hand that “It

is only the Mind of God which possesses in Itself the true knowledge (notitiam veram)

254

Ibid. 255

This theme in Eriugena is briefly discussed below under the subject of Six days of creation. 256

Ibid. 163.

Page 190: 988S

178

of man.” (DDN IV: 768 A) Now the knowledge of man that is exclusively possessed by

Divine mind according to this statement of Eriugena is “perfect” knowledge of human

nature and this does not exclude the possibility of human self-knowledge as such. This is

implied by the italicized word “true” in the statement just quoted. This interpretation is

vindicated; moreover, by Eriugena’s explicit provision that although “there was in

human nature the potency of possessing the fullest knowledge of itself had it not

sinned,” the desire for bliss that remains in post-fall human nature would not have been

there “if she had lost all knowledge of herself and her God.” (See DDN IV: 777C-D)

Anyway the impossibility of true self-knowledge does not imply any

imperfection on the part of human being. It rather is a requirement of human deiformity,

“It is this which reveals most clearly the Image of God to be in man. For just as God is

comprehensible in the sense that He can be deduced from His creation that He is, and

incomprehensible because it cannot be comprehended by any intellect … what He is…

so to the human mind it is given to know one thing only, that it is—but as to what it is

no sort of notion is permitted it.” (DDN IV: 771B-C) Again, “Nor is this unreasonable.

For if it were known to be something, then at once it would be limited by some

definition and thereby cease to be a complete expression of the Image of its Creator”

(DDN IV: 771D) Hence Brian Stock’s conclusion257 that inasmuch as it bears the image

of God, human mind does not know itself and inasmuch as it does not bear that image, it

has self-knowledge, makes more sense in the light of our reading of Eriugena. On the

one hand it shows the connection of human self-knowledge with human deiformity and

257 See Brian Stock, “The Philosophical Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena,” Studi Medievali,

ser. 3a 8 (1967), 22.

Page 191: 988S

179

on the other hand tells us that the lack of self-knowledge does not imply imperfection

but dignity.

Besides, if one grants the conclusion drawn by Gracia, namely that according to

Eriugena man cannot know himself, it would seem curious that Eriugena himself is

trying to define man and at the same time saying that man cannot be known. Be that as

it may, this discussion of mind and art has established the essential relation between

man (i.e. human mind) and his knowledge of the things.

7.1.37.1.37.1.37.1.3 Containment in the Light of Holy ScriptureContainment in the Light of Holy ScriptureContainment in the Light of Holy ScriptureContainment in the Light of Holy Scripture

Let us now go back to the original question regarding the modality of containment in

the light of above discussion. The reasoning from 768 C onwards starts by showing that

“there is a kind of concept in man of all the sensible and intelligible things the human

mind understands.” This premise is based on an interpretation of the Holy Scripture

according to which man has been given dominion over everything. The Scriptural

passage referred to is Genesis: 2: 19 which reads, “Therefore having formed out of the

earth every beast of the field and every bird of the heavens The Lord God brought them

unto Adam to see what he would call them: and whatsoever he called every living soul

that is its name.” According to Eriugena’s own commentary, firstly, being able to name

the things implies a prior understanding of them (IV: 768D); secondly, whatever name

man gave to an object is the very notion of that object (name = notion); thirdly, the

notion of an object may be called its substance, for “where they are comprehended, there

they are; and they are nothing other than the understanding of themselves.” Hence,

“every creature is created as substance in man.” (DDN IV: 772A) The argument thus

constructed gives us Eriugena’s final answer as to how does man contain everything.

One logical gap, however, must be pointed out in this scripturally reasoned argument.

Page 192: 988S

180

What Eriugena seeks to show is a universal proposition, namely, “every creature is

created/contained in/by man” and the scriptural text seems not to warranty this

universal containment even granted the interpretation Eriugena offers for it. For, the

Genesis text does not talk about every creature but only about beasts and birds and at

the end explicitly limits its import to “the living.” It seems that Eriugena was aware of

this logical gap in his argument to a certain degree since in the next passage he claims

that the scope of human knowledge extends from animals to similar things “such as the

elements of the world, the genera and species of grasses and trees, quantities and

qualities and all the innumerable multitude of differentiations.” (DDN IV: 769B)

Although this statement bespeaks of an awareness of a logical gap in the argument from

Genesis 2: 19 to universal containment theory, it does nothing to fill it. Eriugena might

have filled the gap if, for instance, he held, like Ibn ‘Arabi,258 that there is nothing

among the creatures which is not alive.

Anyhow, the argument is recast at 774A, this time with an emphasis upon

hierarchy of mind, notions and things: “Furthermore, if the things themselves subsist

more truly in the notions of them than in themselves, and the notions of them are

naturally present to man, therefore in man are they universally created.” This passage

also points to another possible argument from the fact that everything Returns to its

Creator via man which implies that everything must already be in man.

Eriugena then tries to clarify a confusion regarding what has been said so far.

The alumnus inquires “in what way every creature is created in man seeing that man

258

Ibn ‘Arabi> says basing himself as usual upon the Qur’a>n that since everything sings glory of God, there

is nothing that is not alive. Fus}u>s}, 69 consequently he refuses to consider rationality (in the sense of being

able to speak) a defining characteristic of humanity since in the universe there is nothing which is not

alive and rational.

Page 193: 988S

181

himself was created last of all?” This question is especially interesting since Eriugena

wanted the fact that man was created last of all to imply that all was created in man.

The Alumnus, however, is pitching the very premise against the conclusion Eriugena

wants to draw from it (vide e.g., DDN IV: 782 C-D). The Nutritor starts a lengthy

discourse in response to the question raised, but what we are interested in here is the

way we can make sense of Eriugena’s position on the temporal sequence of creation of

everything. For in addition to accepting the Scriptural assertion of man’s creation being

the last as it is, he also says that “there was, then, no creature, either visible or invisible

before the creation of man—neither in place nor in time nor in rank nor in birth nor in

eternity nor, in a word, in any order of precedence.” (IV: 779D) Does Eriugena

contradict himself at this point? There is a way in which we can reconcile these two

positions.

It would appear from a careful reading of DDN IV: 781D to 786B that Eriugena

does not divide creation-process into two phases, one consisting of creation of

everything other than man and the other of creation of man himself. On the other hand,

he simply takes the whole work of six days to be the process of creation of man himself

in two phases. The work of first five days was in fact non-manifest creation of man

while the sixth day was the day of manifest creation of man. Speaking of the Sixth Day

Eriugena writes, “Thus man himself, whose creation is detail by detail mystically

foreshadowed in the contemplations of the Divine Act referred to before, seeing that all

the foregoing were created in him and with him, not in chronological order but the order

in which causes flow forth into their effects, is at last manifestly formed as the climax of

the whole universe…” (785D: emphasis added) In this light it can safely be said that

Eriugena’s position on the sequence of creation is not inconsistent.

Page 194: 988S

182

7.1.47.1.47.1.47.1.4 Containment and Six Days of CreationContainment and Six Days of CreationContainment and Six Days of CreationContainment and Six Days of Creation

Now the final point worth discussing under the subject of universal human containment

is to show in detail how everything mentioned to have been created on each of the Six

Days can be seen to exist in man. Eriugena introduces this detailed discussion as part of

response to a question asked by the Alumnus as to “why is man not introduced at the

very beginning of the contemplative Act of the whole creation, instead of at the

conclusion of all…?” (DDN IV: 782A). Now according to Eriugena’s interpretation of

Genesis, creation of Light on the First day means creation of “the principal part of man,

the most sublime light that is to say, intellect and reason together with the angelic

nature.” (DDN IV: 783C). Creation of the firmament on the Second Day is not

specifically interpreted to be in human nature but simply a rhetorical question is asked,

“Do we not recognize that the firmament … is established in the essence of man?”

(DDN IV: 783A-B) On the Third Day two elements of human nature namely “stability

of substance” and “instability of accidents” are signified to be created by two words

respectively, “Dry Land” and “Waters.” The Sun, Moon and Stars reported to have been

created on the Fourth Day are declared to be metaphorical expressions for three modes

of sensation which are established in human nature. The first mode likened to the Sun is

that which “without danger of error announces to the mind the species of the sensibles”

since “it does not deceive the mind but with all brightness of the sun uncovers every

sensible species.” (DDN IV: 783C-D) The second mode, likened to the Moon, is “one

through which the mind is often deceived” and “consequently it cannot easily form true

judgments upon objects it receives through sense.” (DDN IV: 783D) The third mode of

sensation “admits to the mind, in multiplicity and accumulation, numbers of sensible

forms” and “attempts by means of certain logical processes, to make statements which

will to some extent resemble the truth.” (784B). This mode is likened to the stars since

Page 195: 988S

183

it offers sometimes opinions “which like bright stars, show a degree of clarity and

proximity to the truth; sometimes opinions that are more obscure and farther from truth,

like dimmer stars.” (Ibid) Since these modes of sensation have been classed according to

the degree of certainty and clarity of data achieved through them, they can be seen to

form a spectrum the one extreme of which is the first mode that always gives certain

and true knowledge and on the other is the second mode which always deceives while

the third mode comes in the middle since sometimes it gives true knowledge and

sometimes it deceives. Eriugena thinks that the fact that the bodily senses are “signified

by the greater things of the world, namely the celestial bodies” implies human dignity

since the unity of man is greater than the whole universe. (DDN IV: 784D) The creation

of creeping things of the sea and birds of the air on the fifth day signifies a further

distribution within sensation since it is not confined to man but is shared by other

animals too.

We have already seen the way creation of man on sixth day fits in with the

preceding five days. We also find a numeric symbolism in Eriugena’s attempt to relate

the creation of everything to that of man. The creation of exterior sense of man,

symbolized by creation of sun, moon and stars, was mentioned by the Scripture to have

taken place on the fourth day since human body to which sense is attached is composed

out of four elements. (DDN IV: 783C) Likewise, the creation of sense common to all

nature was on the fifth day since the sense itself is fivefold. (Ibid. IV: 785C)

7.1.57.1.57.1.57.1.5 Unity and Trinity: Unity and Trinity: Unity and Trinity: Unity and Trinity: DivineDivineDivineDivine and Hand Hand Hand Humanumanumanuman

We observed in our discussion of “trinity of mind” that Eriugena impliedly asserts a

parallel between Divine trinity and human nature. In fact Eriugena addresses Divine

trinity in connection with human nature a bit more explicitly after treating of the Six

Page 196: 988S

184

Divine Days of Creation and tries to infer unequalled human dignity. He notes that the

reference to Holy Trinity in the account of creation of all things before that of man is

only implicit and can be read between the lines. In the words “In the beginning God

created Heaven and Earth”, God the Father is implied by “God”, Son by “the beginning”

while Holy Spirit is mentioned a little latter in the words, “And the Spirit of God

brooded over the waters.” However when it comes to the creation of man on the sixth

day “both the Unity and the Trinity of the Divine Nature are stated most explicitly, the

unity in the words and “He said” … while in the plural verb “Let Us make” are

expressed the three substances of the One Essence.” (786B-C)

It is not clear how one could differentiate the references in these texts to Trinity

by calling one implied and the other “most explicit.” However the reading of trinity in

verses relating story of creation of other beings is allegorical with a certain amount of

arbitrariness while it is symbolic in the case of verse relating the story of man’s creation

and required by an interpretational exigency.

Gracia’s paper on the ontological characterization of containment concluded that

according to Eriugena “What is created in man is not things (i.e. what Aristotle called

individuals or primary substances) or their characteristics, but the notions of things”

therefore, “rather the notions (notitiae) of things and their accidents find a place in the

human mind.”259 While this cannot be dismissed as invalid conclusion it must be pointed

out that in Eriugena’s philosophy there is no hard dichotomy between “notions” and

“primary substances” as is implied by Gracia’s conclusion. Eriugena identifies

“substance” with “notion” therefore when he predicates notion to something that does

not necessarily exclude the application of “substance” to it. Thus, while it is true that

259

Gracia, “Ontological Characterization,” 160.

Page 197: 988S

185

man contains everything in the sense of having their notion, it does not prevent

Eriugena to state that “every creature is created as substance in man.”(DDN IV: 722A)

Keeping in view this Eriugenian understanding of substance if we are asked whether

creatures are found in man in the sense of notions or substances, the answer would be,

“in both senses.” Moreover, Eriugena’s identification of creatures created in the five

days with things in human nature gives a third category to characterize containment,

namely, metaphor. When Eriugena likens, for example, the Sun, moon and stars with

three modes of human sensations and claims that these three celestial bodies are created

in human nature this means that it has their notions neither directly nor indirectly (i.e.

through saying that they substantially exist in human nature) rather a characteristic of

human nature is just being likened to something non-human. Therefore, if we are to take

the treatment of Six Days in book four of DDN seriously, Eriugena’s position on how

every creature is contained in man is much more complex.

Whatever analysis anyway is given to the doctrine of containment, its

importance in Eriugenian system cannot be denied. It is this doctrine, for one thing,

which explains why the function of bringing everything back to its creator should be

assigned to man. (vide DDN IV: 900D) It seems, however, that the logical relation

between containment and return via man is presented from both sides, that is, as

implying and being implied by each other. Same circularity of argument can be observed

in the attempts to relate containment to human deiformity. One reason as to “why he

wished to create all creation in him?” is that “He wished to make him in His image and

likeness, so that, just as the Primal Archetype transcends everything by the excellence of

His essence so His image should transcend all created things in dignity and grace.”

(DDN IV: 764B; Also see IV: 795). Earlier in book II, however, Eriugena has already

Page 198: 988S

186

said “man was made among primordial causes in the image of God that in him every

creature both intelligible and sensible of which he is composed as of various extremes

should become an inseparable unity, and that he should be the mediating term and

unification of all creatures.” (536B) Obviously, in the former text containment is the

means for human deiformity while in the latter it is the other way round.

7.27.27.27.2 IbnIbnIbnIbn ‘Arabi> on Man as Microcosm‘Arabi> on Man as Microcosm‘Arabi> on Man as Microcosm‘Arabi> on Man as Microcosm

Three concepts are central to Ibn ‘Arabi>’s view on the relationship between God, man

and the world: firstly, that man was created upon Divine image, secondly, that he is

God’s vicegerent upon earth and finally that he is microcosm. Here there is considerable

resonance between the thought of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> not only in broader outlines

but in certain important details as well, for instance, the scriptural groundedness of

these concepts, explanation of their meaning and their implications. Although, Eriugena

does mention occasionally the concept of human ‘‘dominion over all creatures’’ he does

not seem to make too much of it in his philosophical anthropology. However, this is a

negligible difference since, as we shall see, in Ibn ‘Arabi> the concept of human

vicegerency is given the same explanation as that of human deiformity and consequently

these two can be submerged. Accordingly, we will not discuss this topic separately but

will refer to it in our discussion of human deiformity. Although he is able to infer the

containment doctrine from some of the Qur’a>nic passages and Prophetic traditions, it is

the concept of human deiformity that is more explicitly grounded in the Islamic sources.

7.2.17.2.17.2.17.2.1 The Scriptural BasisThe Scriptural BasisThe Scriptural BasisThe Scriptural Basis

“The Human being that is Adam comprises of the World as a whole since He is the

small man and a summary of the Macrocosm,” writes Ibn ‘Arabi>. (Fut. II: 124; Also see

Fus}. 49-50) As usual he takes care to ground himself in the Revelation and refers to the

Page 199: 988S

187

Qur’a>n 41:53 “We shall show them Our signs in the Horizons and within their own

souls” and comments “… so that they know that human being is a summary (وجيز) of the

World consisting of the signs that are in the World.” (Ibid. II: 150) He also invites us to

note that this Qur’a>nic verse mentions the horizons, that is, the external world, prior to

the souls, that is, the inner world which is to show the precedence of the world over

human being. (See ibid. II: 151) Another Qur’a>nic teaching that Ibn ‘Arabi> appropriates

to shed light on the microcosm theory is that which states that God created Adam with

His two Hands. God asked Ibli>s, “What prevented you from prostrating yourself to him

whom I created with My two hands?” (38:75) Ibn ‘Arabi> thinks that creation with two

hands implies that God gave human nature all realities of the world and manifested

Himself for it through all the Divine Names. Consequently human nature possesses both

the Divine image and the Worldly image. He also thinks that man is to the world like

the human soul is to the human body. “Thus if Man departs the world, the world dies.”

(Fut. II: 468; Also see Fus}: 54-55) Apart from being a clue to the scriptural ground of

the notion, here we come across some other important points relevant from the

standpoint of comparison with Eriugenian anthropology. Firstly, by referring to the

Divine names, Ibn ‘Arabi> points towards an explanation of the meaning of man’s being a

microcosm. Secondly, he also points towards the intermediary status occupied by man

which is one of the reasons for human configuration to be the most universal of all

configurations. Thirdly, and finally, here there is also a hint toward the eschatological

significance of human micro-cosmic status, although Ibn ‘Arabi> does not seem to

provide further theoretical elaboration of that point. This parallels the Eriugenian view

that everything in this world returns to God through man since man contains everything.

Page 200: 988S

188

7.2.27.2.27.2.27.2.2 How is Man a Microcosm?How is Man a Microcosm?How is Man a Microcosm?How is Man a Microcosm?

Ibn ‘Arabi> writes at one place, “When God created the World as the Great Man and

made Adam and his progeny a summary of this world and for this reason gave him “All

the Names”, that is, all the names attending to existtiation (ايجاد) of the world ... The

world, therefore, as a whole is Great Man (ا8نسان الكبير).” (Fut. 3: 74) “All the Names,”

refer, of course, to the words of the Qur’a>n, “He taught Adam the Names, all of them.”

(2:31) These words echo, with certain important differences, Genesis 2:19 viz. “The

Lord God brought them unto Adam to see what he would call them: and whatsoever he

called every living soul that is its name.” Hence it is interesting to notice that parallel

scriptural passages are being interpreted identically by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. We

have described in the previous chapter how Ibn ‘Arabi> considers everything in the world

to be a theophany, i.e. manifestation of one or more of the Divine Names. Man’s being

microcosm or the world’s being Great Man is to be understood as man’s uniquely and

absolutely having share in all Divine names or being the locus of manifestation of all of

them.260 Ibn ‘Arabi> makes the point sometimes by drawing our attention to the

particular Divine Name, Alla>h, which occurs in the h}adi>th about Adam’s creation upon

Divine image. This name is the most comprehensive names and all other Divine names

are included in it and attributed to it.

7.2.37.2.37.2.37.2.3 Man as IntermediaryMan as IntermediaryMan as IntermediaryMan as Intermediary

Let us dwell a little more on the consequences of the facet of human nature just alluded

to. Human being’s having share in all Divine names make the human configuration the

most perfect of configurations (اكمل النشآت) (Fut. II: 103). Like Eriugena Ibn ‘Arabi>

260

Since the same explanation holds for the concept of human deiformity we will have the occasion to

further elaborate these points in the next subsection.

Page 201: 988S

189

emphasizes at a number of occasions man’s intermediary status ̀ by calling him an

Isthmus (برزخ). For instance he considers the Perfect Man as the middle (وسط) that

separates within the Divine Presence, the Manifest (الظاھر) and the Non-Manifest

hence, being a barzakh whose one face is turned towards the Manifest and the ,(الباطن)

other towards the Non-Manifest, he is the Real since he appears with the Divine Names

and he is creature since he appears with the reality of contingency. (See Fut. II: 391)

This double nature of human being according to Ibn ‘Arabi> can be considered to parallel

Eriugena’s notion of double nature of man as both an animal and not an animal with

noticing the difference that Ibn ‘Arabi> is presenting both aspects of human nature within

the Divine presence, leaving no room for disparaging the creaturely aspect. He also

writes that since God has taught man all the names and gave him the All-

Comprehensive words (جوامع الكلم) man brought-together-in-himself image of the Real

and image of the World. In this way he constitutes an intermediary between God and the

World. (See Fut. III: 298) Here Ibn ‘Arabi> can be seen as taking one step ahead of

Eriugena who maintained that man, being intermediary, combines in himself two sorts

of creatures, intellectual and material while Ibn ‘Arabi> is proposing for human nature a

more comprehensive status by considering it to be combining within itself both Divine

and cosmic images.

7.2.47.2.47.2.47.2.4 Man: the Final CreatureMan: the Final CreatureMan: the Final CreatureMan: the Final Creature

We saw Eriugena repeatedly referring to the fact that Man was created after everything

else in support of his notion of universal human containment. Likewise Ibn ‘Arabi>

repeatedly points out the fact that man is the final of creatures and connects this to the

doctrine of microcosm. Thus he says, “Man, therefore, is the Small world, while the

world is Great Man … so Man is the last begotten in the world that God has created as

Page 202: 988S

190

bringing together the realities of the whole world.” (Fut. II: 150; Also see II: 396) One

favorite phrase used by Ibn ‘Arabi> to express the idea that everything of the created

world is contained within human being is that “man was created upon the image of

World” or vice versa: “… He originally is upon the image of the World whose image is

after that of the Exalted One, so everything is upon His image.” (Ibid. III: 343; See also

II: 512 and II: 652) In the context of six days of creation Ibn ‘Arabi> says about Friday

that “the reason for its eminence is that it is the day on which this human configuration

was created for the sake of which the creatures were created from Sunday to Thursday.”

(Fut. I: 466) It goes without saying that here Ibn ‘Arabi> comes closest to Eriugenian

interpretation of the Six days of creation. Moreover, we saw Eriugena referring to the

words of Bible “Preach the Gospel to every creature.” (760A) impliedly taking them to

mean that every creature is in man. Interestingly Ibn ‘Arabi> has said something so

relevant that it seems almost a gloss on Eriugena’s use of these Biblical words in the

context of containment. Ibn ‘Arabi> writes about man that “certainly he is the sum total

of all realities of the world so he who addresses man addresses the whole world.” (Fut.

II: 95)

7.2.57.2.57.2.57.2.5 Microcosm: Problems of labeling Microcosm: Problems of labeling Microcosm: Problems of labeling Microcosm: Problems of labeling

Finally we have to deal with a critical issue of this comparative analysis of Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> on the containment doctrine. This issue concerns Eriugena’s and before him

St. Gregory of Nyssa’s refusal to call man microcosm and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s applying this

label to man. Ibn ‘Arabi> would not disagree with the claim that the principal reason for

human excellence is not the fact that man contains everything but that this eminence

consists rather in human deiformity: “You must know next that certainly Allah has

created man upon the best of moulds by virtue of the image (s}u>rah) with which He has

Page 203: 988S

191

distinguished him, and it is this (image) which has bestowed upon him this rank.” (Fut.

II: 616) He would however have disagreed with Gregory of Nyssa’s disparaging attitude

towards the world vis. a vis. man. We find him very careful about man’s being apex of

all creation that it should not lead him to disparage, enslave and exploit the world. He

therefore points out at one place the perspective from which the world has a rank higher

than that of the human beings: “Man, therefore, has no eminence over the world as a

whole, rather the world is more eminent than man since it is a degree above man that is

(the fact that) man was created out of the Macrocosm so it is a degree of causality above

him because he was begotten from it. … So it is mandatory for man to exalt his parents

and the world, all of it, is its mother.” (Fut. III: 11). For the sake of explanation of this

point one can use the whole-part symbolism and point out that although a whole is

greater than its parts nonetheless it is a whole thanks to its parts. Hence although “man

is a world apart and everything other than him is (not the whole world but) a part of the

world.” (Fut. I: 67) Although “the world is created due to man upon Divine image and if

the world is deprived of man, it would not be upon the image.” (Fut. III: 107), there is

no reason for holding the cosmos in contempt.

7.37.37.37.3 Human Deiformity: Eriugena on God and ManHuman Deiformity: Eriugena on God and ManHuman Deiformity: Eriugena on God and ManHuman Deiformity: Eriugena on God and Man

7.3.17.3.17.3.17.3.1 Preliminary: Scriptural BasisPreliminary: Scriptural BasisPreliminary: Scriptural BasisPreliminary: Scriptural Basis

The Bible tells us that God said “Let us make man in our image and likeness.” (Genesis

1: 26) Eriugena makes this concept an important part of his philosophical anthropology

since he logically connects, as we saw above, the containment of every creature in man

to this very doctrine. The central critical issue of Eriugena’s treatment of imago dei

from the standpoint of our present interest is the precise meaning of human creation

upon Divine image with a number of questions to which this gives rise, for instance,

Page 204: 988S

192

whether or not the whole human nature participates in it, why was man so created, does

deiformity extend to the whole humanity or simply to Christ and what metaphysical

principles are involved in the notion. Many other peculiar Eriugenian doctrines emerge

as episodes of the attempt to make sense of his position, for instance, interpretation of

the original sin, the fall, spiritual body, the nature of paradise etc. We, however, cannot

discuss these in this subsection and will be content with the questions just mentioned.

7.3.27.3.27.3.27.3.2 Human Body and DeiformityHuman Body and DeiformityHuman Body and DeiformityHuman Body and Deiformity

Just as man mediates intelligible and sensible creatures he combines within his nature

the characteristics of animals and those of celestial essences. Hence he both is and is not

an animal (animal est, animal non est). There is, thus, a double nature261 to man.

For when consideration is given to his body, his nutritive Life Force, to his

senses, and to his memory of sensible and to all his irrational appetites such as

rage and covetousness, he is altogether an animal... but in his nature which

consists of reason and mind, and the interior sense, with all their rational

motions which are called virtues and with the memory of the eternal and Divine

things, he is altogether other than animal. (DDN IV: 752C-D)

These two aspects of human nature Eriugena terms “Outer man/Animal Man”

and “Inner Man/Spiritual Man” referring to St. Paul who uses the words “animalis

homo” and “spiritualis homo” at 1 Cor. 2:14-16. (DDN IV: 753A-B) To the double

nature of man corresponds his double creation: “That in him which resembles the

animals was created with the animals and that which resembles spiritual creatures was

created with the spiritual creatures. (Ibid. IV: 753C)

Thus emerges Eriugena’s answer to one of the important questions raised above:

it is only man’s interior and intellectual nature which is made in the image of God, as far

261

On this point see Brian Stock, “The Philosophical Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena,” 13-14.

Page 205: 988S

193

as his exterior, his body, is concerned, it is “external to human nature which is made in

the image of God” and is “superimposed upon it because of our sin.” (Ibid. IV: 799D)

Moreover, the division of human beings into male and female is also not part of

deiformity but a consequence of Sin. (See ibid. IV: 827A) Gregory of Nyssa, whom we

shall find Eriugena quoting at length, has in fact said that the qualities of being male

and female are “alien from the properties of God.” (Ibid. IV: 795B) The correspondence

between inner/ outer dichotomy and male/female one is worthy of notice since it

becomes the foundation of an allegory that Eriugena presents while interpreting the

Scriptural passages about Adam, Eve and the Serpent. Eriugena writes: “And the

ancient enemy would not have access to the male part of the soul that is the mind which

is created in the image of God, unless first he had seduced the corporeal sense, which is,

so to speak, a woman.” (DDN IV: 847C) Hence in the story of the fall inner man/ outer

man dichotomy is synonymous with male/female dichotomy. Hence it is not complete

human being, “the complete workshop” that is created upon Divine image according to

Eriugena but only one aspect of it.

What about the fact that Man committed the sin after a body was attached to

him and was divided into sexes? Eriugena has to reply first with the doctrine that “all

things …were created at one and the same time.” (DDN IV: 807B) The two creations,

therefore, took place simultaneously. Secondly, he has to tell us that in view of His

foreknowledge at the same time that God created man He created the consequences of

his sin even before he sinned. (See ibid. IV: 807C). Thirdly, in an implied contradiction

to Augustine, and perhaps to himself as well, Eriugena is not ready to believe that the

body that was attached originally to Adam was this very material and earthly body

Page 206: 988S

194

rather it was a spiritual body. He speaks of this body in an eloquent passage consisting

of contrasts between pre-fall and post-fall human bodies. (See ibid. IV: 760A-C)

Since Eriugena has provided for man being “everywhere a whole in himself” the

Alumnus thinks that it follows that “the whole image must subsist in the whole animal

and the whole animal in the whole Image throughout the whole man.” (Ibid. IV: 759A)

In response Eriugena claims that it is here precisely that “the image and likeness of God

in human nature can be recognized” and seeking help of the superlative theology

attempts to show that just as by being “whole in all things He does not cease to be

whole beyond all things” in the same way human nature is in its own world. “For even

the lowest and least valuable part, the body is according to its own principles whole in

whole man, for the body, insofar as it is truly body, subsists in its own principles which

were made at the beginning of creation.” (Ibid. IV: 759B) Hence, to the question

whether man was created upon Divine image in his whole being (body as well as higher

intellectual nature) Eriugena would like to give a Yes and No answer just like he gives

in response to questions about predicating attributes to the Divine Essence. This last

mentioned fact mitigates Eriugena’s otherwise disparaging attitude towards human

body. He moreover is careful not to seem “attacking wedlock and the procreation of

children” in his maintaining that the division of human nature into male and female

were the penalties for transgression. He explains that not only he does not attack these

institutions rather praises them since “they are permitted and ordained by God.” (See

ibid IV: 846D-847 B)

7.3.37.3.37.3.37.3.3 Which man was made upon Which man was made upon Which man was made upon Which man was made upon DivineDivineDivineDivine Image?Image?Image?Image?

Eriugena gives a rather long quotation from Saint Gregory of Nyssa’s De Hominis

Opificio (On the making of Man) (DDN IV: 793C-797D) and it is through this quotation

Page 207: 988S

195

that one can see most clearly how Eriugena would characterize human deiformity, since

the latter does not disagree on any point with what he cites.

St. Gregory poses the question “how an unhappy thing can be called by Holy

Scripture a similitude of what is Divine and blessed?” (Ibid. IV: 794D) and answers,

“That which was made in the image is one thing and that which is shown now to be in

unhappiness another” (Ibid. IV: 795A). It is implied by the explanation that he gives for

this in the light of a careful analysis of Genesis 1:26-27, that it was Jesus Christ, the

Logos, which was made upon the Image of God and not the fallen human beings, the

creation of whom, he thinks is intended in particular by Genesis 1: 27, “Male and

Female created He Them” (Ibid), “While in Christ Jesus there is neither male nor

female.” (Ibid) Strangely, contrary to the point made here, we find Gregory going on to

show that Divine image does extend to whole of humanity. He first of all draws

attention to the fact that “man” instead of “Adam” is mentioned in the Genesis (Ibid.

IV: 797A) and secondly that mind is allotted to all men alike” (Ibid. IV: 797B-C) and

concludes that “the man who was revealed in the first constitution of the world and the

man who is to come after the consummation of all things both equally bear within them

the Divine Image.” (DDN IV: 797C). There seems to be considerable ambivalence as to

who precisely was made upon the Divine image in the passages quoted by Eriugena

although the latter does not take any notice of it and proceeds to cite another passage

from the same book on the issue of male-female differentiation.

The considerations made until this point in the present subsection were mainly

of a negative nature in the sense that they purported to show that according to Eriugena

human deiformity does not extend to certain elements of human nature. It is necessary

now to attend to the positive side of the subject and attempt to understand what it really

Page 208: 988S

196

means for the human being to have been created upon Divine image in positive terms in

addition to the fact that the higher reaches of human nature participate in the imago dei.

7.3.47.3.47.3.47.3.4 WhyWhyWhyWhy and and and and howhowhowhow man was made upon the man was made upon the man was made upon the man was made upon the DivineDivineDivineDivine Image?Image?Image?Image?

The real attempt at explaining the meaning of human deiformity is made by Gregory

with reference to Divine Nature in general and Divine Goodness in particular. Since

“God creates human life for no other reason than that well-being should be its property”

and since God is free of stinginess and envy, He implied a perfect power of goodness and

He did not withhold full participation of man in all that He contains.” This statement

can become a compact answer to the question as to why God created man upon Divine if

it is interpreted, as it must be, in the light of traditional principle that “Good tends to

communicate itself.”262 In this light the meaning of saying that God created man upon

His image means that “He bestowed upon man all of His goodness, withholding

nothing.” The Scriptural passage informing us of human deiformity can be taken as

summary of all good qualities that were given to human being. Thus,

“The catalogue of individual goods is long and not easy to enumerate, Scripture

indicates them all comprehensively by saying that man was made in the image

of God. For by this is meant that he made human nature a participant in every

good. For if God is the plenitude of good things and man is an image of God the

image must resemble the Primal Exemplar in this respect also, that it is the

plenitude of all good. (DDN IV: 795C-796A)

In chapter V of De Hominis Opificio Gregory has given some examples of the

Divine qualities as they manifest themselves in us. God is mind and word and “you see

in yourself word and understanding, an imitation of the very Mind and word.” God is

love and “the Fashioner of our nature has made this to be our feature too.” Finally, “the

262

We take this formulation of the principle from Frithjof Schuon.

Page 209: 988S

197

Deity beholds and hears all things and searches all things out; you too have the power of

apprehension of things by means of sight and hearing…”263 In this citation too Gregory

is taking the view that Divine image is not the privilege of Logos only but extends to

the whole genus of humanity, as the words “in yourself,” “our feature” and “you too”

indicate.

7.3.57.3.57.3.57.3.5 The Metaphysical Principle of DeiformityThe Metaphysical Principle of DeiformityThe Metaphysical Principle of DeiformityThe Metaphysical Principle of Deiformity

One metaphysical principle, namely, that the Good tends to communicate itself, has

already been referred to supra in our comment on the first sentence of quotation from

Gregory of Nyssa. Another related principle is firstly presupposed by his question “how

an unhappy thing can be called by Holy Scripture a similitude of what is Divine and

blessed?” and eventually is brought out at the end of the lines we quoted above. This is

the principle that the image must resemble the Exemplar perfectly. Perfect image is

defined as one which has all features common with the archetype (DDN IV: 822A)

Eriugena asks, “How would [the soul] be an image if in some aspect she differed from

that of which she is the image? Except of course in relation of the subject about which

we spoke in earlier books when we were discussing the Prototype or Principle-exemplar

and its image.” (DDN IV: 778A)

As the ending of this rhetorical question indicates, the universal resemblance of

image to its Archetype does not exclude difference between the two. Eriugena has

stated that the Exemplar is “subsisting through, by and in Himself, neither created nor

formed nor changed by anything” while the image is, “created by Him Whose image it

is, it has received being in accordance with its nature…” (Ibid) This fact must not be

taken as a self-contradiction since firstly, both Gregory of Nyssa and Eriugena are

263

Gregory of Nyssa: Dogmatic Treatises etc.: On the Making of Man, (Grand Rapids, CCEL) p. 534

Page 210: 988S

198

speaking simultaneously of “all but two” and not firstly of “all” and then of “not the two

differences.” Secondly, it must be remembered as was said in a former chapter that this

exception is not made arbitrarily but is required by the very nature of things. Although

the image is image of the Exemplar, it still is image and not the Exemplar. In the

language of superlative theology it would be more appropriate to say that the image

both is and is not the Exemplar, the affirmation applies from the perspective of its being

an image while the negation does from its not being the Exemplar.

7.47.47.47.4 Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on Ibn ‘Arabi> on alalalal----S}u>rah alS}u>rah alS}u>rah alS}u>rah al----Ila>hiyyahIla>hiyyahIla>hiyyahIla>hiyyah

The central place of human deiformity in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s epistemology with special

reference to his short treatise Insha> al-Dawa>’ir has already been studied at length by

Mastaka Takeshita.264 Our focus here, as in the previous chapters, will be on Ibn

‘Arabi>’s Futu>h}a>t with occasional references to Fus}u>s }. In this section we make an

attempt to find out responses to issues raised by its Eriugenian form. These include the

scriptural foundations of the concept, its meaning, the question whether or not

deiformity extends to the whole human race, the status of human body and the division

of sexes, the metaphysical explanation of the deiformity and implications for the ethical

realm. We begin our investigation of this topic with discussing Islamic foundations of

the concept of human deiformity.

7.4.17.4.17.4.17.4.1 The The The The Islamic FoundatiIslamic FoundatiIslamic FoundatiIslamic Foundations of the Concept in Ibn ‘Arabi>ons of the Concept in Ibn ‘Arabi>ons of the Concept in Ibn ‘Arabi>ons of the Concept in Ibn ‘Arabi>

Although the exact parallel of the Biblical homo imago dei is not found in the Qur’a>n

Ibn ‘Arabi> thinks it can be inferred from one of its verses. He therefore writes, “He (i.e.

God) said about man that He has ‘created man in the best of moulds (أحسن تقويم)’ (95:4), 264

See his paper “The Homo Imago Dei Motif and the Anthropocentric Metaphysics of Ibn ‘Arabi> in the

Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir,” in Orient: Report of the Society for Near Eastern Studies in Japan, XVIII (1982), 111-

129.

Page 211: 988S

199

i.e. the mould upon which He has created man is more excellent than every other mould

and this quality, due to which man was given excellence over others, would not become

true except for Allah’s creating him upon His form.” (Fut. II: 683) Although the words

“more excellent than every other mould” express “comparative degree” they really

should be taken in the sense of superlative degree, above which no other degree exists

since this is what is required by the grammatical form of the noun “ah}san” in the

Qur’a>nic verse. This point is of importance because it makes possible the identification

of “Divine form” to “best of moulds.” Ibn ‘Arabi> himself has paid attention to this point

by stating, “So he (i.e. man) was upon the best of moulds not by (way of) comparison

(mufa>d}alah) … rather it is the absolute goodness for the perfect servant like the absolute

majesty that is the Real’s, so he is best of moulds not compared to this or that like the

Real is Great (akbar) not in comparison with this or that.” (Fut. II: 616)

A more direct foundation for the concept of human deiformity, however, is a

h}adi>th according to which Prophet Muh}ammad (peace be upon him) forbade slapping

someone on his face saying “Certainly Allah has created Adam upon His form.”265 The

context of this Prophetic text signals one important implication of human deiformity in

Islam different from the Christian thought, especially Eriugena. That is, it implies the

inclusion of human body in creation upon Divine form. Were it not for this fact it would

have not been possible to extend the ethical repercussion to physical punishment.

A comparison of the above quoted h}adi>th text with the Biblical text about

creation on Divine image reveals another important difference which enables Ibn ‘Arabi>

to add an interpretational nicety. According to the Bible God spoke in the first person

(our image) but in the h}adi>th we have the third person “his.” Ibn ‘Arabi> thinks that this

265

Muslim, Al- Ja>mi‘ al- S}ah}i>h}, Kita>b al- birr wa al-s}ilah, ba>b al-Nahy ‘an d}arb al-wajh.

Page 212: 988S

200

statement can be read and understood in two ways depending upon which noun one

thinks is being qualified by the pronoun “his” in “his form.” In addition to the prevalent

imago dei reading one can interpret these words as “God has created Adam upon

Adam’s Form,” since grammatically a pronoun refers to a noun that is closest to it in a

sentence. Although the context of the h}adi>th makes this interpretation a little odd Ibn

‘Arabi>’s explanation of it makes a lot of sense given the fact that Adam was the first

human being directly created by God: “he did not pass from one stage of creation to

another like semen passes stage by stage from being water to being man, rather God

created him as he appeared.” (Fut. II: 124) One could add another interpretation of this

second reading of the h}adi>th by saying that God created Adam into the spatio-temporal

world according to the form Adam eternally had in Divine knowledge. Although Ibn

‘Arabi> does not give this interpretation, it is based on his general doctrine of creation as

bestowal of existence upon the fixed entities which are objects of Divine knowledge. In

Eriugenian terminology, to say that God created Adam upon his image would mean that

he created him firstly as a primordial cause and then he was created in this spatio-

temporal world. Be that as it may, apart from the short passage just cited Ibn ‘Arabi>

always takes the h}adi>th to mean that Adam was created upon Divine form.

7.4.27.4.27.4.27.4.2 The Meaning of Deiformity The Meaning of Deiformity The Meaning of Deiformity The Meaning of Deiformity

What does Ibn ‘Arabi> understand by man’s creation upon the image/form of God? His

understanding of human deiformity is similar to the one cited by Eriugena from Saint

Gregory of Nyssa according to which it means that God gave man all of his goodness.

Ibn ‘Arabi> asks us first of all to notice the particular Divine name that is mentioned in

the h}adi>th informing us of human deiformity, that is “Allah” rather than “Al-Qayyu>m”

or “Al- Jabba>r” etc. He therefore says, “So Adam appeared upon the image of the name

Page 213: 988S

201

“Allah” since that name encompasses all Divine names.” (Fut. II: 124). Although

everything in the world manifests some particular Divine quality, it is only the “human

configuration” in which all Divine names manifest themselves since ‘Allah taught Adam

the Names, all of them,’ “that is the Divine Names from which all the objects were

created.” (Fut. I: 216) As he understands it, one thing cannot be said to be upon the

image of another unless it is identical to it in all respects. (See Fut. III: 344) Hence Ibn

‘Arabi> shares with Eriugena, in general terms, the principle of image exemplar identity.

In this context Ibn ‘Arabi> builds upon another important Qur’a>nic concept i.e. human

vicegerency (خ\فة). Before creating Adam God said to the Angels “I will create a

vicegerent on earth.” (II: 30) A vicegerent (خليفة) cannot be properly so called unless he

is given the qualities of the one whose vicegerent he is made: “Vicegerency was for

Adam over against other genera of the world in view of Allah’s having created him upon

his image as the vicegerent appears to what he has made vicegerent on, in the image of

the one who made him vicegerent otherwise he would not be a vicegerent in them.”

(Fut. I: 263) In response to the question “What characterizes Adam?” he explains “His

characteristic attribute is the Divine Presence if you will or the totality of Divine names

if you will.” (Fut. I: 67) At another place we find him saying “‘God created Adam upon

His image’ that is, everything that applies to the Divine Presence applies both to the

Small Man and the Great Man.” (Fut. 2: 139) The Divine names obviously connote

some qualities and man’s manifesting the names means being able to realize those

qualities. This fact becomes the foundation of an ethics based upon the concept of

human deiformity. Ibn ‘Arabi> has written, “He, the Exalted One, did not name Himself

with any of the Names except that He made a share from it for human being to assume

its character trait (تخلق) (Fut. I: 124). We would say more about the ethical implications

of this doctrine below.

Page 214: 988S

202

7.4.37.4.37.4.37.4.3 Does the Does the Does the Does the DivineDivineDivineDivine image extend to all human beings? image extend to all human beings? image extend to all human beings? image extend to all human beings?

With reference to a passage quoted by Eriugena from Saint Gregory we observed that

although it was Christ and not the fallen human being that was made upon the Divine

image the whole of humanity is included in the Divine image in a manner explained

neither by Gregory nor by Eriugena. We have to see now who precisely was made upon

the Divine image according to Ibn ‘Arabi>. Unfortunately, his position on this question is

as ambivalent as that of Eriugena since he seems to limit Divine image to the primordial

Perfect Man and at the same time not only extends it to what he calls “the Animal Man”

(al-insa>n al-haywa>n) but to the whole world. After looking at a few texts from Al-

Futu>h}a>t which underscore these two positions we would attempt to interpret the

ambivalence and see if that interpretation can be helpful in making sense of the

viewpoint of St. Gregory/Eriugena as well. The assertion that Divine image is the

privilege of the Perfect man in Ibn ‘Arabi> is made possible in the first place by the

Islamic textual foundation of the concept of human deiformity, i.e. the h}adi>th which,

unlike the Bible, does not say that “Man” was created upon Divine image but uses the

word “Adam.” This point is important for our comparative analysis because we have

seen St. Gregory emphasizing and utilizing the fact that Biblical text uses the word

“man” instead of “Adam.” It is also important since it would make it possible for Ibn

‘Arabi> to be more explicit in limiting the Divine image to the Perfect Man which he

identifies at Fut. II: 468 with Adam. Hence he says about the Perfect Man that “no one

contains the Divine image other than him.” (Ibid. III: 282) Again, “Certainly not every

human being is upon the Image since there is the Animal Man as well as the Vicegerent

Man.” (Ibid. IV: 56) Animal man resembles the Perfect man in his external form but not

otherwise “just as a monkey resembles man in respect of all his external organs” (Ibid.

III: 266)

Page 215: 988S

203

On the other hand we find Ibn ‘Arabi> saying in so many words that “the Divine

image has a governing property (h}ukm)266 in every individual.” (Ibid. III: 184) He also

says in passing that not only the Perfect Man but his vicegerents (khulafa>’uh) were also

created upon the Divine image. (See ibid. III: 280) Even more interesting is the fact that

he does not see any discrepancy between fallen man’s ability to sin and the share he has

out of deiformity. In Ibn ‘Arabi>’s opinion man is able to disobey his Lord only because

he was created upon the Divine image.

Is there any way to reconcile the two seemingly contradictory positions, holding

on the one hand that a particular human being, whether Adam, Christ, Inner Man or

Perfect man was created upon the Divine image and on the other hand that the image

extends to the whole of humanity? One way to this reconciliation could be to opine that

the primordial man enjoyed the Divine image to its absolute perfection while the rest of

humanity has merely some share from it. On the basis of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s explication of

deiformity in terms of the doctrine of Divine names, one could say that every human

being including the primordial man has a share in some basic Divine attributes like Life,

Knowledge, Power etc. while it is only the primordial man who has actualized all the

rest of attributes as well. Other human beings have to struggle in order to realize those

attributes. This interpretation is made plausible by reference to the final return of

everything to the Divine Goodness according to Eriugenian thought and to the ethics of

Divine names in Ibn ‘Arabi> which we shall discuss below in section 7.4.8.

266

We have translated the word h}ukm here as “governing property” following William Chittick. For

various possible translations of this word see his Sufi Path of Knowledge, 48.

Page 216: 988S

204

7.4.47.4.47.4.47.4.4 The Cosmic DeiformityThe Cosmic DeiformityThe Cosmic DeiformityThe Cosmic Deiformity

Ibn ‘Arabi> stretches his doctrine of creation upon Divine image beyond humanity and

states that the whole world was created upon God’s image (See Fut. II: 403; IV: 231) in

the sense of manifesting the realities of the Divine Names (See ibid. II: 139).

Lest it be thought that the concept of macrocosmic deiformity contradicts what

Ibn ‘Arabi> said elsewhere (i.e. Ibid. III: 8) about man being more perfect than

everything, we would like to add Ibn ‘Arabi>’s argument that the World becomes perfect

only when man is included in it and without Man it is imperfect. (Ibid. III: 343) The fact

that there is no clash between human and cosmic deiformity can be seen through

observing that Ibn ‘Arabi> infers the former from the latter through the concept of

containment. (See ibid.)

The concept of macrocosmic deiformity is one of those important points where

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s position diverges from that of Eriugena and his Cappadocian predecessor

Gregory. As we noticed that Gregory’s refusal to apply the term microcosm to man was

based on contempt for the world as compared to man who is believed to be exclusively

created upon Divine image. Ibn ‘Arabi> however extends deiformity to include cosmos

itself and this has profound ethical implication for the human behavior towards the

world that surrounds us. Thus he goes beyond Eriugena on this point although both

agree on the identification of creation with Divine self-manifestation and the general

concept of theophany.

7.4.57.4.57.4.57.4.5 Human Body and deiformity Human Body and deiformity Human Body and deiformity Human Body and deiformity

On the question of body’s participation in the Divine image Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>

represent differing standpoints and this can easily be explained with reference to their

different traditional backgrounds. We have seen that Eriugena does not think that

Page 217: 988S

205

human deiformity extends to human body but holds that man was created upon the

Divine image in his soul only, that body was attached to the soul as punishment for the

Sin, although we also observed him making a comment which somewhat mitigates his

negative attitude towards human body. We observed in the beginning of this section on

Ibn ‘Arabi> that the context of the h}adi>th about imago dei refers primarily to the physical

part of human being. This fact coupled with the general non-disparaging view towards

human body in Islam leaves no room for the exclusion of human body from deiformity.

For Ibn ‘Arabi> one factor adding to this difficulty is his doctrine, explored in the

previous chapter, that whatever appears in this spatio-temporal world is rooted in the

Divine Nature. Likewise there is nothing in the world without a share from the Divine

form. (See ibid. II: 431) The existence of bodies is ontologically rooted in the Divine

Name al-Z}a>hir (the Manifest).(See ibid. II: 433) Far from being punishment and

debasement it was out of Divine mercy that bodies were attached to the souls. (See ibid.

III: 171) Ibn ‘Arabi> would also differ on Eriugena’s exclusion of bodily senses from

deiformity. Referring to a h}adi>th in which God is reported to have said about the servant

He loves that He becomes “his hearing through which he hears and his eyesight through

which he sees” Ibn ‘Arabi> draws our attention to the fact that God Almighty has

mentioned the sensory form but did not describe Himself as rational, reflecting or

imagining. (Ibid. III: 189). More particularly, he thinks that the human sensory faculties

are rooted in the Divine nature just like everything else that exists. (Ibid.)

There is one place where it might seem that Ibn ‘Arabi> does hold the view that

human body is excluded from deiformity.267 Speaking about the Angels’ objection to

creation of Adam as vicegerent upon earth as mentioned in the Qur’a>n Ibn ‘Arabi> writes,

267

We have analyzed Ibn ‘Arabi>’s views on body more fully in “Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Metaphysics of Human

Body,” in Islamic Studies, 46 (2007), 499-525.

Page 218: 988S

206

“(man) is not called khali>fah except through the perfection of Divine image … that is

why the Angels saw nothing of Adam except his dense, elemental, dark bodily and

physical appearance and said what they said but when God informed them of perfection

of image in it and asked them to prostrate before him, they hurried in prostrating before

him.” (Ibid. III: 156) However, the concern of this passage is the perfection of Divine

form and not its existence or non-existence. Therefore, what this passage shows is not

that the soul is deiform over against the body but that in the former Divine form is

perfect while in the latter it is not.

Another issue related to that of the human body vis. a vis. human deiformity is

that of the division of mankind between male and female which Eriugena thinks was an

addition to the pristine humanity as a consequence of the Sin. At this point too Ibn

‘Arabi> does not agree with Eriugena and the difference in the present case too is

understandable in terms of traditional background of these two writers. For one thing

the Qur’a>n mentions repeatedly the phenomenon of male-female divide, although not

exclusively human but cosmic as well, as one of the signs of Allah and His blessings.

(See e.g. 16: 72; 30:21 and 78:8) Although the h}adi>th about Divine image mentions

Adam this should not be taken to mean the exclusion of Eve from deiformity since

“Man includes woman because Eve is a part of Adam.” (Ibid. I: 541) Ibn ‘Arabi> also tells

us that Adam was created upon Divine image while Eve was created upon Adam’s

image which logically implies that Eve was also created upon Divine image. (See ibid. I:

679)

7.4.67.4.67.4.67.4.6 ThThThThe Ethical e Ethical e Ethical e Ethical Dimensions Dimensions Dimensions Dimensions of Deiformity of Deiformity of Deiformity of Deiformity

Ibn ‘Arabi> points out that by being informed of creation upon Divine image humanity is

put to one of the greatest trials. The purpose of this trial is to see whether man “stands

Page 219: 988S

207

by his servanthood and contingency or becomes conceited due to the status of his

image.” (See ibid. II: 189) The success in this trial consists of never losing sight of

servanthood, contingency, poverty and needfulness. (Ibid.) Those human beings who

forgot these essential qualities and claimed divinity for themselves actually failed this

trial. (See ibid. II: 642) In this respect, as well as in some others, deiformity is likened to

human vicegerency. The office of caliphate brings with it enormous responsibilities and

as was said in one h}adi>th Ibn ‘Arabi> refers to, it will be an occasion of regret for those

who failed to fulfill these responsibilities. (See ibid. III: 183-4) Ibn ‘Arabi> advises that it

might help us abstain from taking pride in our deiformity if we look at the world around

us, which although was created for our sake, still its creation is greater than ours. (See

ibid. III: 9) In addition to these guidelines Ibn ‘Arabi> makes the fact that man was

created upon Divine image in the sense that Divine names and qualities manifest

through man a basis for an ethics of Divine names. Deiformity, as we repeatedly

noticed, implies that the Divine qualities, connoted by the Divine Names, were

bestowed upon man. Now some of these qualities, like Life and Vision were bestowed

upon each and everyone while we are ethically obliged to realize in our personalities all

the rest of qualities. Divine Mercy, for example, requires human being to be merciful

and so on.268

7.4.77.4.77.4.77.4.7 Why Human Deiformity?Why Human Deiformity?Why Human Deiformity?Why Human Deiformity? Metaphysical Explanations Metaphysical Explanations Metaphysical Explanations Metaphysical Explanations

Gregory of Nyssa, as quoted by Eriugena, explained human deiformity by referring to

Divine quality of Goodness. What explanation do we find in Ibn ‘Arabi>? Well, he tells

us that “Certainly Allah has not created the creature for the sake of creation but as an

268

See Qaiser Shahzad, “Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Contribution to the Ethics of Divine Names” in Islamic Studies

XLIII (2004), 5-39.

Page 220: 988S

208

example for Him … For this reason He made him upon His image.” (Ibid. IV: 252) Since

God willed to be known and He could not be known except by someone who is upon His

image he created man upon His image. (See Fut. III: 266) This explanation is of course

based on a saying oft quoted by Ibn ‘Arabi> and other Sufis as raison d’être of the

creation namely, “I was a hidden treasure and I loved to be known so I created the

creature.” In the very beginning of Fus}u>s} al- H}ikam Ibn ‘Arabi> put this idea as under:

The Real willed, glorified be He, in virtue of His Beautiful Names, which are

innumerable, to see their identities -- if you so wish you can say: to see His

Identity—in a comprehensive being (kawn ja>mi‘) that comprises the whole

affair… For the vision a thing has of itself in itself is not like the vision a thing

has of itself in another thing, which will be like a mirror for it. (Fus. 48 Trans.

Ringstones, 3)

Hence the deiform man is a mirror created by God for Himself. The explanation

given by Gregory/Eriugena for deiformity is similar to the one provided by Ibn ‘Arabi> in

respect of the fact that both refer to God, but more precisely, whereas the former takes

into account the Divine Nature, the latter revolves around Divine Will. Divine Nature is

concerned with the way Divinity is and the Divine Will obviously concerns what It

wants or desires.269

The metaphysical explanation also includes an exploration of the relation that

exists between the Divine Exemplar and its human image, whether it implies complete

identity or allows some ontological gap between the two. It was observed in the

discussion of imago dei in Eriugena that in spite of being grounded in the principle of

complete exemplar-image resemblance, he does retain the basic creator-creature

269

This important distinction we take from Frithjof Schuon who has shown how losing sight of it leads to

theological mistakes in his essay “Dilemmas Within Ash‘arite Theology” in Islam and the Perennial

Philosophy.

Page 221: 988S

209

difference. Let us now look at the way Ibn ‘Arabi> conceives this issue. Like Gregory and

Eriugena Ibn ‘Arabi> does firmly believe that the image must resemble the exemplar in

all respects and he is likewise careful to emphasize that this principle does not imply a

collapse of Creator-creature distinction.270 His position is, further, a little more

elaborate than the other two writers’. He writes that “It cannot be said about one thing

that it is upon the image (‘ala> s}u>rah) of something unless it be that thing in all respects

except that which cannot be said to be (identical to) it.” (Fut. III: 343) However this

does not collapse all the distinctions, so after all “The Real is The Real, human being is

human being and the world is the world.” (Ibid.) Therefore being upon image of the

exemplar means that most of what can be said about the latter can also be said about the

former but this does not imply that we have one entity instead of two or that the

essential defining characteristics of both are same. We find further explanatory remarks

on this point in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s writings. At one place he says drawing our attention to the

word “created” in the hadi>th that “Allah created Adam upon His image” that it lets man

know that even though he is upon the image of God, he still is creature and consequently

he does not become haughty. (See ibid. IV: 210). This distinction between exemplar and

image with reference to createdness was recognized by Eriugena as we saw above.

Human deiformity, as Ibn ‘Arabi> views it, is just like weighing a gold bar with iron-

weights, just as the latter does not equal the former so “nothing can be weighed by the

human form except what it requires from amongst the Divine Names of the sum of

which it consists and the ones that attended to its creation and which manifested their

effects within it.” (Fut. III: 8) Image exemplar identity is thus to be understood with

reference to creatures’ being loci of manifestation of Divine Names, however on this

270 See 7.4.2 supra.

Page 222: 988S

210

point too Ibn ‘Arabi> is careful to emphasize the creator-creature boundary. Thus he says

that although all the Divine names can apply to the Perfect Man who was created upon

Divine image, nevertheless these names apply to him individually ( ًفرداً فردا) and one by

one ( ًبعضاً بعضا) and the totality of Divine names does not apply to him in one word so

that the Lord be distinguished from the perfect servant. (See Fut. III: 409) What he

means in fact is that although man can be addressed with all the Divine names, unlike

God himself whose essential name is “Allah” which contains all other Divine names,

man does not possess any such all-comprehensive name in which other names should be

included.

By making these qualifications Ibn ‘Arabi> is concerned as much with ethical

dimensions of human deiformity as he is with the metaphysical truth. He continues to

say after giving the iron-weight example, “So know that you are (as if) an iron-weight

with which an unparalleled corundum, has been weighed even though you equal it in

quantity you do not equal its worth or its essence or its characteristic, exalted is Allah,

so stick to your servanthood and know your worth.” (Ibid. III: 8-9)

Why there should be ontological gap between image and exemplar and why

exceptions should be made to the principle that “an image must resemble the exemplar

in absolutely all respects”? One answer can be seen in the afore-cited lines from Fut. IV:

210 to the fact that an image is after all a creature which must be different from the

Creator. However, the categories of creator and creature pertain to the religious level

and we are interested here in having an explanation on the metaphysical level. In Ibn

‘Arabi> metaphysical explanation takes into account the doctrine discussed in the

previous chapter271 that a Divine self-manifestation takes place subject to the nature and

271

See the subsection titled “Form-assuming, Illumination and Elitism.

Page 223: 988S

211

limitations of the locus (مجلى). With this doctrine in mind we can read Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

words: “Likewise when the human form accepted the Divine Image in the presence of

Contingency (إمكان) it did not appear upon the property of the Discloser (المتجلي) in all

respects since the presence of the locus of manifestation, that is the contingency, held

sway over it rather than the presence of the Necessary of Existence.” (Ibid. III: 109)

This means that the Divine image, both microcosmic and macrocosmic cannot be

absolutely equal to the Divine Exemplar since it is as it were composed of

characteristics borrowed from both extremes of the totality of Being namely

contingency and necessity. The former is termed “presence of the locus of

manifestation” while the latter as “the Discloser” by Ibn ‘Arabi> in the citation just

made. Referring to the intermediary status of Macro/microcosm between the Higher and

Lower realms one could say that the Divine Image must necessarily manifest

characteristics of both instead of just being absolutely identical to the Higher.

Page 224: 988S

EightEightEightEight

Conclusion: Conclusion: Conclusion: Conclusion: Summary,Summary,Summary,Summary, InterpretationInterpretationInterpretationInterpretation and and and and ImplicationImplicationImplicationImplicationssss

Having presented in the preceding seven chapters a comparative analysis of the

cosmological doctrines of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> in terms of ontology, metacosm,

macrocosm and microcosm we are ready now to bring the dissertation to a close. It is

time therefore, firstly, to put the results of comparison and contrast succinctly and

reiterate remarkable similarities and significant differences and see whether these latter

are reconcilable or not; secondly, to interpret certain points that emerge out of this

summary and thirdly, to tell what the difference or differences our conclusion is

supposed to make and what are its implications. These, therefore, are the tasks we set

before ourselves in this final chapter of our dissertation.

8.18.18.18.1 Summary Summary Summary Summary

Out of Eriugena’s four divisions of nature we presented a comparative analysis of three

divisions with the cosmological thought of Ibn ‘Arabi>, in addition to focusing on the

ontological discussions of the prologue to DDN. We did not touch upon the fourth

division of nature since it concerns eschatology and requires separate treatment. What

follows is a chapter by chapter summary.

8.1.18.1.18.1.18.1.1

A division of totality is central to the cosmologies of both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>.

Whereas both include not-being side by side with being under this division Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

Page 225: 988S

213

division of totality seems to be more comprehensive. This is in view of the fact that the

not-being Ibn ‘Arabi> talks about in the context of totality is not relative not-being but

non-delimited or absolute non-being. Moreover instead of dichotomizing totality into

these two categories like Eriugena, Ibn ‘Arabi> comes up with a “third-thing” which he

identifies at times with the spatio-temporal world and at others with the eternal objects

of Divine knowledge that at any rate are the origin of the world. Anyhow this totality

which consists of being and not-being is coextensive with Eriugena’s universitas which

combines both creator and creature.

There are two more facets of the ontologies of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> where

considerable resonances are discernible. These two facets come to the light when we

focus on Eriugena’s famous modes of distinguishing being from not-being in the light of

Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought. Out of these modes it is the so called sixth mode which has

greatest affinity with the thought of Ibn ‘Arabi>. Thus, as far as this perspective of

differentiating being form not-being is concerned, true being belongs to God while

everything the existence of which depends upon or derives from Divine Being is

properly speaking non-existent. Moreover, according to his third mode things that are

still hidden in the secret folds of nature are considered non-existents while they are

considered to be once they appear in the spatio-temporal world. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

cosmological doctrine contains the scripturally grounded concept of “treasuries” of

things from which they are created and manifested in the spatio-temporal world. But so

long as things are still in those treasuries they are considered not to be. However one

important difference here is that a thing never really escapes the treasuries since Ibn

‘Arabi> identifies them with the objects Divine knowledge from which nothing can

escape. Eriugena’s first mode implied the application of not-being to God in view of His

Page 226: 988S

214

super-abundant excellence and being to the things that do not escape intellect, reason or

sense, thus this mode has an implication that is totally opposed to that of the sixth

mode. This fact instead of being an inconsistency in Eriugenian ontology, is actually one

of the two facets we just spoke of, namely, that differentiating being from not-being for

Eriugena depends upon the perspective from which one is contemplating. That this

perspectival nature of ontology is definitely shared by Ibn ‘Arabi> can be seen firstly

from the fact that he does not consider existence something additional to the existents

themselves and secondly through his differentiating various meanings of the word

“exists” i.e. verbal, mental and external etc. So one thing might exist in one of these

meanings and not exist from another one.

The second facet reflected in Eriugena’s modes of being is the subordination of

ontology to intelligibility or that of “being” to “being known.” This parallels Ibn

‘Arabi>’s very identification of “being” (وجود) with “finding” (وجدان) and also his

interpreting the Qur’a>nic dichotomy of “what you see and what you do not see” as

“what exists and what does not exist.” As far as the former parallelism is concerned,

unlike Eriugena, the point made by Ibn ‘Arabi> is facilitated by a linguistic fact rather

than being a philosophical innovation.

8.1.28.1.28.1.28.1.2

As a Christian Eriugena believes in triune God but as a representative of the negative

theology he declares God to be beyond unity and trinity. Ibn ‘Arabi> in spite of holding a

doctrine of radical unity as a Muslim, is still amenable to comparison with Eriugena in

view of two facts. Firstly, he is one of the few Muslim thinkers who are ready to

accommodate trinity as specific form of declaration of unity. Secondly, on the

Page 227: 988S

215

metaphysical level, Ibn ‘Arabi> does not assign multiplicity to the realm of illusion but

considers it to be rooted in the Divine side in the multiplicity of Divine names.

Instead of limiting the meaning of “God” just to the Divine Essence, both

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> conceive it as multi-layered term denoting in addition to the

Divine Essence its manifestation as well. This is reflected in Eriugena’s express

statement to the effect that theophanies are also to be understood by the word “God”

and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s definition of the Divine Presence which includes Essence, Attributes

and Actions and the these latter are identified with the world. Eriugena’s “primordial

causes” and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s “fixed entities”, if our argument in the fourth chapter regarding

their parallelism are convincing, can be interpreted as philosophical elaborations of this

inclusion of theophanies within Divine nature. Since Ibn ‘Arabi> shares with Eriugena

the identification of “creating” with God’s “manifesting himself” we can reconcile Ibn

‘Arabi>’s thought with otherwise confusing Eriugenian assertion that God creates

Himself. Moreover there is in Ibn ‘Arabi> an application of the notion of Divine self-

creation in the context of explaining diversity of religious beliefs and practices in

accordance with God’s manifesting Himself (“creating Himself”) differently to each

believer.

Eriugena’s equally startling step from theological point of view is the application

of “nihil” to God, however, this notion does not imply “lack of being” but God’s being

“more-than-being.” Since Ibn ‘Arabi> equates God with Being and explicitly rejects

application of “nihil” to God it seems difficult to reconcile him with Eriugena at this

point. However, this difficulty is overcome by understanding that while rejecting that

application Ibn ‘Arabi> has a different understanding of “nihil” in mind so there is no

contradiction between him and Eriugena. It is as “lack” or “privation” that Ibn ‘Arabi>

Page 228: 988S

216

denies application of “nihil” to God. Besides, there is no difference between Eriugena

and Ibn ‘Arabi> as far as the understanding of creation ex nihilo as creation ex deo is

concerned and the latter has pointed at one place to a perspective from which God can

be said not be.

Consequent upon characterizing God as nihil are questions of knowability. As for

God’s being unknowable to us in as much as His Essence and being knowable from

certain features of existents, Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> absolutely agree. They disagree,

however, and this time the disagreement seems to be irresolvable, regarding the

possibility of Divine self-knowledge. Eriugena thinks that since God is not a “what” i.e.

“thing” and since knowing is equal to defining and God cannot be defined, He cannot

know Himself. Although Ibn ‘Arabi> agrees that God cannot be defined he emphasizes

that God’s knowing “what He is” has nothing to do with definition. Unlike Eriugena,

instead of taking infinity to imply impossibility of Divine self knowledge Ibn ‘Arabi>

thinks that it is only as infinite that God can know Himself the infinite and that this

knowledge is without encompassing. As we said here we stumble upon an irresolvable

difference between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. However emphasizing “in nullo” part of

Eriugena’s in nullo se cognoscit quia infinita est we offer a new interpretation according

to which what Eriugena is denying is God’s knowing Himself “in anything” and there is

nothing in which He could know himself except Himself. If this interpretation is

accepted then we can resolve the difference between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> at this

point.

On the plane of the theological side of metacosm, the final important arena of

comparing Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> is that of religious language. Following the Greek

authorities especially Pseudo Dionysius Eriugena first presents two opposite

Page 229: 988S

217

perspectives and then a third one which combines both. According to affirmative

theology everything can be spoken of God since everything takes its being from Him;

according to negative theology none of the Divine names refer to God since they are

opposed by other names and no opposition can be in Him and finally the hyperphatic

theology which is affirmative in form but negative in intent since it ascribes to God

things like “more-than-Goodness” and “more-than Essence” etc., without giving their

precise meaning. In Ibn ‘Arabi> we have obvious parallels of these three modes of talking

about God. He inherited the concepts of tanzi>h and tashbi>h respectively corresponding

to the negative and affirmative theologies but observing that separately taken these two

modes are inadequate, he added the third perspective which combined both i.e. tanzi>h

ma‘ al-tashbi>h. This perspective is epitomized by the Qur’a>nic words “There is nothing

like unto Him and He is the Hearing, the Seeing” as Ibn ‘Arabi> understands them.

However, although both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> synthesize negative and affirmative

theologies the final flavor of their syntheses is different. Whereas Eriugena tilts towards

negative theology in the final analysis the emphasis in Ibn ‘Arabi> seems to be upon the

affirmative side. This is a fact that stands in need of interpretation and we shall reiterate

its interpretation in the following section.

8.1.38.1.38.1.38.1.3

We alluded above to the fact that Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> alike consider the

manifestation already included in the principle. Eriugena’s positing primordial causes as

“the secretes folds of nature” out of which things are brought into spatio temporal world

and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s fixed entities as “treasuries of everything with God” out of which He

brings the things, can be taken as a cosmological commentary on their respective

definitions of God or Divine presence. Thus if Eriugena gives us primordial causes as

Page 230: 988S

218

prototypes, predestinations, predefinitions and origins of things before their arising in

the visible and invisible, Ibn ‘Arabi> introduces fixed entities as determinations of

objects in Divine knowledge before they are existentiated in the spatio-temporal world.

Thus the fixed entities are functionally identical to the primordial causes. As far as the

specific characteristics of these two notions are concerned, Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>

cannot straightforwardly be reconciled on all of them.

It is well known that Ibn ‘Arabi> held that the fixed entities are non-existent and

this position parallels Eriugena’s third mode of being according to which things still in

their primordial causes are said not be. However, Eriugena has also remarked that the

causes are closest to being and this in addition to creating gap between them and fixed

entities also requires being reconciled with his own former position. Our conclusion

answering to both these difficulties involved synthesizing these two conflicting

positions into the statement that primordial causes both are and are not just like

Eriugena himself said about the things that they were always and were not always. What

helps bring this synthesized position on the ontological status of primordial causes close

to that of fixed entities is that it is not absolute non-existence that Ibn ‘Arabi> claims for

them but only relative one and that he identifies the realm of fixed entities with the

third thing which both is and is not.

Unlike Eriugena who refuses to identify primordial causes with prime matter Ibn

‘Arabi> does allow identifying the realm of fixed entities with prime matter in one place,

however, he does that only for the purpose of analogy.

On the questions related to the knowability Ibn ‘Arabi> is in complete accord

with Eriugena in making it clear that like the latter’s primordial causes, the fixed

entities do not escape Divine knowledge, rather their very nature consists in being

Page 231: 988S

219

objects of Divine knowledge. However whereas Eriugena holds that primordial causes

are absolutely inaccessible to human intellect Ibn ‘Arabi> is not so strict regarding the

knowability of his fixed entities and allows that they can be partially known by some

human beings through Divine grace and holds that the workings of human imagination

proceed through a knowledge of those entities. However, this knowledge does not

include the manner of existentiation of fixed entities.

Another important difference between the primordial causes and fixed entities

that needs to be commented on is that the former are said to be “created” while the

latter are “not existentiated” that is, not created. However, in Eriugena “creation”

amounts to “self-disclosure” and not to “making out of non-existence.” Hence the gap

between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> is bridged once we consider that the latter only denies

that fixed entities are made out of non-existence and admits that they are theophanies.

The fixed entities resemble primordial causes in being hierarchically ordered

within a wider hierarchy of totality consisting of God, causes and spatio temporal world

in Eriugena’s case and of Divinity, fixed entities and the world in case of Ibn ‘Arabi>.

Fixed entities share with the primordial causes the characteristic of being intermediary

between Divinity and the world. However Ibn ‘Arabi> believes in two levels of Divinity,

its pure unity and its being subject of multiple names and attributes. This second level

contributes towards making Ibn ‘Arabi>’s hierarchical picture of totality more

transparent than that of Eriugena. Although Eriugena teaches that everything in the

spatio-temporal world that has some specific characteristic (say, life), has it through

participation in a specific primordial cause (life-in-itself) and through it in the Supreme

Life, he does not make it clear how the last category is related to the Divinity. Is it its

attribute, name, theophany, creation or what? In Ibn ‘Arabi> however, one can find a

Page 232: 988S

220

clear answer as to the way Divinity is related through Divine Names and Attributes to

the Fixed entities which then are existentiated into spatio-temporal world. Fixed entities

are the forms of the Divine Names. This also solves the issue of unity versus

multiplicity of primordial causes and fixed entities. If the multiplicity of primordial

causes poses a challenge for Eriugena which he solves by observing that this multiplicity

is not intrinsic to the causes but arises out of their “effects,” Ibn ‘Arabi> is concerned

about showing that the multiplicity of fixed entities does not multiply the Absolute

Being or Divinity but only its “properties.” An important difference here between two

thinkers is that Ibn ‘Arabi> is more welcoming to multiplicity than Eriugena since he

attempts to metaphysically relate it one of the levels of Divinity.

Now whereas in Eriugena’s hierarchy of primordial causes it is Goodness that

takes the pride of priority, Ibn ‘Arabi> assigns this place to Mercy. However, it is worth

noting that the way Eriugena understands Goodness as the highest and foremost

primordial cause is the same as the one in which Ibn ‘Arabi> explicates his notion of

Mercy since both are characterized by “existence-giving.”

Both primordial causes and the fixed entities are infinite. Similar reasons for

their infinity are given by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. It amounts for both of them to the

fact that God is infinite so they should also be so. Likewise both primordial causes and

fixed entities give rise to the problem of justifying evil. Although Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> share the belief that evil is not a positive entity but pertains to non-existence,

their solutions are slightly different. Eriugena admits that evil indirectly results from the

primordial causes they do not thereby become evil just as the sun does not become

blameworthy for the darkness that inevitably results from the shadow of its ray. For Ibn

‘Arabi> God cannot be held responsible for evil since evil is something subjective and

Page 233: 988S

221

relative to particular desires and creation consists in bestowal of existence upon fixed

entities irrelevant of individual likes and dislikes.

However, on one account fixed entities differ from primordial causes. Whereas

according to Eriugena the latter subsist in the Word, in Ibn ‘Arabi> fixed entities and do

not relate in this manner to what might look like a parallel of the Word/Logos namely

Perfect Man. This is so because there is a fixed entity in Divine Knowledge even of the

Perfect Man.

8.1.48.1.48.1.48.1.4

Having compared the views of Eriugena on the nature of divinity and primordial causes

with similar views in Ibn ‘Arabi> we proceeded to investigate the way they relate the

world to God. Both of them hold that the essential nature of the world consists in

symbolizing or signifying God. Eriugena expresses this idea by saying that the world

participates in the Divine and that it is a theophany or appearance of God while Ibn

‘Arabi> expresses this very idea by saying on the one hand that whatever appears in the

spatio-temporal world has a root in the Divine side and on the other that the world is a

tajalli> of God. Our comparative analysis showed that Eriugena’s concept of participation

resembles Divine roots theory in Ibn ‘Arabi> while his theophany is the exact parallel of

al-tajalli>. Both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> introduced their concepts, respectively, of

participation and Divine roots in the context of division of totality. However, whereas

all three members of Eriugena’s totality (God, the primordial causes and the world)

relate to each other in the relation of participation, in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s totality (Essence,

Names and Actions/World) a participation like relation exists only between the last two

members for reasons we explained. According to Eriugena’s understanding of the word

“participation” it does not mean “taking of some part” but “derivation from some higher

Page 234: 988S

222

essence” or “being/having after something else.” Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Divine root doctrine is

parallel to the concept of participation in both senses given to the word by Eriugena.

When Ibn ‘Arabi> says that a particular phenomenon is rooted in the Divine Side he

means nothing but that it is ontologically derived from one of the Divine names or

attributes. Once again, his notion of the “levels” of Divine Presence makes his Divine

roots theory more clear and elaborate than that of Eriugena. Thus we discern countless

instances of relating existent entities to Divine roots in Ibn ‘Arabi>’s writings. This

process of “relating” proceeds in either of two directions, from existents to names and

from names to existents. However, in addition to relating these specific existents to

their Divine roots Ibn ‘Arabi> also relates the ten categories to specific Divine qualities

and attributes. It might seem that on the question of ten categories Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> are taking totally different positions since the former denies that they apply to

God while the latter is trying to find Divine roots for them. In spite of providing Divine

roots for the categories Ibn ‘Arabi> expressly rules out their application to God except of

action and affection since, among other things, God hears our prayers and responds to

them. Thus unless one wants to accuse Ibn ‘Arabi> of flatly contradicting himself, one

has to differentiate between finding Divine roots for the categories and their direct

application to Divine Essence. Saying that “God is time” is different from saying that

“God is in Time.” the former implies that there is something about God which is

responsible for the existence of time in the phenomenal world, not necessarily His

Himself being in time which would be a direct application of the category to God. Of

course Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> remain different in view of the fact that the former does

not make room for any ontological connection between God and categories. The

difference we alluded to above in the final orientation of apophasis-cataphasis synthesis

proposed by these two philosophers explains the present difference. Thus, since

Page 235: 988S

223

Eriugena remains inclined towards negative theology and Ibn ‘Arabi> towards

affirmative, the former refuses to connect the categories to Divine Reality while the

latter is ready to do that. However, one must not neglect the similar non-Aristotelian

way in which both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> conceive ousia, the first category, as a

substrate for all the rest.

8.18.18.18.1....5555

The comparison of participation with Divine roots doctrine has revealed the resonances

between Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> on one side of the question about God-World

relationship, that is from the side of the world. When we look at this relation from

God’s side it is analyzable in terms of the concept of “theophany” to which Ibn ‘Arabi>’s

“al-tajalli >” corresponds. These two concepts which are equally central to the

cosmologies of both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> also deliver same meaning, namely

“manifestation of the Divine.” Both these notions in turn are understandable either

ontologically, i.e. the world is a theophany, or epistemologically, i.e. a mode of knowing

God. However, in Ibn ‘Arabi> this distinction is more clearly discerned than it is in

Eriugena, since the former sometimes gives specific terms to denote two perspectives.

Theophany/tajalli> understood ontologically does not imply collapse of Creature-Creator

boundary and it does not compromise Divine unknowability when understood

epistemologically. Eriugena’s contrasting theophany with knowledge of Divine realities

as they are in themselves and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s principle that there is no tajalli> at the level of

Divine Essence make this point clear.

The way Eriugena understands his notion of theophany is deeply Dionysian and

consequently he elaborates it as form-assuming of the formless, maintains that only the

spiritual elite has access to it and there is an element of illuminationism to it according

Page 236: 988S

224

to which spiritual self-discipline is not sufficient for access to theophany rather God

must will and become manifest. Of these characteristics that of “form-assuming” has its

parallel in Ibn ‘Arabi> identification of tajalli > with “God’s transmutation in forms”

(tah}awwul fi> al-s}uwar) and of the world as “locus of manifestation” (majla>) as a “form”

in which God becomes manifest. Ibn ‘Arabi>’s explication of tajalli> as a mode of knowing

God contains many indications of elitism as it is available to Prophets and saints and not

to people of an exoteric bend of mind. He adds an illuminationist dimension by

describing tajalli> based knowledge as a Divine light bestowed upon some of the chosen

ones.

8.1.68.1.68.1.68.1.6

Coming to the final arena for the comparative analysis of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> we

have to look at the way they envisage Man’s place within the universe and in relation to

his creator. Both present man as Divine image and as containing the whole of universe

within himself. Eriugena relies upon Gregory of Nyssa for elaborating his doctrine of

Divine image. Since Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> share the principle that an image must

resemble its exemplar, they both understand human deiformity to mean that man was

bestowed with the plenitude of all good, while Ibn ‘Arabi> founds on the concept of

human deiformity an ethical system as well. Emphasis upon the Divine names once

again makes Ibn ‘Arabi>’s explication of human deiformity a little more elaborate than

that of Eriugena. Both make it clear that image-exemplar resemblance does not alter the

fact that the image belongs after all to creaturely sphere and on that account there must

be ontological gap between it and its exemplar. On the question whether deiformity

characterizes whole humanity or was it the privilege of primordial perfect man both

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> take ambiguous positions of saying “yes” to both these

Page 237: 988S

225

questions but this ambiguity can be removed by explaining that the deiformity of the

perfect man is actualized and perfect whereas in the rest of humanity it is imperfect and

needs to be realized to its full. In addition to these similarities between Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> there are some differences between their doctrines of Divine image which must

not be ignored. Being honest to the Christian tradition Eriugena ousts human body from

deiformity and limits it to human soul while Ibn ‘Arabi> is exceptionally positive to

human body in line with general positive Islamic attitude to human body and a special

reference to body in the h}adi>th mentioning creation upon Divine image. Unlike Eriugena

who does not want to call man “microcosm” since that would give the impression that

human dignity is based on man’s containing the world in himself while the world is too

low to dignify human being, Ibn ‘Arabi> extends the Divine image to the whole world,

thus in him we find a macrocosmic deiformity in addition to human deiformity.

Man’s relation to the created nature is explained in terms of containment theory

and the final Eriugenian position on the precise meaning of this concept is, in our

opinion, that everything is created in man in substance however by this he simply means

that in human mind there are notions of everything and he identifies “notions” with

“substance.” On the other hand in view of his concept of cosmic deiformity, Ibn ‘Arabi>

does not hesitate from calling man “small world” and labelling the world as the “great

man.” He explains his version of containment doctrine by referring to his view that

human configuration is the most all-encompassing of all since God taught Adam the

Names all of them, which implies that microcosmic status of man as the created nature

is nothing but manifestation of Divine Names according to Ibn ‘Arabi>. In view of this

all-encompassing status man is an intermediary not only between material and spiritual

Page 238: 988S

226

creatures, as he is seen to be by Eriugena, but he brings together in himself creaturely

qualities as well as Divine qualities.

Thus, except for their divergence on human body’s participation in deiformity,

Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>’s view regarding the relation of man to God and to nature

present remarkable similarities.

8.28.28.28.2 InterpretationInterpretationInterpretationInterpretation

A number of important questions were raised in connection with interpretation or

explanation of certain characteristics of the cosmological doctrines of Eriugena and Ibn

‘Arabi> or differences between them and we attempted to respond to them. Here we are

recapitulating with bit more elaboration three of these.

8.2.18.2.18.2.18.2.1

Dermot Moran and many other Eriugena scholars see in Eriugena a precursor of German

idealists. In our opinion this view oversimplifies Eriugena’s complex positions and

neglects certain important indications of realism in his thought. Likewise Ibn ‘Arabi> has

been classified as a firm empiricist by Mastaka Takeshita. We submit that due to an

important methodological feature they share, these thinkers defy classification into

pigeon holes of the “isms” of modern and post-modern philosophy.

We do not consider the fact that Eriugena subdues ontology to epistemology

enough to make possible his characterization as an Idealist in the sense attached to this

word by Post-Cartesian (modern) western philosophy. First of all the very possibility of

there being an idealism in pre-modern philosophy is controversial and at least,

anachronistic. Secondly, ironically in Eriugena literature one finds scholars declaring

Eriugena to be and not to be an idealist on account of his holding to one and the same

Page 239: 988S

227

notion. Thirdly and most importantly, such characterization neglects certain important

textual evidences from Eriugena where he appears to be implying realism instead of

idealism, for instance, his statement that things which do not have being cannot be

understood. At one place he subdues knowability to existence and at another place gives

an objective explanation for starting the enumeration of primordial causes from

goodness. The fact is that the thought of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>, and for that matter of

many other great pre-modern philosophers and metaphysicians, cannot be justifiably

encapsulated in well defined and mutually exclusive schools that typify modern

philosophy.

8.2.28.2.28.2.28.2.2

One further point where our reading of Eriugena differed from that of Moran was his

claim that the modes of being mentioned in the prologue to DDN are not central to this

work. Contrary to this claim we attempted to show that at various points in the main

body of DDN applications of one or other of those modes of being. We found that

Eriugena’s doctrine of Divine nothingness and ontological status of the primordial

causes can be seen to result from an unfolding, respectively of the first and third mode

of demarcating being from not-being.

8.2.38.2.38.2.38.2.3

It was observed that although both Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> synthesize negative and

affirmative theologies synthesis presented by the former remains negative in the final

analysis while that of the latter tilts towards affirmation. Using Frithjof Schuon’s

typology of religions we explained this difference by referring to the fact that Eriugena,

following the Greek authorities, was re-acting to a tradition that belonged to “God-

become-man” type while Ibn ‘Arabi> had to counterbalance a tradition that contained an

Page 240: 988S

228

emphasis upon “God as such.” In case of Eriugena, our interpretation implied a

disagreement with Willemien Otten who suggests that Eriugena’s concept of theophany

counterbalances his negative theology. If one agrees with Otten’s view then the

difference between orientation of syntheses presented by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> would

disappear.

8.2.48.2.48.2.48.2.4

What are we to make of the remarkable similarities between the work of Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi>, writers belonging to different times, places and religious backgrounds?

Presumably, the most expected response to the results of our comparative analysis

would consist in uttering that those similarities owe themselves to a shared

philosophical heritage, Neo-Platonism! Though Eriugena’s connection with Neo-

Platonic heritage is incontestable in view of his translations of Maximus the Confessor,

Pseudo Dionysius and other Greek fathers, connections between Ibn ‘Arabi>> and Greek

philosophical heritage are not that transparent and all such judgments are based simply

on the the argument from similarities of terminology to borrowing without establishing

historical connections and discarding a number of important differences between Ibn

‘Arabi> and Plato/Plotinus. Thirdly, Unlike the Muslim Peripetetic philosophers who

were not really interested in grounding the philosophical ideas they were transmitting

into their own tradition, whatever external influences Ibn ‘Arabi> might have accepted,

he was never a passive recipient of foreign doctrines and their transmitter to the coming

generations. Thus we always find him referring to some of the Qur’a>nic verses to ground

his philosophical doctrines and notions. This point can be brought home by borrowing

an image from Ibn ‘Arabi> himself. He gave us the principle that the nature of receptacle

(locus of manifestation) colors the nature of theophany. This cosmological principle can

Page 241: 988S

229

be transplanted to the plane of intellectual interaction between different human

societies. It provides us an excellent model for positively interacting with intellectual

environment while remaining grounding in our own Scripture. However, this does not

mean that every philosophical idea can be legitimized through artificially reading it into

our scripture. We notice that Ibn ‘Arabi>’s interpretations in most of the cases are neither

allegorical nor arbitrary but are within the genuine interpretational space allowed or in

some cases even dictated by the literal meaning of the texts. This is not the case with

Eriugena and this can be seen, for instance, in the way Eriugena grounds his “primordial

causes in the Bible and the way Ibn ‘Arabi> grounds his notion of “fixed entities” in the

Qur’a>n. Whereas the former simply identifies dogmatically and arbitrarily his primordial

causes with “waste and void” mentioned in the Genesis, the latter puts forward his

notion as development of an implication of the Qur’a>nic verse about the treasuries of

everything with God out of which they are brought.

8.38.38.38.3 ImplicationsImplicationsImplicationsImplications

Why should someone living in today’s world care about the teachings of Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> and the common ground shared by them? Is there anything of relevance to

the situation we are living that we can learn from them? Let us see if we could find a

worthy answer in the conclusions that we drew from our comparative analysis.

8.3.18.3.18.3.18.3.1 Yes and No:Yes and No:Yes and No:Yes and No: A Cosmology of ToleranceA Cosmology of ToleranceA Cosmology of ToleranceA Cosmology of Tolerance272

Ibn ‘Arabi> relates (See Fut. I: 153-4) his encounter with the great Muslim philosopher

Ibn Rushd (Averroes, d. 1198) when he was just a young boy. The philosopher had

272 “Tolerance or intolerance,” to quote Nasr, “are not only moral issues but have a cosmic dimension.” S.

H. Nasr, “Metaphysical Roots of Tolerance and Intolerance: An Islamic Interpretation,” in Philosophy,

Religion and the Question of Intolerance, ed. Mahdi Amin Razavi and David Ambuel (Albany: SUNY,

1997)

Page 242: 988S

230

already heard of the young mystic and showed great respect towards him. When asked

by Ibn Rushd what kind of solution he had found through illumination and Divine

inspiration and whether that was same as what philosophers receive through speculative

thought, Ibn ‘Arabi> replied, “Yes and no!” In our opinion this combination of negation

and affirmation is the characteristic answer Ibn ‘Arabi> gives to most of the important

questions he treats in his writings. In addition to his combination of similarity and

incomparability, unity and multiplicity, bodily senses and Divine inspiration, this

characteristic of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s thought lurks behind the emphasis he attaches to the

concept of barzakh (intermediary). He is always positing intermediaries between

extremities: the third thing a barzakh between being and not-being, Divine Names

barzakh between Divine Essence and the World, Man as barzakh between God and the

world, imagination a barzakh between bodily senses and the intellect, so on and so forth.

Eriugena also does not give straightforward yes or no answers to most of his central

questions. Thus he tells us, for example, that the primordial causes both flow into their

effects and do not flow into them, that things always were and always were not and that

God is both found and is not found in His theophanies. This, in our opinion is the

greatest methodological insight that we are afforded by Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>. In the

light of latter’s picture of totality it is God as absolute Being that deserves an absolute

“yes” and Absolute non-existence that being absolute evil deserves absolute “no” while

everything in our world lies in between these two poles and consequently is combination

of goodness and imperfection and the only proper response to it is nothing but “yes and

no.”

No arguments need be mustered in order to show what our world is going

through due to prevalence of the “logic of the sword” which slices the world into black

and white and makes certain people declare “either with us or against us” and the

Page 243: 988S

231

millions of people suffer from this tabloid thinking. Hence the greatest practical lesson

to be learnt from Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> is that reality does not consist of pure black

and pure white. It is not only that there is a grey area between the two but something

black lies at the heart of white and something white lies at the heart of the black, as the

Far Eastern symbol of yin and yang marvelously represents. Hence both Eriugena and

Ibn ‘Arabi> teach us to discern a grain of goodness in every single existent, whatever be

its nature. Indeed Ibn ‘Arabi> goes to the extent of finding some value even in absolute

not-being. Likewise for Eriugena Divine gifts and graces flow to all orders of reality

even to the lowest of them.

8.3.28.3.28.3.28.3.2 Green Cosmologies: Green Cosmologies: Green Cosmologies: Green Cosmologies: Restoring Restoring Restoring Restoring Harmony between God, Man and Harmony between God, Man and Harmony between God, Man and Harmony between God, Man and

NatureNatureNatureNature

Amongst the problems our world is facing today there is one which is the most urgent.

This urgency arises from the fact that this problem concerns the very existence of this

world, as has been marvelously shown by former US Vice President Al-Gore’s

documentary An Inconvenient Truth. A few decades have passed since we first realized

this problem. Since that moment many voices have been raised and many attempts to

analyze the causes and suggest solutions have been made. As has been argued in

numerous studies the real nature of the crisis we are facing, and the worst part of which

is to come is intellectual and the first step of solution is therefore intellectual. As Nasr

has argued, the environmental crisis has much deeper causes than mere mishandling of

technology. 273 Modernity detached the world from God and consequently made man the

sole master of the universe whose mandate it was to exploit his slave to the utmost. As

Nasr has put it “The earth is bleeding from wounds inflicted upon it by a humanity no

273

Man and Nature (London: Harper Collins, 1989)

Page 244: 988S

232

longer in harmony with Heaven and therefore in constant strife with the terrestrial

environment.”274 We will have to reassert the proper harmony between God, man and

Nature. Fortunately we do not have to start from ground zero since the traditional

worldview, of all great religions of the world, affords us many keys.

The comparative analysis of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> gave us three keys for

rediscovering a worldview based on harmony between God, man and nature: first, the

world as theophany, second, man as image of God and third, man as containing the

whole world within himself. These three concepts are pillars for establishing the edifice

of a theo-anthropo-cosmic vision. The first key opens the door to “resacralization” of

our desacralized world, the second relates man to God and the third harmonizes him to

the rest of nature in a manner in which harming nature becomes harming oneself, a

suicide! According to Deirdre Carabine Eriugena’s more holistic and perspectival

approach to the whole of created reality which perceives all things as bound together in

an ineffable harmony can be understood to imply the sanctification of all created

things.275 Dierdre Carabine has expressed her belief that Eriugena’s thought could be

appealing today as a further source for a sound Christian environmental ethic.276

Although we agree with Carabine on this point we would like to argue that if Eriugena

can be a foundation for a sound environmental ethic in spite of the fact that he does not

like to apply the title “microcosm” to man since the world is unworthy to become a

cause of dignity for man and that he refuses to extend the imago dei status to human

bodies, then an even more sound environmental ethic can be based on the thought of Ibn

‘Arabi> who not only does not hesitate from calling man a microcosm and extends imago

274

Religion and the Order of Nature, 3. 275 See Dierdre Carabine, John Scottus Eriugena, 109. 276 Ibid. 55.

Page 245: 988S

233

dei to human body but goes to the extent of declaring that the whole cosmos is made

upon Divine image and deserves from man same respect that his parents deserve from

him.

In view of these practical implications we can confidently assert that the

comparison of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi> we conducted is not mere “exercise in dialectic”

but affords us the key elements of restoring the harmony of God, man and nature, a

restoration that many people now see as the only way to cope with the difficult time our

world is going through.

Page 246: 988S

Works CitedWorks CitedWorks CitedWorks Cited

IIII----WWWWorkorkorkorks of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>s of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>s of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>s of Eriugena and Ibn ‘Arabi>

Eriugenae, I. S. (1968) Periphyseon (De diuisione naturae), The Dublin Institute for

Advanced Studies, Dublin.

------------. (1972) Periphyseon (De Diuisione Naturae), The Dublin Institute for

Advanced Studies, Dublin.

------------. (1981) Periphyseon (De Diuisione Naturae), The Dublin Institute for

Advanced Studies, Dublin.

------------. (1987) Periphyseon, trans. I.P. Sheldon Williams, Dumbarton Oaks,

Washington.

------------. (1988) Homily of John the Scot, the translator of the Hierarchy of Dionysius,

trans. O’Meara J., in Eriugena, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 158-176.

------------. (1998) Treatise on Predestination, trans., Mary Brennan, Notre Dame: ND

University Press.

Ibn ‘Arabi>. Muh{yiddi>n. (n.d.) Al-Futu>h}at al Makkiyah, Da>r S}a>dir, Beirut.

------------. (1980) Fus}u>s al-H}ikam, Da>r al-Kita>b al-‘Aabi>, Beirut.

------------. (1994) Kita>b al-‘Aba>dilah, Maktabat al-Qa>hirah, Cairo.

------------. (1999) Rasa>il, Da>r Ih}ya>’ al-Tura>th, Beirut.

------------. (2003) Al-Tadbi>ra>t al-ila>hiyyah fi> Is}la>h} al-Mamlakah al-Insa>niyyah, Da>r al-

Kutub al-‘Ilmiyyah, Beirut.

------------. (2005) Insha>’ al-Dawa>’ir, Da>r al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyah, Beirut. [Eng. Trans.:

Fenton, P. and M. Gloton, (1993) “The Book of the Description of Encompassing

Circles,” in Hirtenstein S. and Tiernen M., Eds., Muh}yiddi>n ibn ‘Arabi>: A

Commemorative Volume, Element Books, Shaftsbury, 24-40.

Page 247: 988S

235

------------. (2003) Awra>d al-Ayya>m wa al-Laya>li>, Da>r al-Fath}, Oman. [Eng. Trans.:

Beneito P. and Hirtenstein S. (2008) The Seven Days of the Heart, Anqa Publishers,

Oxford.]

IIIIIIII----Works of other WritersWorks of other WritersWorks of other WritersWorks of other Writers

‘Affi>fi>, Abu>’l-‘ala>’. (1969) “Ibn ‘Arabi> fi> Dira>sa>ti>,”> in Al-Kita>b al-tidhka>ri> li Muh}yiddi>n

Ibn ‘Arabi>, Da>r al-Ka>tib al-‘Arabi>, Cairo, 3-35.

Amooli>, H}asan Za>deh. (1378 A.H) Mumidd al-Himam, Waza>rat e Farhang e Isla>mi,

Tehran.

Aristotle. (1952) The Works of Aristotle: Categories, Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc.,

Chicago.

Augustine, Saint. (1890) The City of God and the Christian Doctrine, ed., Phillip Schaff,

The Christian Literature Publishing Co., New York.

Augustine, Saint. (1982)The Literal Meaning of Genesis, Paulist Press, Mahwah.

Ba>li> Za>deh, Mus}t}afa>. (2002)Sharh} Fus}u>s} al-H}ikam, Da>r al-Kutub al-‘Ilmiyyah, Beirut.

Beierwaltes, W. (1973) “The Revaluation of John Scottus Eriugena in German

Idealism,” in Dominic J. O’Meara, ed., The Mind of Eriugena: Papers of a Dublin

Colloquium, 14-18 July 1970, Irish University Press, Dublin, 190-198.

------------. (1994) “Unity and Trinity in Dionysius and Eriugena,” in Hermathena:

Proceedings of the Dublin Conference on Neoplatonism, 1992, University of Dublin,

Dublin.

BÞwering, G. (1994) “Ibn al-‘Arabi>’s concept of Time,” in Gott ist Schon und Er liebt

die Schonheit: Fetschrift Annemarie Schimmel, eds. A Giese and J.C. Burgel Lang

Verlag, Zurich, 71-91.

Brennan, M. (1977) “A Bibliography of Publications in the Field of Eriugena Studies

1800-1975”, Studi Medievali, 28282828 401-447.

Burkhardt, T. (2001) Mirrors of the Intellect: Essays on Traditional Science and Sacred

Art, Suhail Academy, Lahore.

Page 248: 988S

236

Burnyeat, M. (1982) “Idealism in Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley

Missed,” in Idealism: Past and Present, ed. G. Vassey, Cambridge University Press,

Cambridge, 19-50.

Carabine, D. (1995) The Unknown God: Negative Theology in the Platonic Tradition:

Plato to Eriugena, Eerdmans, Louvain.

------------. (2000) John Scottus Eriugena, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Chittick, W. C. (1982) “The Five Divine Presences: From al-Qu>nawi> to al-Qays}ari>” in

The Muslim World, 72727272 107-128.

------------. (1994) Imaginal Worlds: Ibn al-‘Arabi> and the Problem of Religious

Diversity, State University of New York Press, New York.

------------. (2000) The Self-Disclosure of God: Principles of Ibn al-Arabi's Cosmology,

Suhail Academy, Lahore.

------------. (2000) The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn al-'Arab+'s Metaphysics, Suhail

Academy, Lahore.

Coates, P. (2002) Ibn ‘Arabi> and Modern Thought: The History of Taking Metaphysics

Seriously, Anqa Publishing, Oxford.

Copleston, F. (1950) A History of Philosophy, Paulist Press, New Jersey.

Duclow, D. F. (1977) "Divine Nothingness and Self-Creation in John Scotus Eriugena",

Journal of Religion.

Duddy, T. (2002) A History of Irish Thought, Taylor and Francis, New York.

Dupré, A. (1982) “Muh}yiddi>n Ibn ‘Arabi> and St. Albertus Magnus of Cologne,” in

JMIAS, 1111 12-26.

Elmore, G. (2001) “Four Texts of Ibn al-‘Arabi> on the Creative Self manifestation of the

Divine Names,” in JMIAS, 29292929 1-39.

Farka>wi>, Mah}mu>d. (1953) Sharh} Mana>zil al-Sa>’iri>n, Ma‘had al-‘ilmi> al-faransi> li al-a>tha>r

al-Sharqiyyah, Cairo.

Ghaza>li>, Abu> Ha>mid. (1964) Mishka>t al-Anwa>r, Ed. Abul ‘Ala>’ al-‘Afi>fi>, Al-Da>r al-

Qayyu>miyyah, Cairo.

Page 249: 988S

237

Gracia, G. J. E. (1978) “Ontological Characterization of the Relation between Man and

Created Nature in Eriugena,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 16161616 (2) 155-166.

Gregory of Nyssa: Dogmatic Treatises etc.: On the Making of Man (De hominis

Opificio) at: www.ccel.org

Gilson, E. (1965) The Unity of Philosophical Experience, Charles Scribner and Sons,

New York.

Guenon, R. (1945) Introduction to the Study of Hindu Doctrine, Luzac & Co., London.

Hakim, S. (1981) Al-Mu‘jam al-Sufi, Dandarah, Beirut.

Helm, P. (1988) Eternal God: A Study of God without Time, Oxford University Press,

Oxford.

Ibn Khaldu>n, Abdurrah}man. (1986) The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History, trans.

Franz Rosenthal, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

Iqbal, Muh}ammad. (1986) Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam, Ed. M. Saeed

Sheikh, Institute of Islamic Culture, Lahore.

Isfaha>ni, Ra>ghib. (1961) Al-Mufrada>t fi> Ghari>b al-Qur’a>n, As}ah}h} al-Mat}a>bi‘, Karachi.

Izutsu, T. (1997) Sufism and Taoism: A Comparison of Key Philosophical Concepts,

University of California Press, Berkeley.

Kalin, I. (2007) “From the Temporal Time to the Eternal Now: Ibn al-‘Arabi> and Mulla

Sadra> on Time” in JMIAS, 41414141 31-63.

Kazemi, Reza Shah. (2006) Paths to Transcendence: According to Shankara, Ibn ‘Arabi>

and Meister Eckhart, World Wisdom Books, Bloomington.

Marenbon. J. (1980) ‘‘John Scottus and the Categoriae Decem” in Beierwaltes, W. (ed.),

Eriugena: Studien zu seinen Quellen, Carl Winter Universitäts Verlag, Berlin, 116-34.

------------. (1983) Early Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

McCue, E. C. (1933) Theophany: A Study of the Nature of God and His Manifestations

from the works of Joannes Scotus Eriugena, Ninth Century Irish Philosopher-313. PhD

Thesis. Saint Louis University.

Page 250: 988S

238

McEvoy, J. J., Riel, G. v. and Steel, C. (eds.) (1996) Iohannes Scottus Eriugena: The

Bible and Hermeneutics, Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, Leuven: Leuven University

Press.

McGinn, B. J. (1975) “Negative Theology in John the Scot,” in Studia Patristica: Papers

Presented to the Sixth International Conference on Patristic Studies, 13131313 232-238....

Moran, D. (1979) “Natura, Quadriformata and the beginnings of the Physiologia in the

Philosophy of Johannes Scottus Eriugena,” in Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale, 21212121

41-46.

------------. (2002) “Time and Eternity in the Periphyseon,” in History and Eschatology

in John Scottus Eriugena and his Time, ed. James McEvoy and Michael Dunne,

University Press, Leuven, Leuven, 487-507.

------------. (1989) The Philosophy of John Scottus Eriugena: A Study of Idealism in the

Middle Ages, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Murata, S. (1992)The Tao of Islam: A Sourcebook on Gender relations in Islamic

Thought, SUNY, New York.

Nasafi>, ‘Abdulla>h b. Ah}mad. (2005) Mada>rik al- Tanzi>l, Da>r al-Nafa>’is, Beirut.

Nasr, S. H. (1972) “Conditions for Meaningful Comparative Philosophy,” in Philosophy

East and West, 12121212 57-58.

------------. (2004) Religion and the Order of Nature, Lahore, Suhail Academy.

------------. (1989) Knowledge and the Sacred, SUNY, Albany, N.Y.

------------. (1989) Man and Nature, Harper Collins, London.

------------. (1997) “Metaphysical Roots of Tolerance and Intolerance: An Islamic

Interpretation,” in Philosophy, Religion and the Question of Intolerance, ed. Mahdi

Amin Razavi and David Ambuel, SUNY, Albany.

Notcutt, M. (1985) “Ibn ‘Arabi: A Handlist of Printed Materials: Part II,” in JMIAS, 4444

65-74.

O’Meara, D. J. (1981) “The Concept of Nature in John Scotus Eriugena", Vivarium, 19191919

(2) 126-145.

Page 251: 988S

239

Otten, W. (1990) “The Interplay of Nature and Man in the Periphysion of John Scottus

Eriugena,” Vivarium, 22228888 (1) 1-16.

------------. (1991) The Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena, E J Brill, Leiden.

Patton, Kimberley C. and Ray, B. C. (Eds.) (2000) A Majic Still Dwells: Comparative

Religion in the Post-modern Age, University of California Press, Berkeley.

Popper, K. (1950) The Open Society and Its Enemies, Princeton University Press, New

Jersey.

Pseudo-Dionysius, (1987) The Complete Works, Paulist Press, Mahwah.

Schuon, F. (1959) Gnosis Divine Wisdom, John Murray, London.

------------. (1965) Light on the Ancient Worlds, Perennial Books, London.

------------. (1984) Islam and the Perennial Philosophy, Suhail Academy, Lahore.

------------. (1986) Survey of Metaphysics and Esoterism, Bloomington, World Wisdom

Books, Indiana.

------------. (1990) To Have a Centre, World Wisdom Books, Bloomington.

------------. (1992) Echoes of Perennial, Wisdom, World Wisdom Books, Bloomington.

------------. (1999) Understanding Islam, Suhail Academy, Lahore.

------------. (2001) Stations of Wisdom, Suhail Academy, Lahore.

------------. (2005) Esoterism as Principle and As Way, Suhail Academy, Lahore.

------------. (2005) Form and Substance in the Religions , Third Eye, New Delhi.

Schindler, D. C. (2005) “What’s the difference? On the Metaphysics of participation in

a Christian Context,” in Saint Anselm Journal, 3333 1-27.

Sells, M. (1994) The Mystical Languages of Unsaying, University of Chicago Press,

Chicago.

Shahrista>ni>, Abd al-Kari>m. (1975) Al-Milal wa al-Niùal, Da>r al-Ma‘rifah, Beirut.

Smirnov, A. V. (1993) “Nicholas of Cusa and Ibn ‘Arabi>: Two Philosophies of

Mysticism”, Philosophy East and West, 43434343 (1)65.

Page 252: 988S

240

Stock, B. (1967) “The Philosophical Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena,”in

Studi Medievali, ser. 3a 8, 1-57.

Takeshita, M. (1982) “An Analysis of Ibn ‘Arabi>’s Insha>’ al-dawa>’ir with Particular

Reference to the Doctrine of the ‘Third Entity’,” in Journal of Near Eastern Studies, 41,

243-260.

Tillich, P. (1964)Theology of Culture, Oxford University Press, New York.

Van Reel G. (1996) “A Bibliographical Survey of Eriugenian Studies 1987-1995,” in

Iohannes Scottus Eriugena: the Bible and Hermeneutics, Leuven University Press,

Leuven, 367-400.

Wolfson, H. A. (1976) The Philosophy of Kalam, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.